Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 7
Lovers of Sophia Page 7

by Jason Reza Jorjani

letter now at once many times and burn it.44

  So it seems that no forthright and literal expression of Plato’s true

  doctrine is to be found in the corpus of his writings that has been

  handed down to us. Instead, we are left to search the dialogues for

  traces of it. This is why the speaker is always Socrates or some other straw man, and Plato does not so much as even mention his own

  name in these texts – except on two very significant occasions. The first is Socrates’ defense of his way of life when he stands trial and is ultimately sentenced to death in the Apology. The second is his discourse on the immortality of the soul as he awaits death in the

  Phaedo, and it is to this that I will now turn, as if following traces of blood that lead to the scene of Plato’s unfilial crime against the Being of “father Parmenides”.

  The only way that Plato could in some way preserve the aloof

  utter ineffability of the ideal realm of Parmenides’ One, once he has

  allowed the forms and matter to touch in the receptacle and without

  making any concessions to Becoming, is to defer the experience of

  perfection – devoid of all physicality – to a place and time beyond

  death. In the Phaedo, Socrates argues that leading a life of using one’s inner and inherent reason one stays a longer and longer time

  in the realm of ultimate reality between the deaths and rebirths of a

  purifying process of reincarnation. This results in “recollection”, the phenomenon in which people look at an imperfect circle, a shadow

  or semblance in the physical world, and somehow knows that it is imperfect, implying they know of a perfect circle though they have never seen one. Through this process one comes closer and closer

  to leading the perfect philosophic life each time one is reborn until

  final y, one evolves to the point where upon death one’s soul is freed from substance (the body, senses and phenomenal world) altogether to directly experience the ultimate reality of eternal forms. While living one should try to assimilate this ideal immaterial state as

  much as possible, by withdrawing within oneself and using the mind

  to transcend the body.

  44 Ibid.,

  Second Letter: 314 a-c.

  54

  jason reza jorjani

  In the Phaedo, which stands within Plato’s corpus as the

  crucifixion stands within the New Testament, Plato writes:

  Surely the soul can reason best when it is free of all distractions

  such as hearing or sight or pain or pleasure of any kind – that is,

  when it leaves the body to its own devices, becomes as isolated as

  possible, and strives for reality while avoiding as much physical

  contact and association as it can...

  Don’t you think that the person who is most likely to achieve

  [knowledge] flawlessly is the one who approaches each object, as

  far as possible, with the unaided intel ect, without taking account of any sense of sight in his thinking, or dragging any other sense into his reckoning – the man who pursues the truth by applying his

  pure and unadulterated thought to the pure and unadulterated

  object, cutting himself off as much as possible from his eyes

  and ears and virtual y all the rest of his body, as an impediment

  which, if present, prevents the soul from attaining to the truth

  and clear thinking? Is not this the person... who will reach the

  goal of reality, if anybody can?45

  In the drama of the Phaedo, Plato’s Socrates welcomes his death because he claims to believe it is only in an ideal realm free of the

  mortal coil that true knowledge is possible:

  If no pure knowledge is possible in the company of the body,

  then either it is total y impossible to acquire knowledge, or it is

  only possible after death, because it is only then that the soul will

  be isolated and independent of the body.

  ...he will never attain to wisdom worthy of the name elsewhere

  than in the next world...46

  Yet at the outset of the dialogue, when Phaedo is recounting all of

  those who were present at the execution he says the following:

  45 Ibid.,

  Phaedo: 65c–66a

  46 Ibid., 67a; 68b

  55

  lovers of sophia

  Echecrates: Who were actual y there, Phaedo?

  Phaedo: Why, of the Athenians there were this man Apollodorus,

  and Critobulus and his father, and then there were Hermogenes

  and Epigenes and Aeschines and Antisthenes. Oh yes, and

  Ctesipus of Paeanis, and Menexenus, and some other local

  people. I believe that Plato was il .47

  “...I believe that Plato was il .” It is likely that no author has ever written, nor ever will write, with such outstanding wit and such

  masterful y subtle irony. Unless Plato was on his own deathbed,

  nothing would have stopped him from attending the execution

  of his teacher, the teacher of whom he was the brightest and most

  beloved disciple. Nor is Plato merely saying this to write himself

  out of a scene that he is expected to have been present at in order

  to preserve his distance from his dialogues. Except for the case

  in the Apology, where establishing his presence is key to lending credibility to his ‘transcript’ of the trial proceedings that led up to the death sentence, Plato never mentions his presence or absence

  in any of Socrates’ conversations. He allows it to be tacitly assumed

  that he was there while at the same time excusing himself from

  being responsible for giving a literal account. Yet here he goes to the extent of naming all those who were present and explicitly excluding

  himself. Oh and by the way “...I believe that Plato was il .” What an

  outrageously nonchalant and matter-of-fact tone! Plato is bending

  over backwards to get us to read those preposterous words over and

  over again, because he knows that we know damn well that he was

  there. Those words must mean something else – they must constitute some tremendous hint. I believe that Plato means to say that he was nauseated.

