onkings

Home > Other > onkings > Page 45
onkings Page 45

by Faun Rice


  élever un nourisson; prendre soin de quelq’un, comme une mère s’occupe de ses

  enfants” (1899: 624).

  19. That would be mikarakara or mitandrina, or, if the meaning was just curing, mitsabo.

  It’s important to emphasize in what follows that mitaiza has never been used as a

  general term for any relation of caretaking, but only those of a particularly intimate

  or, alternately, ritually significant kind.

  270

  ON KINGS

  celebration of the ancestral dead thus ultimately turns into a war against death

  itself, and just as an unlocked or unattended tomb can lead to ghosts escaping

  to steal one’s babies, the most appropriate response to locking one, I was often

  told, was to immediately go home and have sex, preferably with one’s wife or

  husband, if not with anyone who’s willing and available, since doing so at that

  moment was most likely to bring new babies into the world.

  These are obviously extremely abbreviated descriptions, but they serve to

  bring home two points I believe to be critical. The first is that the theme of nur-

  ture, and, especially, women’s labor in the rearing of children, is a key way of im-

  aging the creative power of ritual; the second, that such relations tend to become

  the locus of reversals of authority structures, where ancestors turn into children,

  or slaves turn into vehicles for kings. These reversals don’t necessarily overthrow

  or challenge relations of authority (though they can), but they definitely become

  a way of negotiating such relations. All this is important when one turns back

  to royal ritual, because the moment one begins to look, one starts seeing all sorts

  of obvious parallels—even though these are precisely the elements that might

  otherwise be most likely to be overlooked if one did not have this larger ritual

  context in mind.

  Understanding the ritual logic is all the more crucial because highland king-

  doms—whether the various warring principalities of the eighteenth century or

  the great imperial state of the nineteenth—were essentially organized on ritual

  terms. This is not to deny that they were not also vast forms of labor extraction;

  rather, it is to suggest that within them no clear distinction between what we

  would call “work” and what we would call “ritual” could be made (cf. Sahlins

  1985: 113). Both were seen as necessary, and overlapping, aspects in the con-

  stant human efforts required to create and maintain the material and social

  universe.20

  We might state the matter this way: What we call “societies” are always vast

  coordinated systems of ritualized labor. Always, too, the elementary unit of any

  such system is some kind of household; however it might be configured (and

  as anthropologists know, there are an enormous number of possibilities in this

  20. It is worth noting that while there is a Malagasy word for “work” ( asa), there is no

  generic word for what we’d call “ritual”—the closest is, perhaps, fanasinana, which

  is the term for the actions of making things masina, powerful or sacred. But not

  all forms of ritual were considered fanasinana—mortuary ritual, for instance, was

  not. What’s more, many types of ritual—notably, mediumistic curing—could often

  themselves be referred to as “asa” or work.

  THE PEOPLE AS NURSEMAIDS OF THE KING

  271

  regard), this household is the elementary unit of work, solidarity, domination,

  and the creation and fashioning of human beings. In this sense women’s labor,

  which tends to predominate within households, is also the most fundamental

  form of work itself. These statements, I think, can be made of any known hu-

  man society. Obviously, this is never all. Anything we feel merits the name of

  a “society” will also have more encompassing structures through which all this

  is coordinated: clans, temple complexes, joint-stock corporations, and so forth.

  Usually, these look quite different from households. What makes monarchies

  unique is that, much though there might be all sorts of things going on in the

  middle of the hierarchy, the very top almost exactly resembles the very bottom.

  Kingdoms not only begin with households, they also end with one. This apical

  household is, of course, the royal household.

  Now, certainly, royal households are almost invariably far more elaborate

  than any ordinary households (which do not, for instance, ordinarily involve

  harems attended by eunuch slaves, dancing dwarfs, and so forth), and often they

  are organized in ways that can only be described as intentionally perverse, in the

  sense of violating the basic moral principles that govern ordinary households

  (led by men who murder their fathers, marry their sisters, and so forth), but they

  are considered households nonetheless; in the final analysis, they are the same

  sort of unit, a domestic unit creating, nurturing, and educating children—that

  is, producing people—as the household units at the very base.

