Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 12
Lovers of Sophia Page 12

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  political arrangements that aim at the common interest are correct in conforming to what is unqualifiedly just, while those that aim at the interest of their rulers alone are all mistaken and are perversions of the correct political arrangements”.19

  Not only does Aristotle equate unqualified justice with

  lawfulness, but to have particular justice as a character virtue

  means to assume the perspective of a good citizen. Particular

  justice, whether distributive or corrective in kind, is concerned with external goods of fortune,20 especial y those of which one could want

  and take more of than one’s fair share: honor, wealth, and safety.21

  In the Nicomachean Ethics, there is an overlap between Aristotle’s discussion of particular justice (or injustice) with respect to honor, wealth, and safety, and his treatment of the virtues of magnanimity22

  and proper pride,23 which are concerned with honor; liberality24

  and magnificence,25 which are relevant to wealth; and courage,26

  which deals with safety. If there is to be a clear distinction between (particular) justice and these other particular virtues, it is that the latter concern honor, wealth, and safety as such in their significance for oneself, whereas the particular virtue of justice is concerned with them in respect to one’s attitude towards other citizens who are also

  more or less entitled to them.

  In other words, Universal justice encompasses particular justice

  (as one virtue among others) and is, in turn, the socio-political

  condition for the possibility of all of the other particular virtues

  19 Ibid., 1279a17-20, my emphasis.

  20 Ibid., 1129b1-3.

  21 Ibid., 1130b2.

  22 Ibid.,

  Nicomachean Ethics, IV. 3.

  23 Ibid., Nicomachean Ethics, IV.4.

  24 Ibid.,

  Nicomachean Ethics, IV.1.

  25 Ibid.,

  Nicomachean Ethics, IV.2.

  26 Ibid.,

  Nicomachean Ethics, III. 6-9.

  93

  lovers of sophia

  whose practice alone allows human beings to fulfill their purpose.

  If having been properly habituated from childhood counts for

  everything in virtue, and each virtuous person was at one point a child who needed to be raised by already virtuous parents who

  also were once children in need of proper habituation, then where

  does the chain of responsibility end? It cannot be traced in a linear

  manner back to a particular person or group of persons – even to a

  sagacious lawgiver of the past, such as Solon. Rather, for Aristotle,

  its “end” must lie in the circular structure of the self-perpetuating

  polis: the abode of the eternal essence of Man. This turns the polis into both the creative matrix through which all beings come to be,

  and the crowning accomplishment whose excellence is that for-the-

  sake-of-which all things, artificial and natural, have their being.

  To be sure, Aristotle never explicitly sets forth this view.

  Nevertheless, it is a legitimate development from out of the tensions

  in Aristotle’s thinking, and something like it is in order if he is to justify the following statement in his Politics, which contradicts the quotations from Nicomachean Ethics that open this paper: “we set down that the highest good is the end of politics... it takes the greatest part of its pains to produce citizens of a certain sort, namely, ones

  that are good and inclined to perform beautiful actions.”27 If Man

  – taken not as an individual, but collectively in the polis – were essential y one with Nature’s God, then the highest good would

  indeed be the end of politics. Political activity, which opens the space for all other uses of the logos definitive of being human, would be the “divine” final cause even of “the things out of which the cosmos

  is composed.”28 Indeed, the political subordinates all theoretical

  understanding of Nature. The word “theory” stems from the

  Greek verb theorein, the noun belonging to which is theoria; these words involve a conflation of two more basic ones, thea and horao

  – which taken together mean to attentively see to the appearance

  or manifestation of things in an engaged and absorbed manner

  that abides with them. This root thea is also the basis of the Greek 27 Ibid., 1099b29-33, my emphasis.

  28 Ibid., 1141b2.

  94

  jason reza jorjani

  word theatron or “place” ( -tron) of “viewing”, from which we have derived “theater.” The active intellect does not creatively actualize

  phenomena in isolation, but by building the viewing-place of the

  polis.

  3. The Master Craftsmen

  It might seem that Aristotle’s notion of the gods in certain passages in the Nicomachean Ethics29 violates the essential identity of the singular divine Being and collective socio-political human

  existence, for which I have been arguing. First of al , at least in

  certain passages, the gods seem to be a finite multiplicity of beings above human beings, and their distinctive essence is also thinking.

