Why People Die By Suicide

Home > Other > Why People Die By Suicide > Page 15
Why People Die By Suicide Page 15

by Thomas Joiner


  adolescents would be rated higher on a measure of expendability

  than would be a psychiatric control group. The expendability mea-

  sure specifically included a sense of being a burden on one’s family.

  Results conformed to predictions: Suicidal youth scored higher on

  the expendability measure than did a psychiatric comparison group.

  Studies of youth like this one suggest that the concept of burden-

  someness may affect a broad range of ages. Related to feeling a bur-

  den on one’s family, suicide attempts among children have been

  The Desire for Death ● 111

  linked to perceived inability to meet parental demands.42 Again, the

  emphasis on the term perceived bears repeating; the facile explanation that parents are responsible for their children’s death by suicide

  because of high demands is hardly worth considering. However, the

  explanation that people who perceive themselves as not measuring

  up and as being a burden are prone to suicidal behavior is more seri-

  ous and is supported by numerous research studies.

  The potential importance of perceived burdensomeness emerged

  in a study of low-income, abused African-American women. This

  study identified protective and risk factors that differentiated suicide

  attempters from those who had never made an attempt. Protective

  factors associated with nonattempter status included self-efficacy as

  well as effectiveness in obtaining material resources.43 In the current

  framework, these results could be viewed as suggesting that those

  who feel effective in general, as well as effective in providing material

  resources in particular, are buffered from feeling a burden and thus

  at relatively low risk for suicidality.44

  Data on suicide in the Netherlands in the early twentieth century

  are in accord with a role for perceived burdensomeness as well. A

  higher suicide rate in rural as compared to urban areas was noted

  and was attributed to “the peculiar conditions of the Dutch farming

  system under which the aged find themselves a burden,”45 an experi-

  ence not shared by older Dutch people in the cities.

  One implication of the burdensomeness view is that suicides may

  be more common during difficult economic times; when resources

  are strained, the consequences of perceived burdensomeness may

  be more acute (for example, the socially sanctioned suicide among

  the Yuit Eskimos of St. Lawrence Island outlined earlier in this chap-

  ter). Other data support this view. A significant association between

  deprivation and the suicide rate in thirty-two London boroughs

  has been documented. This study is unique in contemporaneously

  studying closely contiguous and roughly culturally homogenous ar-

  112 ● WHY PEOPLE DIE BY SUICIDE

  eas that nevertheless vary with regard to socioeconomic variables

  and suicide rate.46 Several others have reached the conclusion that

  economic prosperity has a beneficial impact and economic down-

  turns a detrimental effect on suicide rates.47 In a study of suicide in

  African-American men, the risk of suicide was higher in areas where

  occupational and income inequalities between African-Americans

  and Caucasians were greater.48 At the individual level, too, several

  studies have found that financial hardship constitutes a risk factor

  for suicide.49

  Suicidal Behavior in an Evolutionary Context

  Some believe that suicidal behavior must have conferred some bene-

  fit in the course of evolution, in part because it is common across

  cultures today. But how would a behavior that leads to pain, impair-

  ment, and death produce any sort of increased ability to pass on

  one’s genes?

  According to DeCatanzaro’s50 model of self-preservation and self-

  destruction, there are conditions under which death may produce an

  adaptive advantage. Specifically, death may produce an evolutionary

  edge for an individual who has few prospects for reproduction and

  who poses such a burden to close kin—who carry his or her genes—

  that it reduces their prospects for reproduction.

  For any case for adaptive benefit to be made, a lot of compelling

  evidence would need to be marshalled (and even then, as I will point

  out, questions will remain). For example, if suicidal behavior is an

  exclusively human phenomenon not occurring in other primates and

  animals, then the case for evolved behavior becomes more difficult.

  If, by contrast, suicidal behavior is documented in primates and

  other animals, the case is not made, but it may become a little easier

  to imagine.

  Is suicidal behavior an exclusively human phenomenon? Many

  presume it to be so. For example, the promotional material for

  The Desire for Death ● 113

  Shneidman’s The Suicidal Mind 51 makes the claim that “suicide is an exclusively human response to extreme psychological pain.” In Conceptions of Modern Psychiatry, the American psychiatrist Harry Stack Sullivan stated, “So far as we know, there is nothing remotely approaching [suicide] in the infrahuman primates or any of the lower

  animals. It is a distinctly human performance.”52

  The most famous possible case—lemmings dying by mass suicide

  in a kind of intentional population control effort—is not really a

  case at all. Lemmings do die en masse, but this is because they mi-

  grate en masse after they exhaust their food source—a type of slow-

  growing moss—and many die in the hardship and chaos of the mi-

  gration.

