Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 61
Lovers of Sophia Page 61

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  482

  jason reza jorjani

  incapable of conjuring events and summoning us to them.20 The

  relationship of concepts to their plane is rather that of events to their horizon. The plane is an event horizon, but a horizon independent

  of different observers rather than relative to them. It is what grants the concept its independence of the visible state of affairs through

  which it manifests.21 Strictly speaking, neither can it be thought in

  the way that a concept can, nor is it even a method that defines and

  precedes proper thinking in terms of concepts.22

  Rather, according to Deleuze, the plane of immanence is what

  allows one “to find one’s bearings in thought.”23 Concepts are

  intensive features of absolute dimension encountered in the context

  of this non-conceptual field of understanding, which must always

  already be scoped out for them.24 This cal s to mind the image of

  someone with his hands outstretched as he makes his way through

  a dark but familiar room, where the wal s and furniture are intuited

  before making contact with them as if by an unfocused and invisible

  searchlight. Indeed, Deleuze describes the “diagrammatic features”

  of the plane of consistency as dimensions of fractal (not co-ordinate) directionality that can only be intuited.25 Deleuze goes so far as

  to suggest that this occult background of philosophical thought,

  which only intuition can access, is of the order of dreamlike esoteric experiences that may be classed as pathological and irrational (from

  an academic or scholastic standpoint).26 Deleuze evokes the image

  20 Ibid.

  21 Ibid., 36.

  22 Ibid., 37.

  23 Ibid., 73.

  24 Ibid., 40.

  25 Ibid., 39-40.

  26 Ibid., 41. “Precisely because the plane of immanence is prephilosophical and does not immediately take effect with concepts, it implies a sort of groping experimentation and its layout resorts to measures that are not very respectable, rational, or reasonable. These measures belong to the order of dreams, of pathological processes, esoteric experiences, drunkenness, and excess. We head for the horizon, on the plane of immanence, and we return with bloodshot eyes, yet they are the eyes of the mind. Even Descartes had his dream. To think is always 483

  lovers of sophia

  of a desert whose dunes are always in motion to help us understand

  this space that concepts come to populate, for a time.27

  That which lies beyond conceptual understanding is Chaos. For

  Deleuze the Chaos into which thought plunges is not an absence of

  determinations. Rather, it is characterized by the transformation of

  immeasurable determinations at what he cal s “infinite speed” so that

  they vanish almost as soon as they take shape “without consistency

  or reference, without [discernable] consequence.”28 Deleuze cal s to

  mind the Buddhist notion of Shunyata when he describes Chaos

  as “a void that is not a nothingness.”29 In other words, Being is the

  virtual. This is also Deleuze’s view of the irrational in Nature as

  “infinite variabilities” that we need “just a little order” to protect ourselves from.30

  Deleuze asks, “what would thinking be if it did not constantly confront chaos?”31 The plane of immanence, which allows for the

  creation of concepts, is a section of Chaos – i.e. a cross-section that slices through Chaos.32 Deleuze identifies what he cal s “conceptual

  personae” as the points of view that stand between Chaos and the

  diagrammatic features of the plane, as well as between the plane

  and the concepts that it allows to take shape on the plane. 33 In other words, it is a conceptual persona that first and foremost “plunges

  into the chaos” to extract from it both the diagrammatic features of

  the plane and its intensional features – both the horizon for concept-

  formation and the groups of concepts related by their mutual

  possibility within this horizon.34 He compares this “constructivism”

  to follow the witch’s flight.”

  27 Ibid., 41.

  28 Ibid., 42, 118.

  29 Ibid., 188.

  30 Deleuze,

  What Is Philosophy? , 201.

  31 Ibid., 208.

  32 Ibid., 42.

  33 Ibid., 75.

  34 Ibid.

  484

  jason reza jorjani

  to “a throw of dice” in “a very complex game.”35 This means that

  although at times Deleuze lays out personalistic, diagrammatic, and

  intensive elements involved in philosophy as if they were co-equal

  functions, the personalistic features determine the diagrammatic

  and intensive ones.36

  A philosopher’s name is actual y a pseudonym for his conceptual

  personae, and Deleuze suspects that: “The face and body of

  philosophers shelter these personae who often give them a strange

  appearance, especial y in the glance, as if someone else were

  looking through their eyes.”37 For Deleuze, the “idiot” popularized

  by Dostoevsky – the private man of the cogito – is Descartes’

  conceptual persona.38 Deleuze also cites the examples of “the

  Socrates of Plato”, “the Antichrist” and “the Dionysus of Nietzsche”

  among others.39 Deleuze takes Nietzsche to have worked with more

  conceptual personae, of both a sympathetic and antipathetic nature,

  than any other thinker. Deleuze points out that it is almost a rule

  that sympathetic personae can never ful y free themselves from their

  antipathetic shadow (or “ape” in the case of Zarathustra) to emerge

  into pure positivity.40 For two personae to even be able to encounter

  each other in a hostile manner they have to be functioning on the

  same plane.41 Nietzsche’s sympathetic personae include Dionysus,

  Zarathustra, and the Superman whose arrival he heralds. His

  antipathetic ones are Christ, the Priest, the Last Men, and even

  Socrates (a conceptual persona appropriated from Plato).42

  35 Ibid.

  36 Ibid., 77.

  37 Ibid., 64, 73.

  38 Ibid., 64. In the guise of the question “Descartes goes mad in Russia?”

  Deleuze draws a connection between the conceptual personae of the old and new idiot, as exemplified by Descartes’ doubter in search of absolute mathematical certainty and Dostoevsky’s underground man who wil s a return of the absurdly incomprehensible. (Deleuze, 62-63)

