An Introduction to Madhva Vedan

Home > Other > An Introduction to Madhva Vedan > Page 9
An Introduction to Madhva Vedan Page 9

by Deepak Sarma


  49

  anyathâ-khyâti, the New Theory that False Cognition is Knowing

  [Something] as Otherwise.

  Mâdhva realism

  Madhvâcârya’s epistemology undeniably is the foundation for his

  extreme realism. Positing sâkùî enables the existence of a subtle

  predominance of experiential knowledge over both úruti and anumâna.

  Though Madhvâcârya never states that experience has such importance,

  it certainly seems to follow that it does.

  Like all else in the Mâdhva universe, the components of his realist

  epistemology are arranged hierarchically. Some components have more

  authority than others. Some sentients are destined to have increased

  capabilities over others.

  Madhvâcârya’s realism necessitates a rich and developed ontology

  that is also hierarchical. As long as the universe is real, as are our

  perceptions of it, describing its components is a crucial and unavoidable

  task. To begin to accomplish this I will turn to an analysis of Mâdhva

  ontology, to the machinery and ingredients of the universe.

  63

  CHAPTER THREE

  Mâdhva ontology

  As stated in the Parama Úruti: ‘... The wise [recognize] that [the

  universe] is known and protected by Viùõu. Therefore it, [the

  universe,] is proclaimed to be real. But Hari [that is, Viùõu] alone is

  supreme.’1

  This passage, taken from Madhvâcârya’s VTV, strikes at the heart of

  his ontology. For Madhvâcârya, the universe is unquestionably real,

  as are its components. Viùõu, who is the pinnacle of the Mâdhva

  system, moreover, governs real things. To explain these relationships,

  Madhvâcârya offers what he believes to be a comprehensive analysis

  and classification system of all the items that one could possibly

  encounter. Such an account is not to be trivialized, for correct

  knowledge of Viùõu and the nature and function of the universe is

  essential in order to progress on the path to mokùa, liberation.

  Like the elements of his epistemology, those of his rich ontology are

  also arranged hierarchically. Viùõu, the central deity in the Mâdhva

  pantheon, plays the most important role in the Mâdhva universe. He is

  the facilitator of all entities and possible events. He not only acts in the

  universe; in fact, the entire universe is manifested due to His activity.

  As I point out in Chapter 4, knowledge of this hierarchy and acting in accordance to one’s place in it, results in mokùa, liberation from

  the cycle of birth and rebirth. The importance of hierarchy in the

  Mâdhva world becomes undeniable where Madhvâcârya’s soteriology

  is concerned.

  Madhvâcârya’s personal, interactive and existent God directly

  contrasts with the impersonal divinity found in the school of Advaita

  Vedânta. Madhvâcârya’s conception of God differs from the quasi-

  idealism-realism of the Viúiùñâdvaita School founded by the Vaiùõavite

  Râmânujâcârya. If one were to plot the traditions on a continuum,

  Úaükarâcârya’s impersonal absolute of the Advaita School would be

  found at one end, Râmânuja’s immanent-yet-transcendent, qualified

  monotheism slightly right of center and Madhvâcârya’s mitigated

  monotheism at the other end, as illustrated in Fig. 3.1.

  1 mataü hi jñâninâmetasmitaü trâtaü ca viùõunâ | tasmât satyam iti proktaü paramo harir eva tu iti paramaúrutiþ | VTV.

  50

  64

  Mâdhva Ontology

  51

  Advaita

  Viúiùñâdvaita

  Mâdhva

  Impersonal Absolute

  personal God

  nirguõa

  saguõa

  3.1 Schools of Vedânta

  The schools can also be distinguished according to the significance they

  give to hierarchy. For the Advaita School there is no deity at the top of an

  ontological hierarchy, while such a gradation has eminent importance in

  the Mâdhva school.