  The difference, of course, is that the royal household, in the vast majority

  of cases anyway, was only about the creation of people, and did not involve all

  those other forms of production—of food, clothing, ironware, basketry, and so

  on—that in ordinary households served as essential material elements for that

  process of tending, growing, and nurturing human beings. In fact, the tendency

  in those ordinary households is for what we would label “work,” “play,” “ritual,”

  and “education” to be, not indistinguishable perhaps, or not usually, but in every

  way entangled, overlapping, and mutually entailed. In contrast, royal households

  could be seen as the first prefiguration of the modern consumer household,

  which at least ideally is set in a sphere entirely opposed to the “production” of

  material goods, which is just about the creating and shaping and maintaining

  of people. Royal households largely divorce the making, shaping, and maintain-

  ing of people from the making, shaping, and maintaining of things. They also

  separate work, ritual, and play—at least, when royal figures do plow fields or lay

  the foundations of buildings, it’s almost invariably as a form of ritual play; it’s

  not considered actual labor. Royal households will tend to be full of servants and

  272

  ON KINGS

  retainers, some of whose work is to continually teach members of the royal fam-

  ily how to behave like proper royalty, just as, say, presidents and prime ministers

  nowadays tend to be surrounded by hosts of aides and advisors whose function

  is to teach and remind them how to be proper heads of state. But rarely do they

  do a lot of what we’d consider productive work. What we’d call “material pro-

  duction” tends to be outsourced onto other households.

  This might seem an odd way to frame things. Surely, kingdoms are not run

  by a royal household. They’re run by an individual called “the king.” Which is,

  of course, true: no kingdom has ever been ruled by a household collectively (at

  least, not officially), and in principle, the entire purpose of the royal household

  is to produce that one single individual—the monarch—who is, properly speak-

  ing, the entire focus of all ritual l
abor. But the apparatus for the creation of such

  individuals is nonetheless crucial, since such individuals, for all their occasional

  insistence to the contrary, are mortal, and can be replaced at any time.

  I’m emphasizing all of this—at least some of which might seem self-

  evident—because I think it’s important to problematize received categories in

  order to understand what’s really going on in monarchies, which are, after all, an

  extremely common form of government historically, even if they seem strange

  and exotic to most people today. The terms of political economy, invented in

  the North Atlantic world around the same time that modern republican forms

  of government were being instituted in the late eighteenth century, really don’t

  seem adequate to describe them. These terms propose a very simple schematic

  version of what an “economy” is, one that has become so much a matter of com-

  mon sense that we have to remind ourselves that for most people, the very idea

  of a division between spheres of “production” (in workplaces) and “consump-

  tion” (at home) would simply make no sense. Some of the attendant political

  economy categories have been thoroughly critiqued by anthropologists. Others

  have not.

  Take, for instance, the commonplace notion that labor is basically about

  “production”: that it’s typically directed at making things, transforming the

  world by combining raw materials into finished products. This is simply as-

  sumed in most theoretical literature. But it’s a very odd assumption. Even a

  moment’s reflection should make clear that nowhere in the world is most activ-

  ity we would ordinarily refer to as “work”21 directed at making anything. This is

  21. Let us define “work” here as repetitive or formalized activity not performed for its

  own sake, but primarily to change the state of something else.

  THE PEOPLE AS NURSEMAIDS OF THE KING

  273

  true even if we restrict ourselves to work directed at material objects. Most such

  labor isn’t aimed at producing things, but at cleaning or maintaining them or

  moving them around. A ceramic coffee cup is “produced” just once; it’s washed

  and stacked a thousand times. Even if it’s a disposable paper or styrofoam coffee

  cup, far more time and energy is spent transporting, storing, and disposing of it

  than in the relatively brief moment of its actual fabrication.22

  This blindness has any number of pernicious effects, but for present purposes

  I am just invoking it to make three points which I think are crucial to under-

  stand the organization of labor in Merina kingdoms. The first is the obvious an-

  thropological one: that we cannot presume Malagasy assumptions about what

  work is and what is important about it necessarily mirror our own. And they

  are indeed quite different. The second is that, as I’ve argued elsewhere (Graeber

  2007c), assumptions about the nature of work tend to be organized around cer-

  tain forms of what I will call “paradigmatic labor”—that is, certain varieties of

  work effectively stand in, in the popular imagination, for a whole class of other

  ones. In contemporary social science, and, to a large extent, popular discourse as

  well, the two most important of these are factory work and childcare. The first

  has become the paradigm for all paid work, the second, for unremunerated, do-

  mestic labor. This is the imagery lurking in the background, for instance, when

  Marxists speak of “productive” versus “reproductive” labor; this is what can allow

  popular commentators to blithely declare that the decline in the number of fac-

  tories in Britain or America means there is no more working class in such coun-

  tries, even though there’s probably never been a single place in the history of the

  world where the majority of working-class people were employed in factories.

  The third point is that in monarchies like the Merina kingdom, the easiest

  way to understand how work was imagined is by examining the forms of ritual-

  ized labor surrounding kings.