  39 Ibid.

  40 Ibid., 76.

  41 Ibid., 77.

  42 Ibid., 65.

  485

  lovers of sophia

  Although, for this reason, many have seen Nietzsche as a poet

  or mythmaker, his conceptual personae are neither historical figures

  nor literary heroes (or vil ains). By means of them he populates the

  plane of immanence that he lays out – life as will to power – with many new concepts, such as: “forces”, “value”, “becoming”, “life”,

  “eternal return”, “ressentiment” and “bad conscience.”43 It is also with reference to Nietzsche, that Deleuze volunteers one of his most

  il uminating definitions of what he means by evoking a conceptual

  “horizon” as a metaphor for the plane of consistency – namely that

  one plane or another is a bounded field that opens up are certain

  determinate “modes of existence or possibilities of life.”44 Conceptual personae are, in turn, not “invented” in a facile manner so much as

&nb
sp; they are “brought to life.”45

  Deleuze claims that the personal names affixed to diverse

  scientific propositions – such as the Pythagorean theorem, Cartesian

  coordinates, Hamiltonian number, etc. – are not conceptual

  personae, but partial observers that extract prospects from sentences in relation to a particular axis of reference.46 These partial observers

  – even in quantum mechanics – are not indicative of subjectivism,

  they attest to a truth of the relative and not a relativity of truth.47 They are the postulation of a monadic perceptive and experiential capacity

  to be affected to things studied, without which those things could

  not be studied.48 Deleuze also wants to differentiate the conceptual

  personae of philosophy from the psychosocial types studied by the sciences – especial y psychology and sociology.49 He cites the work

  of Simmel and Goffman on identifying certain of these psychological

  types that are functions of a structured social field, such as the

  stranger, the exile, the migrant, the transient, the native, and the

  43 Ibid.

  44 Ibid., 72.

  45 Ibid., 76.

  46 Ibid., 24.

  47 Ibid., 129-130.

  48 Ibid., 130, 155.

  49 Ibid., 67.

  486

  jason reza jorjani

  homecomer.50 Deleuze takes these psychosocial types to be “only

  physical and mental” in nature, whereas conceptual personae are

  “spiritual.”51 Psychosocial types may help us assess the relationship

  of conceptual personae to the epoch in which they manifest, but

  the way in which the personae are in a realm of pure thought above

  (or beneath), beyond, and determinative of a historical milieu qua a state of affairs observable by social science, is taken by Deleuze

  to mean that conceptual personae and psychosocial types never

  merge.52

  Conceptual personae allegedly not only differentiate philosophy

  from science, but also from the arts. Deleuze attempts to draw a clear distinction between the personae of philosophy and the figures of

  art. Unlike conceptual personae, which are “the powers of concepts,”

  aesthetic figures are supposed to be “the powers of affects and

  percepts.” Deleuze draws an analogy between the way that the great

  aesthetic figures of literature (Melville’s Captain Ahab), painting

  (David’s Marat), sculpture (Michelangelo’s David), and music

  (Strauss’ Zarathustra) produce affections and perceptions that go

  beyond those ordinarily experienced, and the way that conceptual

  personae allow us to think beyond ordinary opinions.53 This

  analogy is based on a parallelism of distinction. Deleuze does not

  at all belittle art by comparison to philosophy. He claims that while

  such powerful contemplative artists as Hölderlin, Rimbaud, Kafka,

  Artaud, and Melville are in one sense only “half” philosophers, they

  are “also much more than philosophers.”54

  So long as its materials – stone, canvas, chemical color – last, art

  preserves by means of them and so artworks are also the subject of

  a concern for preservation that is unique to them among all things.55

  This unique concern for preservation of the work of art is on account

  50 Ibid.

  51 Ibid., 68.

  52 Ibid., 70.

  53 Ibid., 65.

  54 Ibid., 67.

  55 Ibid., 163.

  487

  lovers of sophia

  of an at least tacit acknowledgement that what is enfolded within

  it is a compound of percepts and affects, concentrated sensations that have their own manner of being, their own existential capacity

  to affect – even in the absence of human observers – by means of

  perceptions encoded within them.56 This understanding of art in

  terms of percept and affect blurs the boundary between works of art

  and natural becomings: “The artist is a seer, a becomer…”57 Deleuze

  claims that through his relationship with Moby Dick, Captain

  Ahab enters into a becoming-whale that allows him to real y have perceptions of the sea – a nonhuman landscape of nature – and the

