The Big Picture

Home > Other > The Big Picture > Page 18
The Big Picture Page 18

by Carroll, Sean M.

14

  putationally cumbersome. There tends to be a trade-off between compre-

  15

  hensiveness of a theory and its practicality.

  16

  Our ability to construct two different theories about the air in your

  17

  room, once as a fluid and another time as a collection of molecules, is an

  18

  especially concrete and vivid example of emergence, and more generally of

  19

  the poetic- naturalist idea of telling multiple stories about the same underly-

  20

  ing reality. There are, as you might guess, some subtleties worth exploring.

  21

  22

  •

  23

  One of the features of the molecules/ fluid example is that we can derive the

  24

  macroscopic fluid theory from the microscopic molecular theory. That is,

  25

  we can start with the molecules, assume that there is a high density of mol-

  26

  ecules at every point in space, and then “smooth out” the distribution to

  27

  obtain explicit formulas for fluid properties such as pressure and tempera-

  28

  ture in terms of what the molecules are doing. This is what is meant by

  29

  “ coarse- graining” above.

  30

  Sneakily, however, we have taken advantage of a very special feature

  31

  of kinetic theory, one that doesn’t readily extend to other situations we

  32

  might be interested in. At heart, the molecules in the air are simple objects,

  33

  mindlessly bumping into one another when they pass through the same

  34

  point in space. All we’re really doing to derive the fluid description is

  S35

  N36

  99

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 99

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  calculating the average properties of all the molecules. The average number

  02

  of molecules gives us the density, the average energy gives us the tempera-

  03

  ture, the average momentum moving in different directions gives us the

  04

  pressure, and so on.

  05

  We can’t take such features for granted. Quantum mechanics, in par-

  06

  ticular, features the phenomenon of entanglement. It’s not possible to spec-

  07

  ify the state of a system by listing the state of all of its subsystems

  08

  individually; we have to look at the system as a whole, because different

  09

  parts of it can be entangled with one another. To dig a bit deeper, when we

  10

  combine quantum mechanics with gravity, it is widely believed (although

  11

  not known for certain, since we know almost nothing for certain about

  12

  quantum gravity) that space itself is emergent rather than fundamental.

  13

  Then it doesn’t even make sense to talk about “a location in space” as a

  14

  fundamental concept.

  15

  We needn’t ascend to esoteric realms of quantum gravity to find situa-

  16

  tions in which a straightforward smoothing- out process isn’t enough to

  17

  take us from a microscopic theory to an emergent one. Perhaps we want to

  18

  have a theory of the human brain that emerges out of the behavior of many

  19

  neurons. Or a theory of a single neuron that emerges out of the interactions

  20

  of the molecules of which it is made. The problem is that both neurons

  21

  and the complicated organic molecules in each neuron are pretty complex

  22

  in their own right; their behavior depends in subtle ways on the specific

  23

  inputs they are receiving from their environments. Simply averaging over

  24

  all of them in some region isn’t going to capture all of that subtlety. That’s

  25

  not to say that there can’t be a useful emergent theory, with a many-to-one

  26

  map from neuron states to brain states, or molecular states to neuron states;

  27

  it’s just that obtaining it is going to be a bit more indirect than it was for the

  28

  air in our room.

  29

  The molecular and fluid descriptions of air in a room provide an inno-

  30

  cent, uncontroversial example of emergence. Everyone agrees on what is

  31

  happening and how to talk about it. But its simplicity can be misleading.

  32

  Seeing how relatively easy it is to derive fluid mechanics from molecules,

  33

  one can get the idea that deriving one theory from another is what emer-

  34

  gence is all about. It’s not— emergence is about different theories speaking

  35S

  different languages, but offering compatible descriptions of the same under-

  36N

  lying phenomena in their respective domains of applicability. If a

  100

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 100

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  R E A l I t y E M E R g E S

  macroscopic theory has a domain of applicability that is a subset of the

  01

  domain of applicability of some microscopic theory, and both theories are

  02

  consistent, then the microscopic theory can be said to entail the macro-

  03

  scopic one; but that’s often something we take for granted, not something

  04

  that can explicitly be demonstrated. The ability to actually go through the

  05

  steps to derive one theory from another is great when it happens, but not at

  06

  all crucial to the idea.

  07

  08

  •

  09

  As systems evolve through time, perhaps in response to changes in their

  10

  external environment, they can pass from the domain of applicability of

  11

  one kind of emergent description to a different one— what’s known as a

  12

  phase transition. Water is the most familiar example. Depending on the

  13

  temperature and pressure, water can find itself in the form of solid ice, liq-

  14

  uid water, or gaseous water vapor. The underlying microscopic description

  15

  remains the same— molecules of H O— but the macroscopic properties

  16

  2

  shift from one “phase” to another. Because of the different conditions, the

  17

  way that we talk about the water changes: the density, hardness, speed of

  18

  sound through the medium, and other characteristics of the water can be

  19

  completely altered, and our vocabulary changes along with them. (You

  20

  wouldn’t talk about pouring a block of ice, or chipping a cup of liquid water.) 21

  22

  23

  Heat being added

  24

  gas

  25

  boiling

  26

  perature

 
27

  mTe

  liquid

  28

  29

  melting

  30

  31

  solid

  32

  Time

  33

  34

  How water changes phase from solid to liquid to gas, as heat is added to it and the temperature rises. The melting and boiling points exhibit plateaus; here the internal structure S35

  of the molecules is being rearranged, even though the temperature remains fixed.