  Still, Shneidman and Sullivan may have been wrong in thinking

  that suicide is an exclusively human phenomenon. Perhaps the clear-

  est examples of animal suicidal behavior involve a phenomenon

  dubbed “adaptive suicide” in insects and possibly in birds. For in-

  stance, researchers have studied pea aphids, which are parasitized by

  a specific species of wasp.53 The wasp injects an egg into the host

  aphid; the young wasp matures inside the aphid, feeding upon its or-

  gans. When the wasp is ready to emerge as an adult, it chews a hole

  out the back of the aphid’s body. Aphid populations can be devas-

  tated by parasitic wasps.

  Recall that DeCatanzaro theorized that self-sacrifice carries sur-

  vival value for an individual who has few prospects for reproduction

  and who poses such a burden to close kin—who carry his or her

  genes—that it reduces their prospects for reproduction. The parasitized pea aphid could be viewed as just such an individual—prospects

  for reproduction are few, because death is imminent; a potential bur-

  den is posed to close kin, because the parasite wasp will live on to in-

  fect other pea aphids. Aphids parasitized early in development, and

  who thus would not produce any offspring, frequently engage in a

  kind of “aphid suicide”—specifically, they drop from their host plant

  114 ● WHY PEOPLE DIE BY SUICIDE

  to the ground, where they are frequently preyed on by ladybugs and

  other natural predators.

  Worker bumblebees parasitized by a specific species of fly will of-

  ten abandon their nest altogether, cutting themselves off from the

  hive and ensuring their death. The bees’ behavior can be see
n as an

  instance of adaptive suicide because the parasitized bee’s premature

  death kills the parasite and avoids its spread in the bee colony.54

  A similar phenomenon may affect birds. Under famine conditions,

  evolutionary pressures may select for behaviors like fratricide (one

  member of a brood killing its sibling), infanticide (a parent killing

  the offspring), and suicide (by the nestling with the shortest life ex-

  pectancy, which abandons the nest prematurely).55 This kind of self-

  sacrifice is sort of what Durkheim had in mind (though from an en-

  tirely different perspective) when he wrote about altruistic suicide,

  which he defined as self-sacrifice for the good of the group. A key

  difference, however, is that adaptive suicide takes place not for the

  good of the group, but for the good of one’s own genes.

  Perhaps an even clearer example of self-sacrifice for the good of

  one’s genes occurs in the Australian redback spider. Male redback

  spiders submit to being cannibalized by females after sex. They do

  so apparently because they thereby gain advantages in the competi-

  tion for females: Cannibalized males copulate longer and fertilize

  more eggs as compared to males that survive copulation. Also, female

  redbacks are more likely to reject subsequent males after consuming

  their first mate.56 Self-sacrifice has been selected for in the course of

  male redback spider evolution.

  Self-injurious behavior has been documented in nonhuman pri-

  mates; most studies are on rhesus monkeys. The form of their self-

  injury is usually self-biting—at times of distress, some monkeys will

  bite their arms or legs, sometimes causing injury. This body of re-

  search suggests that self-injury in nonhuman primates is a way to

  self-regulate at times of stress (e.g., accelerated heart rate decreases

  when the behavior is enacted). Animals with early stress experiences

  The Desire for Death ● 115

  are vulnerable to the behavior, suggesting that these early experiences

  disrupted the development of more normal stress-regulation abili-

  ties. Self-injury as a means to regulate emotions has been docu-

  mented in humans too, of course, particularly among those with

  borderline personality disorder.

  Apart from adaptive suicide in insects, birds, and spiders, there

  is very little evidence of death by suicide in animals. There is at least

  one claim that dogs sometimes die by suicide—by drowning or by

  food refusal in response to being cast out of a household or re-

  morse57—but this assertion would need more systematic scientific

  support before it is given much credence.

  I said earlier that I believe suicidal people are mistaken when they

  view themselves as burdens. An adaptive suicide viewpoint would

  suggest otherwise—specifically, that suicidal behavior evolved in hu-

  mans to remove actual (not just perceived) burdens from kin and

  thus facilitate kin’s survival. In fact, when researchers interviewed the

  significant others of eighty-one people who had recently attempted

  suicide, a majority of significant others reported that their support of

  the patient represented a burden to them.58

  Nevertheless, I do not much like this adaptive suicide view; my

  own dad died by suicide and the idea that he was an actual burden

  is offensive. My view is that self-sacrifice is adaptive in some ani-

  mal species. It may have been adaptive under certain conditions in

  the course of human evolution, but we will never really know. Most

  important, it does not really matter now. What matters now is that

  perceived burdensomeness—and, to the extent that it exists, actual

  burdensomeness—are remediable through perception- and skill-based

  psychotherapies. Death is no longer adaptive, if it ever was.