  Aristotle contrasts changing social conventions and standards of

  justice in the human realm with unchanging laws of nature, and

  then implies that the ‘customs’ of the gods would be as unchanging

  as the latter: “among the gods, no doubt, nothing changes at al ”.30 A similar passage at 1154b25-33 in the Nicomachean Ethics states that only a bad natured, or deficient, being needs change and finds it

  sweet, because the transition from pain to pleasure is pleasurable,

  whereas gods enjoy an enduring and single pleasure that is greater

  on account of its motionlessness. We find out that this single,

  continuous pure pleasure is that of intellectual contemplation,

  which Aristotle distinguishes at length from the other merely

  human virtues.31 Intellectual virtue is radical y unlike and separate

  from distributive justice, courage, generosity, and other virtues

  that require other people in order to be practiced, and also from

  virtues like temperance or self-restraint, which are contingently

  dependent on our composite nature as desiring beings subject to

  pain. Intellectual virtue is unconditioned, and it is the sole ‘virtue’

  of the gods.

  29 Ibid., 1134b28; 1154b25-33; 1177b25–1178b25.

  30 Ibid., 1134b28.

  31 Ibid., 1177b25–1178b25.

  95

  lovers of sophia

  Aristotle claims that no one would (or should) deny that the

  gods are real y alive, and therefore at-work in some way. However,

  he maintains that it is also absurd to imagine them making contracts

  with one another, or showing bravery in the face of death during

  war, or being generous to others, and so forth. Thus, the only way

  they are at-work is in their continuous contemplation, and they

  seem not to need anything or anyone else, even other gods, in order

  to experience this singularly blessed pleasure. This seems especial y

  problematic for the interpretation that I have been developing

  when we consider that the gods have no political community. In

  addition to the implication of this in the passages referred to above, at 1145a10-11 in the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle explicitly states that Politics, which orders human cities, does not rule the gods.

  There are, however, some passages that blur the categorical

  distinction between humans and gods in such a way as to allow us

  to take Aristotle’s ‘gods’ as symbolic of the divine element in man,

 
which transcends his composite animal nature. In the course of

  laying out the opposites of three types of character flaws – namely

  vice, lack of self-restraint, and an animal-like state – Aristotle notes that the opposite of the animal-like state is not obvious like the

  other two, and he goes on to identify it as becoming “godlike”. Just

  as an animal-like state is something different from vice, the state

  belonging to a god “is something more honorable than virtue” and

  is “a virtue that transcends us”. He seems to affirm the view that

  “people are turned from humans into gods by a surpassing degree of

  virtue”. Aristotle concludes these remarks32 with the observation that both the animal-like man and the godlike man are rare, which of

  course implies that, however rare, he takes godlike men to actual y

  exist. Aristotle compares the gods to the highest goods, claiming

  that they are above praise, since they cannot be measured by any

  human standard.33 Yet, in the same passage he implies that there

  is nothing wrong with measuring the other way, since he holds

  humans up to the standard of gods, calling them “the most godlike

  32 Ibid., 1145a20-35.

  33 Ibid., 1101b18-25.

  96

  jason reza jorjani

  among men, blessed and happy.” It is also the case that at the end

  of the discussion of the uniqueness of intellectual virtue (referenced above), Aristotle says that we humans should not rest content with

  our mortal nature. We should, rather, strive to be as much like the

  immortals as possible.34

  These passages certainly allow for a reading of ‘the gods’ not as a

  finite class of existing beings separate from humans, but as a foil or counter-point for all that is animal in man. They would hypostatize what, in the finite multiplicity of human being, exists beyond the four causes, as the in-forming principle of all substances. It would be in

  this sense, then, that “those who are completely base… do ungodly

  things.”35 In other words, vicious persons “can do ten thousand times

  as much evil as an animal”36 because they are also something far

  more than ‘a rational species of animal’, and so to betray this is to

  be worse than an animal without such a potentiality. It is to fail to

  realize the ontological difference that there is between beings and

  our Being.

  However, the view that I have been developing here of the polis

  as the theater of Being is further complicated by Aristotle’s implicit establishment of a hierarchy of humanness that begins with a natural slave, goes on to a “merely human” being, and then to a “most

  human” being that is god-like. Rational judgment involves clearly and distinctly delineating things, and “making distinctions is not

  something most people do.”37 Rather, most people are natural slaves, no better than “fatted cattle” or other “beasts of burden”; they are

  incapable of living their own lives properly and need political slave

  drivers to beat them into obedience or banish them if they prove

  “incurable”.38 Aristotle’s analogy between the relation of a master to his slave and the relationship between the rational part of the soul

  and the irrational part that is commanded by it strongly implies that

  34 Ibid., 1178b9-25.

  35 Ibid., 1166b5-6.

  36 Ibid., 1150a9.

  37 Ibid., 1172b3-4.

  38 Ibid., 1095b19-22; 1180a1-13.

  97

  lovers of sophia

  a slave is not a rational being.39 Therefore, a slave is also incapable of virtue, since “there is no virtue without wise judgment.”40 People who are capable of practicing all of the other virtues except the intellectual one are described by Aristotle as “merely human”, whereas the