  whale for his part has a compound of sensations that involve him in

  a non-human becoming “ocean.”58 Deleuze wants to differentiate the zone of indiscernibility here from that at work within philosophical

  concepts, a non-distinction and reversion of human and animal

  wherein “something or someone is ceaselessly becoming-other.”59

  This does not allow aesthetic figures to grasp heterogeneity in an

  absolute form the way that conceptual personae do.60 Sensory

  becoming only expresses otherness in a striking way.61

  The work of art confronts opinion by strategical y marshalling the

  destructive force of chaos. The artist does not face a blank canvas or an uncarved block; she is always already confronted by a coagulation

  of clichés that must be painted out or chiseled away.62 These clichés

  are the attempts of opinion to resist chaos, but they are too feeble

  and faltering to secure us from a col apse into the abyss. So the artist draws on chaos to produce a composition of sensations that defies

  every opinion, every past attempt at art that has been assimilated

  and uprooted.63 Deleuze uses the term “chaosmos” – borrowed

  56 Ibid., 164.

  57 Ibid., 171.

  58 Ibid., 169.

  59 Ibid., 173, 177.

  60 Ibid., 177.

  61 Ibid.

  62 Ibid., 204.

  63 Ibid.

  488

  jason reza jorjani

  from James Joyce – to refer to this composed chaos wherein chaotic

  variability has been transformed into a chaoid variety that allows for a sensory encounter with chaos.64

  By contrast, whether it transforms the chaotic variability into a

  determinist calculus – where a future state is supposed to be able

  to be determined from a present one – or whether enough of chaos

  is allowed in to only admit of a calculus of statistical probabilities, Science does not aim at the retrieval of chaos. Rather, the scientist

  at least tacitly filters chaos out of a framework of constants, limits, and coordinate axes of mathematical spatio-temporality.65 This

  referenced chaos becomes ‘Nature’ qua object of empirical research

  – by contrast with the natural non-human becomings at work in

  art.66 The sciences slow down the infinite into a “freeze-frame” that

  allows for propositional thought to penetrate matter, turning the

  virtual into a finite quantity of movement, force, or energy bounded

  by the parameters of a universal constant (e.g. the speed of light) so that it congeals into the formulaic mold of a frame of reference.67

  Yet there are numerous instances throughout What is Philosophy?

  where Deleuze undermines his sharp disciplinary distinction

  between philosophy, science, and art. Some of his remarks readily

  lend themselves to deconstructing this distinction altogether.

  Deleuze sees Art, Science, and Philosophy as the three daughters of

  Chaos, like the three muses. He dubs them “Chaoids.” They produce

  realities out of Virtuality.68 Yet, interestingly, the parallelism and tripartite distinction between them is undermined by the ontological

  priority that Deleuze assigns to the chaoid of philosophy. Concepts are not principles governing the reasonable association of ideas


  or things; they are “mental objects determinable as real beings.”69

  Concepts cut a plane of immanence through chaos, like a cross-

  64 Ibid., 204-205.

  65 Ibid., 205.

  66 Ibid., 206.

  67 Ibid., 118-119.

  68 Ibid., 208.

  69 Ibid., 207.

  489

  lovers of sophia

  section that gives chaos an intellectual y conceivable consistency – a

  “mental chaosmos” which is “a chaoid state par excellence.”70 This

  plainly asserts that the chaoid of philosophy sets the standard for

  those of art and science.71 It contradicts Deleuze’s claim elsewhere72

  that philosophy is not superior to science and art.

  Bearing this in mind, let us look at Deleuze’s admission that the

  relationship between philosophy, science, and art is not merely an

  extrinsic interdisciplinary one.73 There is also an intrinsic relationship between the three on the basis of which we not only see how they

  would need each other74, but why his claim that they are distinct at

  all must real y be called into question. One example of this “intrinsic type of interference” is “when concepts and conceptual personae

  seem to leave a plane of immanence that would correspond to them,

  so as to slip in among the functions and partial observers, or among

  the sensations and aesthetic figures, on another plane; and similarly

  in the other cases.” While on the one hand Deleuze claims that

  “these slidings are so subtle, like those of Zarathustra in Nietzsche’s philosophy” or when “partial observers introduce into science

  sensibilia that are sometimes close to aesthetic figures,” he admits

  that it can bring us to “find ourselves on complex planes that are

  difficult to qualify…mixed planes…” constituted by “interferences

  that cannot be localized.”75 Most significantly, Deleuze sees that

  it is here where “concepts, sensations, and functions become

  undecidable, at the same time as philosophy, art, and science become

  indiscernible,” that they extend a common shadow out of chaos and

  into the future – the specter of the “people to come.”76

  Deleuze also equates the artist and the philosopher, or views

  them as interchangeable, at two crucial points when he is talking

  70 Ibid., 208.

  71 Ibid.

  72 Ibid., 8.

  73 Ibid., 192, 196, 217-218.

  74 Ibid., 218.

  75 Ibid., 217.

 

‹ Prev