  A Note on Life Insurance

  Perceived burdensomeness implies a kind of calculation along the

  lines of, “my death will be more valuable to others than my life.” It is

  interesting to consider the issue of life insurance in this regard. The

  116 ● WHY PEOPLE DIE BY SUICIDE

  usual life insurance policy will pay for death by suicide provided that

  the death occurs two years or more after the initiation of the policy.

  If the death occurs before two years have passed, a usual practice is

  that premiums plus interest are returned, but the policy is not paid.

  If people are considering suicide and they imagine that their death

  will confer benefits to loved ones, then life insurance could enter into

  suicidal people’s thinking. A higher benefit could conceivably en-

  courage suicide. It would be interesting to know the percentage of

  those who die by suicide with life insurance versus the percentage of

  those who die by other means with life insurance. Any comparison

  like this should adjust for demographics, which are very different be-

  tween those who die by suicide versus those who die by other means.

  One way to do this would be to limit comparisons to one ethnicity

  and age range, say, white men over fifty. If, after such adjustments,

  more suicides are insured, it would suggest that life insurance possi-

  bly figured into the calculations made by suicidal people. It would

  only be suggestive, though, because other factors could have influ-

  enced the data. Perhaps a personality variable like lack of optimism

  would explain both the tendency to take out life insurance policies

  and a tendency toward suicidal behavior.

  Perhaps not surprisingly, data on this issue are hard to come by. In

  the 1920s and 1930s, Metropolitan Life paid out more life insurance

  money per claim on suicide versus other deaths, though it was not

  clear that this was corrected for gender and ethnicity. The figures in

  1925 were $2,283 (suicide) versus $1,867 (nonsuicide). In 1931, the

  respective figures were $3,580 versus $2,216.59 These numbers are ob-

  viously quite dated, but suicide often remains the most expensive

  category of death for life insurance companies today.

  As with the findings related to the acquired ability to enact lethal

  self-injury, alternative explanations exist for some of the results link-

  ing perceived burdensomeness to suicidality (e.g., the studies on in-

  creased suicide in difficult economic times are amenable to many in-

  The Desire for Death ● 117

  terpretations). Relatively few studies have explicitly tested the specific

  role of perceived burdensomeness in suicidality. On the positive side,

  every study specifically examining burdensomeness and suicidality

  had stringent features, and each produced results supportive of the

  role of burdensomeness in serious suicidality. As with the findings on

  acquired ability to enact lethal self-injury, the results reviewed on

  burdensomeness were from a wide array of topic areas, samples, and

  methodologies. That such diverse data are at least consistent with the

  parsimonious construct of perceived burdensomeness inspires some

  confidence in its role in suicidality.

  The current model asserts that to perceive oneself as so ineffective

  that loved ones are threatened and burdened is a so
urce for the desire

  for suicide. Perceived burdensomeness, not actual burdensomeness, is the key variable in this account. Empirical data to date, including

  studies explicitly testing this assertion, are supportive. Assuming the

  capability for suicide, perceived burdensomeness removes one of the

  two key barriers to suicide. Even for a person who has acquired the

  capability for suicide and perceives him- or herself to be a burden,

  there remains one “saving grace”—belongingness. In my view, if the

  need to belong is satisfied, the will to live remains intact.

  Thwarted Connectedness: The Sense that One Does Not Belong

  William James, in The Principles of Psychology (1890), wrote, “No

  more fiendish punishment could be devised, were such a thing physi-

  cally possible, than that one should be turned loose in society and

  remain absolutely unnoticed by all the members thereof. If no one

  turned around when we entered, answered when we spoke, or

  minded what we did, but if every person we met ‘cut us dead,’ and

  acted as if we were non-existent things, a kind of rage and impotent

  despair would before long well up in us, from which the cruelest

  bodily torture would be a relief.” I think James’s use of the phrase

  118 ● WHY PEOPLE DIE BY SUICIDE

  “cut us dead” is telling, as is the insight that bodily torture can, under

  some circumstances, be a relief.

  The need to belong is a fundamental human motive. When this

  need is thwarted, numerous negative effects on health, adjustment,

  and well-being have been documented. It is interesting to note that

  the pain of thwarted belongingness may activate similar brain areas

  as physical pain. It has long been known that a brain center called

  the anterior cingulate cortex is important for the processing of physi-

  cal pain signals. Eisenberger and colleagues60 obtained brain scans

  of undergraduates as they played “cyberball.” “Cyberball” is a com-

  puterized ball-tossing game. Participants believed they were playing

  with two other players, and during the game, the two players ex-

  cluded the participant. In reality, there were no other players; partici-

  pants were playing with a preset computer program.

  If someone is in a brain scan machine and receives a pain stimu-

  lus, the scan will show activity in the anterior cingulate cortex. Simi-

 

‹ Prev