onkings

Home > Other > onkings > Page 72
onkings Page 72

by Faun Rice


  der to demote his descendants (see chapter 2). Even the much more powerful

  Ganda kings were sometimes foiled in similar attempts. When one particularly

  high-handed kabaka ordered the shrine of a divinized ancestor be burned to

  the ground, “a spark from the burning shrine flew up and burned the Queen

  Mother’s breast,” leaving a wound that continued to pain her until the king

  finally relented and ordered the shrine be restored to its former state (Kagwa

  1971: 74; Wrigley 1996: 211).53

  53. General y speaking, it would seem that royal ancestors were seen as not particularly

  remarkable ancestral spirits by royals, and as gods by everyone else (Ray 1991: 150–53).

  438

  ON KINGS

  For kings to erase ancestral memories, then, requires extreme measures, and

  those measures may backfire. Attempts to wipe ancestors out of history, as, for

  instance, the New Kingdom pharaoh Thutmoses III famously tried to wipe out

  his mother Hatshepsut and her steward Senenmut, rarely succeed (though ad-

  mittedly if such a project did succeed completely, we would not know about it).54

  Still, even when ancestors cannot be destroyed, they can be marginalized or

  made irrelevant. Stranger-kingship itself might be seen in some cases as a way

  of wiping the slate clean by starting over somewhere else. Another approach is

  to mark some sort of fundamental break or rupture so as to announce a new

  dynasty. Obviously, this is more likely to be an expedient used by popular forces

  or court officials against sitting kings, but there are also cases where the dynastic

  break appears to be internal. The case of Unas is again instructive. He is consid-

  ered the last ruler of the Fifth Dynasty, but in fact there is no evidence his suc-

  cessor, Teti, was an outsider in any particular sense (W. S. Smith 1971: 189–91;

  Rice 2003: 210; Grimal 1988: 79–81)—most of Unas’ court officials remained

  in place, and the new pharaoh, presumably from at least a collateral branch of

  the ruling line, appears to have married one of the old pharaoh’s daughters to

  preserve continuity. He also founded a new capital further from the old burial

  grounds and built two pyramids, in addition to his own, for his primary wives,

  all of which suggests an effort to restart the historical memory—and, presum-

  ably, limit the postmortem ambitions of the overweening Unas. In the latter

  endeavor he had only very limited success, since Unas was later revived as a local

  deity, and was still receiving popular cult around Saqqara many centuries later

  during the Middle and New Kingdoms, by which time Teti would appear to

  have been largely forgotten (Malek 2000: 250–56).

  This leads to the final peril of attempts to marginalize earlier rulers, ances-

  tors or otherwise: that even if the social apparatus by which their memories are

  maintained is thoroughly uprooted, they may become popular heroes, taken up

  as a weapon on the other side of the constitutive war between king and people.

  This often happens at the end of dynasties. The first recorded case we have is,

  surprisingly, the Emperor Nero, the last of the Julio-Claudians. Nero is now

  54. I should emphasize that I am speaking here of the difficulty of destroying the

  memories of a king’s own ancestors. The systematic destruction and/or desecration

  of the apparatus of memory for conquered rulers is a regular practice; our first

  historical record of such practices coming from the Assyrian empire, which would

  regularly attempt to uproot and destroy the memory of conquered dynasties

  (Suriano 2010: 65–67), but the practice is commonplace.

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  439

  remembered through the eyes of his enemies as a monster, a bloodthirsty psy-

  chopath who, ridiculously, fancied himself a great poet, actor, and musician. But

  even in the official accounts there are strong indications that his eccentricities

  actually cut quite the other way: during his early reign he systematically re-

  fused to sign death warrants, and even ordered that gladiators no longer fight

  to the death at games he sponsored. (He did, however, on one occasion order

  that senators themselves take part in the now bloodless fencing contests, which

  might begin to explain some of the vitriol.) He also attempted to negotiate

  a permanent peace with Rome’s main imperial rival Parthia.55 Odd though it

  may seem, Nero was about as close to a pacifist as Rome produced. He might

  have gone a bit further than some in trying to glorify his name and preserve his

  memory (“he took the former appellations from many things and numerous

  places and gave them new ones from his own name. He also called the month

  of April Neroneus and was minded to name Rome Neropolis” [Suetonius, Nero

  55]). After Nero was overthrown in a military coup in ad 68, all of this appa-

  ratus of memory was immediately dismantled, he became one of the few Julio-

  Claudians never to be deified,56 and attempts were made to paint him as a tyrant

  so awful that the subsequent imposition of military rule was entirely justified

  (Henderson 1905; Griffin 1984; Champlin 2003).

  Most of Nero’s former subjects, apparently, disagreed. Already in ad 96, we

  read that “even now, everybody wishes Nero were still alive; and the great ma-

  jority believe that he is” (Dio Chrysostom 21.10). Three different pretenders

  55. Nero’s misfortune was that while he was anything but brutal by Roman standards,

  those relative few on whom he did vent his wrath—Christians, who were widely

  held to have been responsible for the fire that devastated Rome in ad 64, and the

  senatorial class, after many, including his former mentor Seneca, were implicated

  in an assassination plot in ad 65—were precisely those who wrote later histories.