  To map out this hierarchy, Madhvâcârya offers a number of different

  categories within which to classify all of the constituent parts of the

  universe. Given the various ontologies to which he was exposed,

  it comes as no surprise that his taxonomical language is dependent

  on those of his predecessors. His categories are reminiscent of the

  Vaiúeùika and Sâükhya schools and may be modifications of their

  respective concepts.2

  I reply upon several texts for my analysis of the components of

  Mâdhva ontology. These include Madhvâcârya’s Tattvasaükhyâna,

  The Enumeration of Reality (hereafter TS) and Tattvaviveka, The

  Delineation of Reality (hereafter TV). The TS has only eleven granthas

  while the TV has thirteen. These brief texts are part of Madhvâcârya’s

  daúaprakaraõa, ten minor philosophical texts, and they concern

  ontology.

  Later Mâdhvas have offered more detailed accounts of the categories

  that Madhvâcârya first described. Some are responses to criticisms of

  their taxonomy by the two rival schools of Vedânta and others attend

  to lacunae in Madhvâcârya’s original classifications. Most notably,

  Vedagarbha Padmanâbhâcârya composed an independent treatise on

  Mâdhva ontology called the Madhvasiddhântasâra, The Compendium

  of Established Truths of Mâdhva [Vedânta] (also known as the

  Padârthasaügraha, The Compendium of [Taxonomical] Categories)

  in the 18th century. Although other English introductions to Madhva

  Vedânta use Padmanâbhâcârya’s template, I do not, however, include

  his or other analyses, commentaries and taxonomies in my account

  because they explore debates about the extant concepts and are intended

  2 See Gough, Vaiúeshika Aphorisms of Kaõâda and Bahadur, The Wisdom of Vaisheshika for more on the Vaiúeùika tradition. See Larson, Classical Sâükhya for more on the Sâükhya tradition.

  65

  52

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  for advanced students rather than introductory ones. The TS and TV are

  sufficient for this introduction.

  Given the centrality of Viùõu to the Mâdhva ontology, I begin my

  summary at the bottom of the hierarchy. Leaving the most important for

  last, I first examine asvatantram, dependent entities, and then I turn to

  Viùõu, the only svatantra, independent entity.

  Asvatantram, dependent entities

  Madhvâcârya separates, tattva, all of reality, into svatantra, independent, and asvatantra, dependent, entities. The only independent entity is

  Viùõu. All other entities are asvatantra, dependent. 3 According to Professor B.N.K. Sharma, the Mâdhva school of Vedânta has been

  known as the ‘Dvaita,’ dualist, school because of the magnitude of

  this split between svatantra, independent, and paratantra, dependent entities (see Fig. 3.2).4

  tattva

  Viùõu/ svatantra

  avatantra

  3.2 Dvaita

  What makes entities dependent? On what or on whom are they

  dependent? Are they dependent on Viùõu for their creation? It is not

  surprising that Madhvâcârya holds that all entities are dependent on Viùõu.

  Not only do they require Viùõu for their existence but also, as I show, they
r />   require Him for their operation. Dependency is their nature, although

  many ignorant sentients are deluded and see themselves as independent.

  3 svatantram asvatantraü ca dvividhaü tattvam iùyate | svatantro bhagavân viùõur |

  TS 1. In his TV, Madhvâcârya refers to these asvatantra as paratantra, dependent on another. The difference between the two is only nominal. dvividhaü paratantraü ca bhâvo ‘bhâva itîritaþ | TV 2.

  4 Sharma, Philosophy, 323. I use the term ‘Mâdhva’ rather than ‘Dvaita’ because the latter is often misunderstood as referring to the number of items recognized in the

  Mâdhva universe, namely Viùõu and the jîvas. To avoid this misinterpretation I use

  ‘Mâdhva.’

  66

  Mâdhva Ontology

  53

  God did not create the material stuff of the universe ex nihilo, yet the

  material stuff is nonetheless dependent on Him. God is the efficient or

  instrumental cause, while prakçti, material stuff, is the material cause.

  In this way, the universe is dependent upon God who impels its

  development. Hence God is understood to be the only independent

  entity while all else is necessarily dependent. Dependency characterizes

  the relationship of all entities, sentient, eternal, or otherwise, with Viùõu

  and is the foundation of Mâdhva ontology and, as I show in Chapter 4,

  soteriology.