  Why? Because here is Socrates, Plato’s beloved teacher, on

  the verge of a tragical y unjust death and he is surrounded by his

  disciples as if by frightened children. Cebes himself says to Socrates:

  “Probably even in us there is a little boy who has these childish

  terrors. Try to persuade him not to be afraid of death as though it

  47 Ibid.

  56

  jason reza jorjani

  were a bogey.”48 Like a father who must force a smile and cheer up

  in the face of adversity so as to al ay the fear of his children, Socrates tel s his disciples:

  If I did not expect to enter the company, first, of other wise

  and good gods, and secondly of men now dead who are better

  than those who are in this world now, it is true that it would be

  unjust for me not to grieve at death. As it is, you can be assured that I expect to find myself among good men; while I would not

  particularly insist on this, I assure you that I could commit myself upon [this] point if I could upon anything...49

  ...This makes Plato sick. Whereas Socrates clearly states that if pure intellection in the absence of embodiment and sensory mediation

  is not possible after death then rational knowledge is not possible at al , here he is contradictorily describing the state after death as one experienced by means of what the Greeks called a soma pneumatikon

  or spectral body – which is a ‘sensory’ medium of experience even if

  not a material on
e. Very tangible agonies and mundane pleasures are

  experienced by means of it, so that pure intellection appears elusive

  even after death and before rebirth. In the Republic Plato elaborates on this view, which he inherited from the esoteric Pythagorean

  Order of which he was a member. Although Plato’s belief in

  reincarnation is set forth in several other texts as wel , it is in the story of Er the son of Armenius from 614b–621d of the Republic that we are presented with his most extensive treatment of the subject. In

  fact, its importance cannot be overemphasized since Plato chooses

  to bring the entire text of the Republic to its culmination and closure with this very tale.

  Er is a soldier to whom it is given to have a Near Death Experience,

  with total recal , so that he may inform the living of what transpires after death. He bears witness to the process that finds its eastern

  analogue in the bardo state described most famously in the Tibetan 48 Ibid., 77e.

  49 Ibid., 63c, my emphasis.

  57

  lovers of sophia

  Book of the Dead.50 As in the eastern version, there are heavenly realms where souls enjoy extraordinarily pleasant experiences and

  hellish underworld realms where they are subjected to all manner

  of terrifying visions and torturous trials, but neither of these states is permanent. The souls of the deceased ultimately choose their

  next lives, and whether these are honorable and rewarding lives or

  whether they are miserable and violent ones is determined on the

  basis of how consciously and deliberatively they are able to make

  their choice.

  It sometimes happens that those who have spent a long time in

  the heaven realms on account of having lived a good previous life

  become complacent and unconsciously choose a terrible subsequent

  life. They fail to look deeply enough into a vision of it so as to see beyond the thril s that shimmer on its surface. Sometimes those

  who have just come from tribulations in the hellish underworld

  have had the awareness to choose more soberly beaten into them.

  The extent to which a soul’s awareness has been cultivated correlates

  to how much of its previous lives will be forgotten and how much

  it will be able to instructively remember so as not to repeat prior

  mistakes. Each must drink a measure from the river Lethe while in the netherworld, but those who are undisciplined find it sweet

  and gulp down a great deal more. In other words, the cycle of

  experiences that progressively purifies the soul until it becomes that of a philosopher is a very long one, and there may be many regresses

  where what appear to be good men suffer a great fal , perhaps even

  to the level of being reborn as an animal, and have to work their way

  up again. So, while Socrates might be somewhat confident that he

  will fare well after drinking the hemlock, the reassurances that he

  gives to his fearful disciples in Phaedo are most certainly soothing lies. Consider the implications of this realization given that Socrates seals this consolation with the claim that he is as sure of it as he is or ever was of anything. The full import of these words will be drawn

  out only as I conclude this essay.

  50 W.Y. Evans-Wentz, The Tibetan Book of the Dead (New York: Oxford University Press, 1960).

  58

  jason reza jorjani

  Final y, it is worth noting that Plato’s views on the equality of

  women to men may be bound up with the fact that, as Er recounts,

  not only can women choose rebirth as men but the souls of eminent

  men sometimes reincarnate as women. This would, in fact, have to

  be the case for there to be female philosophers, since the philosophic soul is the most perfected and it could have freely chosen its sex.