  For what it’s worth, I have always personally suspected that Christians (perhaps

  the Peter faction) actually were at least partly responsible for the great fire—some

  certainly can be seen to be gloating about it in Revelations 18.8-20—and that Nero

  might not have actually died in ad 68 at all, since the account of his suddenly

  abandoning a plan to flee to the east for no particular reason and instead killing

  himself (Suetonius Nero 48–49) seems novelistic and implausible. For all we know,

  the “imposter” who ended up in Persia was really him.

  56. Normal practice was to deify emperors only after their deaths so the reigning

  princeps could be referred to as “son of a god” ( divi filius). Nero thus duly deified his

  adopted father Claudius, and later added his wife Poppaea and daughter Claudia,

  but for obvious reasons he did not receive the same honors after his own death

  (Woolf 2002: 250).

  440

  ON KINGS

  claiming to be Nero appeared in the eastern provinces, at least one sparking a

  widespread revolt; the Parthians kept another as a bargaining chip; and as late as

  ad 410, St. Augustine of Hippo wrote that pagans still insisted Nero was sleep-

  ing somewhere, waiting “until the time is right” to reclaim his throne, just as

  Christians feared that, though dead, he would rise from the grave as Antichrist

  ( Civ. Dei 20.19.3). As one biographer writes:

  The persistent expectation that
Nero would return from hiding (or from the

  dead, in the negative formulation of the Antichrist) puts him into the select

  company of historical figures whom people wanted to return, figures like King

  Arthur, Charlemagne, Saint Olaf, Frederick Barbarossa, Frederick II, Constan-

  tine XI, Tsar Alexander I, and Elvis Presley. (Champlin 2003: 21)

  The latter, significantly, referred to as “the King.”57 To which list one might add

  Cuatemoc in Mexico and Tupac Amaru in Peru. Almost every one of these was

  a figure whose memory his successors had attempted, vainly, to suppress.

  2. Becoming the dead

  Another way to solve the problem is by declaring oneself the same person as

  a previous, more famous ruler, or, even more, through a system of positional

  succession, saying that all kings are effectively the same person. Think of this

  perhaps as the ultimate extension of Marshall Sahlins’ “kinship” or “heroic I,”

  whereby a Maori chief can tell an enemy, “I killed your grandfather,” referring

  to an event that happened many centuries before (Prytz-Johansen 1954: 29–31;

  Sahlins 1983a: 522–23; 2013: 36–37).

  Stephanie Dalley (2005: 20) has argued that the former approach was quite

  common in the ancient Middle East, where living monarchs could assimilate

  themselves to more famous antecedents, “prototypes” of great rulers—as, say,

  Sargon I of Assyria (722–705 bc) simply took on the name and persona of

  Sargon of Akkad (c. 2340–2284 bc), or various independently minded queens

  in the same part of the world all became “Semiramis.”58 One might say there is

  57. For an excellent Durkheimian analysis of Elvis as messiah figure in the American

  religion of consumerism, see Stromberg (1990).

  58. “A striking feature of ancient Mesopotamian history is the naming of a new king

  after a much earlier king of a different dynasty to whom he was unrelated. Sargon,

  Naram-Sin, and Nebuchadnezzar are three obvious examples” (Dalley 2005: 20).

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  441

  a strong form and a weak form of such identification. Almost all kings will play

  this game in the weak sense: either by identifying with past heroes (as Edward

  IV, to take a fairly random example, presented himself as a reincarnation of

  King Arthur [Hughes 2002]), or just by all taking the same name: this is why in

  the High Middle Ages almost all English monarchs were named either Henry

  or Edward, and France had sixteen different kings named Louis. Attempting

  this strategy in the strong sense of claiming to actually be Sargon, or Arthur, or

  the last Louis, is relatively rare. All Shilluk reths are embodiments of the found-

  er, “Nyikang,” but one reason the Shilluk kingship is considered so interesting

  and exotic is because they are one of the few to take this principle to its logical

  conclusion, and even among the Shilluk, it’s not as if the historical personalities

  of individual sovereigns are actually wiped out.

  In fact, positional succession systems, whereby whoever takes a given office

  is assimilated to some historical prototype, are much more typical of relatively

  egalitarian political orders like the seventeenth-/eighteenth-century Haudeno-

  saunee (“League of the Iroquois”), where the characters said to have been in-

  volved in the creation of the League centuries before were still very much alive:

  the fire-keeper of the central Onondaga lodge was always Thadodaho; the Roll

  Call of the Founders recorded the names of fifty original chiefs who were still

  present at every League council (Morgan 1851: 64–65; Graeber 2001: 121–29;

  Abler 2004). But these were societies where there was no real difference be-

  tween names and titles, since each clan had a fixed stock of names, which could

  only be portioned out by clan matrons one at a time, and the entire effect seems

  to be to minimize the scope for personal self-aggrandizement.59 Kings tend to

  avoid positional succession for exactly this reason. It might allow them to de-

  stroy their ancestors’ ability to make a unique name for themselves, but only by

  the sacrifice of their own.