  Abhâva , non-existent entities

  Dependent entities are two-fold: bhâva, existent, and abhâva, non-

  existent entities.5 Madhvâcârya further subdivides abhâva, non-existent things, into three categories: prâg, prior, pradhvaüsa, posterior, and sadâ, always non-existent things (see Fig. 3.3).6

  asvatantra

  bhâva

  abhâva

  prâg

  pradhvaüsa

  sadâ

  3.3 Asvatantra

  Prâgabhâva, prior non-existence, is the non-existence of a substance

  before it comes into being. There is a prâgabhâva, an antecedent

  non-existence, of this sentence before I type it. Pradhvaüsâbhâva,

  posterior non-existence, is the non-existence of a substance after it is

  destroyed. The mug that shattered after you dropped it on the kitchen

  floor yesterday has been replaced by a pradhvaüsâbhâva. Things

  that are sadâbhâva, always non-existent, are entities like square circles,

  or the two examples used in South Asian philosophy, úaúaúçïga, the

  horn of a hare, and vandhyâputra, the son of a barren woman.

  5 ... bhâvâbhavau dvidhetarat | TS 1.

  6 prâkpradhvaüsasadâtvena trividho ‘bhâva iùyate | TS 2.

  67

  54

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  These are impossible entities and are sometimes called atyântâbhava,

  permanently non-existent.

  What does Madhvâcârya gain by this category? The cognition ‘The

  container is not there’ is actually ‘The non-existence of the container is

  there.’ Or, the cognition ‘This container has not water’ is actually two

  cognitions: ‘This container is there’ and ‘The absence of water is there.’

  In this way, abhâva explains the experience of negation.

  Bhâva , existent entities

  Madhvâcârya separates bhâva, existent entities, into those that are

  cetana, sentient and acetana, those that are not sentient. 7 Entities either think or are incapable of thinking. Following the order in which

  Madhvâcârya analyzes them, I address the sentient and then the non-

  sentient components of his ontology. As per the Mâdhva worldview,

  they are arranged hierarchically.

  Cetanas , sentient beings

  There are several types of cetanas, sentient beings, in the Mâdhva

  universe. Their position in the ontological hierarchy is determined by

  their ability, or lack thereof, to obtain mokùa, liberation, the ultimate and implicit goal to which all adherents aspire . Ontological components are

  directly linked to eschatological and soteriological matters. Just as a

  classroom has different kinds of students who can be divided according

  to their individual abilities and potentials, so too can the sentient

  denizens of the universe be divided. Given the importance of hierarchy

  in the Mâdhva universe, it should come as no surprise that cetanas are

  also hierarchically arranged. In fact, as I show in Chapter 4, status in mokùa is also graded, since some sentient beings experience more

  ânanada, bliss, in mokùa than others. These gradations, moreover, are inscribed in the fabric of the universe and are immutable.

  The taxonomy of sentient beings found in the TS is neither an a

  posteriori classification nor an arbitrary organization of data obtained

  by mere observation. Rank also cannot be altered in the way that

  students in remedial classes, through effort and merit, are able to change

  their status when they are enrolled in more advanced classes. Instead,

  the latent capabilities of sentient beings are determined a priori, cannot

  be altered and are part of the nature of the universe. This hierarchy

  strictly correlates a fixed ontology with an equally fixed eschatology

  7 cetanâcetanatvena bhâvo ‘pi dvividho mataþ | TS 2.

  68

  Mâdhva Ontology

  55

  and soteriology. The ability, or lack thereof, to attain mokùa, liberation,

  for all sentient beings is part of the predetermined nature of the Mâdhva

  universe. Knowing one’s place in the hierarchy is a central component in

  the path to mokùa.

  Sentient beings are two-fold: duþkhaspçùña, those who are connected

  with suffering, and tadaspçùña, those who are not. Ramâ is the only

  tadaspçùña jîva and is nityâduþkha, eternally without suffering (see

  Fig. 3.4).8

  bhâva

  cetana

  acetana

  duþkhaspçùña

  tadaspçùña (Úrî)

  3.4 Components of bhâva

  Ramâ is also known as Lakùmî and as Úrî. She is Viùõu’s consort and, as

  indicated above in Chapter 2, she is awarded special epistemological

  and ontological status. 9 Despite having such an exalted status in the Mâdhva pantheon, Úrî is nonetheless dependent upon Viùõu.