  Let me introduce another distinction here, and cite a term I introduced in an

  earlier work (Graeber 2007c): “emblematic labor.” If paradigmatic labor is what

  you imagine to be the model for work in general, or a whole broad category of

  work, emblematic labor is work seen as typical of a certain group of people, a

  kind of work that defines what sort of people they are seen ultimately to be. A

  “fisherman” might spend only a relatively small proportion of his time actually

  fishing, he might even get a larger proportion of his income from something

  22. In this sense, even my previous comments about households and production aren’t

  precisely right.

  274

  ON KINGS

  else, but a “fisherman” is nonetheless what he is basically seen to be. In many

  societies, this emblematic labor is the kind of work that sort of person does in

  ceremonial contexts. Caste systems are an obvious case in point: drummers or

  washermen or barbers in an Indian village do not spend most of their working

  days making music, washing, or cutting hair. Yet those activities define their role

  in the larger society, largely by determining what role they play in important

  cosmological rituals.

  A. M. Hocart (1950) in fact insisted that caste systems of this sort originate

  specifically in royal rituals, where, as in Fiji, different groups in a kingdom were

  defined by the kind of labor they performed specifically for the king. Thus in

  Fijian kingdoms, there were certain groups identified as fishermen—not be-

  cause they spent most of their time fishing, or even because they spent more

  of their time fishing than anyone else (everybody fished), but because it was

  their responsibility to provide fish to the court or royal rituals. Each Fijian clan

  was characterized by its own form of emblematic labor, and this was seen as

  establishing what kind of people they really were. Eighteenth- and nineteenth-

  century Merina arrangements have been referred to as “caste-like” for similar

  reasons (e.g., Bloch 1977): different ancestries, and different orders of nobility,

  were defined by the work they performed for the royal household (particularly,

  the products they brought as first-fruits or santatra), and the role they played in

  building royal houses and royal tombs.

  I think examining emblematic labor in the Merina kingdom in this fashion

  is the best way to understand the structure of the kingdom, and the role of

  the royal household. But in order to do so we first must say something about

  paradigmatic labor. In highland Madagascar, the paradigm for work in general

  is not production or even, precisely, childcare. When people think of “work,”

  they think first and foremost of the bearing of burdens: moving, dragging, and,

  especially, carrying things, which includes everything from carrying babies to

  dragging trunks of wood to moving earth with shovels. The semantic range and

  web of associations is quite different than we are used to. But once we under-

  stand this, a lot of other things begin to make much better sense.

  Speaking, carrying, and making

  The essentials of the matter do not seem to have changed much sin
ce the nine-

  teenth century. Then as now, work was seen as centered on the household, and

  was primarily the business of women. This is not to say men did not work at

  THE PEOPLE AS NURSEMAIDS OF THE KING

  275

  all—often they worked very hard—but women spent more of their time in ac-

  tivities viewed as working ( asa), and women’s general dispositions were seen as

  pragmatic, industrious, and generally work-oriented in a way that men’s simply

  were not.23 If I were to guess what kind of paradigmatic image was called to

  mind by the idea of work—parallel to the clock-punching industrial worker

  of our own imagination—it would most likely be a young woman, infant slung

  over her back, laboring in a rice field, or carrying water or produce on her head.

  Domestic labor here represents the perfect fusion of child-rearing and physi-

  cal work because women tend to attend to children and carry out other duties

  simultaneously.

  The paradigmatic form of work, then, was—and is—not seen as a making

  or building anything, or even maintaining anything, but, rather, lifting things

  up and moving them around. The importance of such matters can be seen in

  that fact that, traditionally, who carries what for whom in what circumstances

  is carefully regulated, at least in formal or ritual moments—indeed, formal or

  ritual moments are above all those in which the niceties of etiquette in such

  matters are strictly enforced.24 Who carries what for whom is probably the most

  important way of indicating rank. Even well-educated, not particularly tradi-

  tional women, I found, would on trips occasionally make (half-hearted) offers

  to carry my backpack, noting that, properly, if a man and woman are of roughly

  the same age, the man shouldn’t be the one shouldering the burden. But mainly

  these rules applied to seniority. As elsewhere in Madagascar, the ranking of

  children by age is especially important. Indeed, insofar as one can speak of an

  “atom of hierarchy’” in highland society, it is embodied in the principle—re-

  peated in proverbs—that elder brothers or sisters should speak for their juniors,

  and juniors, carry burdens for their seniors.25 Often this is treated as a reciprocal

  23. Women in general endlessly denounced males as lazy ( kamo lahy), either individually

 

‹ Prev