  There are few exceptions. Perhaps the most famous is the Luapulu king-

  dom of Central Africa, whose ruler is always Kazembe (Cunnison 1956, 1957,

  1959)—but only because the Luapulu dynasty appears to have conquered a

  group of people who, very unusually for Africa, practice positional succession

  in their lineages. (When a man or woman dies, for instance, another is given

  their name, and accedes to their possessions and even family, though they are

  59. For this reason, the two most famous figures in the epic, considered the founders of

  the League—Deganawideh and Hiawatha—still exist as titles, but their positions

  are never filled.

  442

  ON KINGS

  allowed after a brief decent interval to divorce an unwanted spouse acquired in

  this way.) By far the more common pattern is the weak version exemplified by

  the medieval notion of the “King’s Two Bodies” (Kantorowicz 1957), where the

  king is a flesh-and-blood individual, capable of receiving personal allegiance,

  and an immortal concept at the same time.

  3. Outdoing the dead

  This one is fairly self-explanatory; we’ve already seen how even kings who ac-

  complish feats so extraordinary their own ancestors vanish (does anyone know

  or care who Alexander’s grandparents were?) will make up some imaginary rival

  like Semiramis to compete with. We’ve also seen how monarchs dealt with the

  continued presence of mummified ancestors in political life in two very different

  circumstances: in Peru, where each new Inka had to conquer a new territory to

  feed their dependents; and in Egypt, where, the Nile Valley being circumscribed

  and further opportunities for conquest rarely available, the result was an efflo-

  rescence of monumental architecture unparalleled before or since.

  Building monuments, of course, is effective only if one manages to attach

  one’s name to that monument over the long term. It can be difficult to make

  names stick. As we’ve seen in the case of Semiramis, if you establish enduring

  fame—however you manage to attain it—you will also tend to get credit for all

  sorts of monuments you did not build and probably never even touched or saw,

  in much the way that all witty things said in late-nineteenth-century America

  now tend to be attributed to Mark Twain, or in England, to either George

  Bernard Shaw or Oscar Wilde, leaving those who actually did say the witty

  things or build the various earthworks, walls, towers, and cities ascribed to the

  queen to languish in obscurity.

  There is another option I haven’t really discussed, however, and that’s a

  hypertrophy of sovereignty itself, in the specific sense of arbitrary destructive

  power. It is hard to find any other explanation for why, when kings do manage to

  accumulate enough power that their kingdoms can be called “states”—basically

  that tipping-point at which kings can be definitively said to win—one of the

  first things they do is embark on some kind of campaign of ritualized murder.

  Such massacres include the acts of mass sadism that, as Lewis Mumford used

&n
bsp; to point out (1967: 183–85), we so often squeamishly write out of history—the

  massacres, torture, mutilation—but typically, in this initial phase at least, they

  can justifiably be labeled human sacrifice.

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  443

  For archaeologists, for instance, it is notorious that the mass slaughter of

  retainers at the burial of rulers tends to mark the very first stages of the emer-

  gence of states.60 It can sometimes escalate to the massacre of entire courts. The

  phenomenon has been thoroughly documented among other places for early

  Egypt, Ur, Nubia, Cahokia, China, Korea, Tibet, and Japan; as well as the Mo-

  che in Peru, Scythians, and Huns (Childe 1945; Davies 1984; Parker Pearson

  1999; van Dijk 2007; Morris 2007, 2014). It has also been documented ethno-

  graphically in West Africa, India, and among the Natchez. As the final example

  makes clear, when one is dealing with kings whose absolute and arbitrary power

  was largely confined to the circle of their own court, such mass killings might

  best viewed as a kind of final supernova of sovereignty—but a sovereignty still

  incapable, for all its blazing out in glory, of bursting through its frames. It’s also

  important to remember these sacrifices were organized not by the former king

  (who was after all dead) but by his successor. In this light it’s telling that at least

  two of the more dramatic cases of retainer sacrifice (Peru, early Egypt) are in

  precisely places where later we find dead kings maintaining their own courts

  and retinues, and competing with the living for a share of the surplus—suggest-

  ing one motive might simply be to ensure this did not occur. Instead, in a curi-

  ous twist, a final display of divine power that ostensibly catapults the ruler into

  godhood also serves to wipe out the entire human apparatus that had served to,

  in Audrey Richards’ (1964) felicitous phrase, “keep the king divine.”

  Why, then, does it stop? Ellen Morris (2014: 86–87) suggests that, histori-

  cally, retainer sacrifice tends to lead to a dangerous game of one-upmanship.

  Other royal households, or just wealthy and powerful ones, will adopt the prac-

  tice; kings will then feel they have to kill even more retainers to assert their ex-

  ceptional nature. They will also, inevitably, come to measure themselves against

 

‹ Prev