  The soul still has a sex and indeed may have hellish or heavenly

  sexual experiences by means of the soma pneumatikon, both in the state between lives and even once it is perfected and chooses the life of a philosopher whose highest calling is to serve as a republican

  Guardian. This further emphasizes how profoundly Plato’s whole

  afterlife scheme undermines the idea of the kind of enduring

  airtight intellectual isolation from sensory experience that Socrates

  claims would be required to definitively demonstrate the possibility

  of perfectly rational knowledge.

  The tale of Er is not the only part of Republic that undermines this core tenant of exoteric academic Platonism. The following passages

  of the Republic 51 on the idea of the Good – the form of forms – are also relevant, so much so that they deserve to be quoted at length;

  they are perhaps the key to unlocking Plato’s unwritten doctrine:

  The good, then, is the end of all endeavor, the object on which

  every heart is set, whose existence it divines, though it finds it

  difficult to grasp just what it is...

  ‘We shall be quite satisfied if you give an account of the good

  similar to that you gave of justice and self-control and the rest.’

  ‘And so shall I too, my dear chap,’ I replied, ‘but I’m afraid it’s

  beyond me, and if I try I shall only make a fool of myself and be

  laughed at. So please let us give up asking for the present what

  the good is in itself; I’m afraid that to reach what I think would be

  a satisfactory answer is beyond the range of our present inquiry.

  But I will tell you, if you like, about something which seems to

  51 Hamilton, Collected Dialogues of Plato, Republic: 505e; 506d–507a; 508c; 508e–509c.

  59

  lovers of sophia

  me to be a child of the good, and to resemble it very closely – or

  would you rather I didn’t?’

  ‘Tell us about the child and you can owe us your account of the

  parent,’ he said.

  ‘It’s a debt I wish I could pay back to you in ful , instead of only

  paying interest on the loan,’ I replied. ‘But for the present you

  must accept my description of the child of the good as interest...

  ...though the sun is not itself sight, it is the cause of sight and is seen by the sight it causes... ‘Wel , that is what I called the child

  of the good,’ I said. ‘The good has begotten it in its own likeness,

  and it bears the same relation to sight and visible objects in the

  visible realm that the good bears to intelligence and intelligible

  objects in the intelligible realm.’

  ...‘Then what gives the objects of knowledge their truth and the

  knower’s mind the power of knowing is the form of the good.

  It is the cause of knowledge and truth, and you will be right to

  think of it as being itself known, and yet as being something

  other than, and even more splendid than, knowledge and truth,

  splendid as they are. And just as it was right to think of light and

  sight as being like the sun, but wrong to think of them as being

  the sun itself, so here again it is right to think of knowledge and

  truth as being like the good, but wrong to think of either of them

  as being the good, whose position must be ranked still higher.’

  ...‘The sun, I think you will agree, not only makes the things

  we see visible, but causes the processes of generation, growth

  and nourishment, without itself being such a process.’ ‘True’

  ‘The good therefore may be said to be source not only of the

  intelligibility of the objects of knowledge, but also of their


  being and reality; yet it is not itself that reality, but is beyond

  it, and superior to it in dignity and power.’ ‘It real y must be

  miraculously transcendent,’ remarked Glaucon...

  60

  jason reza jorjani

  Taken together these passages suggest the following. The “form

  of the good” is the Sun in light of which all of the other forms are

  il uminated. Yet it must in some way be fundamental y different from

  the other forms, because while Plato’s Socrates can explain “justice”,

  “beauty”, etc... he cannot explain the “form of forms”. While at first he feigns that this is simply due to lack of skil , he ultimately admits that an explanation of the Good in-itself will never be forthcoming because it is inherently impossible. We are told to content ourselves

  with the simile of the Sun, which suggests that the form of the Good

  is to the other forms in the intelligible realm as the Sun is to the

  objects of perception in the sensuous realm.

  So far this is no great revelation – but let us now recall how the mixture of the forms and matter, Being and Non-Being, in

  the receptacle which gives rise to becoming, compromises the

  transcendent sanctity of the forms. If the division between the

  ideal and sensuous worlds col apses according to the logic of Plato’s

  metaphysics, then the form of the Good becomes Heraclitus’ never-

  setting Sun. Is it real y an accident that this Heraclitean symbol lies at the heart of Plato’s philosophy? Or does Plato choose to place it

  there as a sign that in him the Heraclitean vision of his youth has

  surreptitiously assimilated, encompassed and triumphed over

  Parmenides’ idealist revolt? Let us read on from where we left off in

  the Republic:

  I think you know that students of geometry and calculation and

  the like begin by assuming there are odd and even numbers,

  geometrical figures and the three forms of angle, and other

  kindred items in their respective subjects; these they regard as

  known, having put them forward as basic assumptions which

  it is quite unnecessary to explain to themselves or anyone else

  on the grounds that they are obvious to everyone. Starting from

  them, they proceed through a series of consistent steps to the

  conclusion which they set out to find...

  ...You know too that they make use of and argue about visible

 

‹ Prev