  Madhvâcârya devoted a portion of the seventh canto of his Dvâdaúa

  Stotra to salutations and praise of Úrî and in his Chândogya Upaniùad

  Bhâùya, he states that, despite being insignificant in comparison to

  Viùõu, the immortal goddess Úrî is the object of great love. 10 Though Madhvâcârya makes tadaspçùña part of his classification system, the

  category of sentient beings without suffering is comprised of only one

  member, namely Úrî, Viùõu’s consort.

  Sentient beings who are spçùña-duþkhas, connected with suffering,

  are two-fold: duþkha-saüsthas, those whose state of being is suffering,

  and vimuktas, those who are already liberated from suffering.11 V imuktas

  8 duþkhaspçùñam tadaspçùñam iti dvedhaiva cetanam | nityâduþkhâ ramâ ‘nye tu spçùñaduþkhâssamastaúaþ | TS 3.

  9 See Kumar’s The Goddess Lakùmî for further reading on Úrî.

  10 alpâpi hy amçta devî úrîþ pûrõâtipriyatvataþ iti ca | Chândogya Upaniùad Bhâùya, 7.26. Thanks to Siauve for this reference. Siauve, 343, nt. 2.

  11 spçùñaduþkhâ vimuktâú ca duþkhasaüsthâ iti dvidhâ | TS 4.

  69

 
56

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  are five-fold: devas, gods, çùis, seers, pitçs, ancestors, pa, protectors of the world, and naras, the highest among men. The duþkha-saüsthas are two-fold: the mukti-yogyas, those qualified for release who can be

  liberated from suffering and are comprised of the same five groups as

  the vimuktas, and the mukty-ayogyas, those who cannot be liberated

  from suffering. Only the mukti-yogyas are fit to be liberated from

  suffering and to achieve mokùa. 12 How does one obtain liberation from suffering? If cetanas are predestined to obtain mokùa, can they act however they wish? Do jîvas have an agency? I answer these and other

  questions in Chapter 4.

  According to Madhvâcârya, there are mukty-ayogyas, sentient beings

  that can never change their status and are eternally predestined to suffer.

  These sentient beings neither can be released from suffering, nor can

  they achieve mokùa. The mukty-ayogyas are also subdivided into tamo-yogyas, those who are fit only for darkness, and nitya-saüsârins,

  (literally, ‘those who remain in the journey’) those who are eternally

  caught in the cycle of birth and rebirth (see Fig. 3.5).13

  spçùña-duþkhas

  duþkha-saüsthas

  vimuktas

  devas çùis pitçs

  pa naras

  mukti-yogyas

  mukty-ayogyas

  devas çùis pitçs

  pa naras tamo-yogyas nitya-saüsârins

  3.5 Spçùña-duþkhas

  12 devarùipitçpanarâ iti muktâs tu pañcadhâ | evaü vimuktiyogyâú . . | TS 5.

  13 ... ca tamogâþ sçtisaüsthitâþ | TS, 5. The terms tamoyogyâþ and nityasaüsârin were first used by Jayatîrtha in his PP: ayoginaþ api trividhâþ | muktiyogyâþ nityasaüsâriõiþ tamoyogyâú ca iti | PP 19.

  70

  Mâdhva Ontology

  57

  Tamo-yogyas, those fit for darkness, are proclaimed to be four-fold: the

  daityas, demons, the râkùasas, orcs, the piúacas, ghastly lurkers, and the martyâdhamas, vilest of the mortals.14 Tamo-yogyas are two-fold: prâptâdhatamasas, those who suffer in complete darkness, and

  sçtisaüsthitâs, those whose way to darkness is through saüsâra (see

  Fig. 3.6).15 Some are thus born in a place of suffering and some

  eventually are reborn in such places. Madhvâcârya thus proposes a time

  frame for some of these vilest to exhibit their vile behavior and, in due

  course, to suffer in darkness!

  tamo-yogyas

  prâptâdhatamasas

 

‹ Prev