  intellectual virtue is something “separate” and “most human”; it is

  the divine nature within humanity.41 Unlike other virtues, such as

  courage or charitableness (which require someone to be courageous

  or generous to), contemplation can be pursued without reliance on

  anything external; it also does not aim at any greater good or profit

  for which it may become merely a useful means.42 It is divine in that

  it approximates the self-sufficiency of the gods.43

  This cal s into question the socio-political status of god-

  like humans with intellectual virtue. Just as it undermines the

  reading of virtue as always already socio-political y conditioned

  and contextual, the “god-like” ideal of ful y actualized human

  potential cal s for a reinterpretation of Aristotle’s conception of

  friendship ( philia) – which he takes to be the binding force of the polis. Friendships usual y break up because one or the other of the partners mistakes the type of philia upon which their relationship is based.44 These breakups are so distressing that they become cause

  for questioning oneself. This follows from the fact that the intimacy

  of friendship, extended over a long span of time, is necessary in

  order to secure justified belief concerning our own moral character.45

  We come closest to objective knowledge of our own actions only in

  the “mirror” of character friendship, and this means that we may

  be faced with redefining ourselves or losing our virtuous friends –

  possibly because we cannot tolerate the way in which they make us

  39 Ibid., 1138b8-10.

  40 Ibid., 1144b21-22.

  41 Ibid., 1177b25-1178a25.

  42 Ibid., 1177a20-1177b5; 1178a29-35.

  43 Ibid., 1178b25.

  44 Ibid.,

  Nicomachean Ethics, 9.3.

  45 Ibid., Nicomachean Ethics 9.9 1169b28-1170a4; see also: Magna Moralia 1213a10-26.

  98

  jason reza jorjani

  aware of our own failings. According to Aristotle, virtue friendships

  are the only ones inherently resistant to slander and other violations of trust, and it is on this account that they should be enduring.46

  This, however, presumes that we are capable of enduring them.

  Is it possible for anyone who is not a “god-like” philosopher to

  endure a virtue friendship with someone who is one? This is as much

  as to question whether a virtue friendship is genuinely possible

  between non-philosophers. Aristotle is aware of this difficulty. One

  is supposed to wish the best for one’s friends, but no one who is not

  a philosopher would wish that one’s best friends become god-like,

  otherwise one would no longer be fit to be their friend. Note this

  passage at 1158b29-1159b15:

  But what is equal in matters of justice does not seem to work

  the same way as what is equal in friendship… this is clear if the

  divergence becomes great… for no longer are they friends, nor

  do they deserve to be. This is most manifest in the case of the

  gods… In such cases there is no precise boundary up to which

  they are friends, for when many things have been taken away the

  friendship still remains, but when they are separated greatly, as

  from a god, it no longer does. From this an impasse is raised,

  that perhaps friends do not wish for the greatest goods for their

  friends, such as that they be gods; for then they would no longer

  have friends… [for a person like this to wish] for good things

  for a friend for that friend’s own sake, that friend would need to

  remain whatever he is…

  Here self-love and the
supposed altruism of the truest friendship

  seem to collide. If we are to maintain that Aristotle’s ethics is not

  egoistic, then we must draw the conclusion that character friendship

  is only possible between genuine philosophers. Only those with

  the ruthless aspiration to become “god-like” would be unafraid of

  constantly drawing each other ever further beyond the “merely

  human.” This is in line with two passages where Aristotle describes

  46 Ibid., 1164a14.

  99

  lovers of sophia

  the highest type of friendship as consisting of the dynamical y

  transformational contemplative dialogue exemplified by Plato’s

  Socrates.47 Aristotle’s use of the phrase “going hunting” in the latter of these two passages is a metaphor for the love of wisdom. Aristotle

  also refers to this proverbial ‘fellowship of eagles’ at 1177a27–1177b3

  (my emphasis): “the wise person is able to contemplate even when

  he is by himself, and more so to the extent he is more wise. He will contemplate better, no doubt, when he has people to work with, but he is still the most self-sufficient person.” To conclude, the only

  enduring philia is one wherein friends are bound together not by

  “need” of any kind, but by philo-Sophia – their hopelessly falling for the same beloved, namely Wisdom. Philosophical friendship is

  always at least a ménage a trois.

  This esoteric reading requires taking Aristotle’s pronouncements on the virtues as exoteric. He deliberately concealed his radical view that, inwardly, the free circle of god-like friends lives beyond

  society and above its laws. For such a person the plurality of social y conditioned, public virtues are merely something to be tolerated in

  order to keep from arousing suspicion and meddling that would

  interfere with contemplation:

  …But for someone who contemplates there is no need of such

  things for his being-at-work; rather, one might say they get in

  the way of his contemplating. But insofar as he is a human being

  and lives in company with a number of people, he chooses to do

  the things that have to do with virtue, and thus will have need of

  such things in order to live a human life.48

 

‹ Prev