  N36

  101

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 101

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  The way that phase transitions actually occur is a subject of endless fas-

  02

  cination to scientists. Some transitions are rapid, some are slow; some

  03

  change the substance utterly, others represent a more gradual evolution. The

  04

  figure illustrates one interesting feature of phase transitions: not all changes

  05

  are visible on the surface. As we add heat to water, it goes from ice to liquid

  06

  to vapor, and the temperature rises along the way. At the precise transition

  07

  point, there is a period where the temperature remains constant while the

  08

  molecular structure of the water is being rearranged. Entirely new physical

  09

  properties can come into existence as we change phases, such as solidity or

  10

  transparency or electrical conductivity. Or life, or consciousness.

  11

  When we’re talking about simple molecular systems, it’s often possible

  12

  to pinpoint precisely what kind of theoretical vocabulary is appropriate, as

  13

  well as where we transition from one phase to another. The boundary lines

  14

  become fuzzier when we start discussing biology or human interactions,

  15

  but the same basic ideas apply. We’ve all witnessed phase transitions in the

  16

  mood of a roomful of people, when someone says the right (or wrong)

  17

  thing, or when a new person enters the dynamic. Here is a partial list of

  18

  important phase transitions in the history of the cosmos:

  19

  20

  • The formation of protons and neutrons out of quarks and

  21

  gluons in the early universe.

  22

  • Electrons combining with atomic nuclei to make atoms, sev-

  23

  eral hundred thousand years after the Big Bang.

  24

  • The formation of the first stars, filling the universe with new

  25

  light.

  26

  • The origin of life: a self- sustaining complex chemical reaction.

  27

  • Multicellularity, when different living organisms merged to

  28

  become one.

  29

  • Consciousness: the awareness of self and the ability to form

  30

  mental representations of the universe.

  31

  • The origin of language and the ability to construct and share

  32

  abstract thoughts.

  33

  • The invention of machines and technology.

  34

  35S

  There are phase transitions in the realm of ideas as well as that of mate-

  36N

  rials. Philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn popularized the idea of a

  102

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 102

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  R E A l I t y E M E R g E S

  “paradigm shift” to describe how new theories could induce scientists to

  01

  conceptualize the world in starkly different ways. Even an individual per-

  02

  son changing their mind about something can be thought of as a phase

  03

  transition: our best way of talking about that person is now different. Peo-

  04

  ple, like water, can exhibit plateaus in their thinking, where outwardly they

  05

  hold the same beliefs but inwardly their mental gears are gradually turning.

  06

  07

  •

  08

  The fact that each theory or way of talking works only within a specified

  09

  domain of applicability is absolutely crucial. Again, the example of air is a

  10

  simple one, but perhaps so simple that it lulls us into a false sense of com-

  11

  placency.

  12

  Even though we think of the air in the room as “really” being made of

  13

  various molecules, that theory’s domain of applicability fails to include

  14

  some situations, such as when the density becomes so high that the air

  15

  would collapse into a black hole. (Not to worry, that’s far removed from the

  16

  physical situation in most rooms you will find yourself in.) But the fluid

  17

  description also fails in those cases. In fact, the domain of applicability of

  18

  the emergent fluid theory is a strict subset of the domain of applicability of

  19

  the molecular theory.

  20

  21

  22

  The Universe

  The Universe

  The Universe

  23

  Theory 1

  24

  Theory

  Theory

  Theory

  Theory

  Theory

  25

  1

  2

  1

  2

  2

  26

  27

  28

  How domains of applicability of different theories could relate to each other.

  29

  30

  That situation— two ways of talking, one of whose domain of applica-

  31

  bility fits inside that of the other— is by no means necessary. In the diagram,

  32

  we have shown various ways that domains of applicability might fit to-

  33

  gether. One might be a subset of the other; or the two might be distinct but

  34

  overlapping; or they could just be completely different, not sharing any

  S35

  situations in common. For example, in string theory, a leading candidate

  N36

  103

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 103

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  for a quantum theory of gravity, there are “duality relations” between theo-

  02

  ries that leave us in the middle situation, where we have two theories with

  03

  overlapping domains of applicability.

  04

  Another example— controversially— might be human consciousness.

  05

  People are made of particles, and we have a successful picture of how indi-

  06

  vidual particles behave, the Core Theory we’ll discuss more in chapter 22.

  07

  You might think that we could fully describe a person if only we knew the

  08

  complete state of all of their particles. We have every reason to believe that
<
br />   09

  the domain of applicability of particle physics includes the particles that

  10

  make up human beings. But it’s possible, however unlikely, that there is one

  11

  set of rules obeyed by particles when there are only a handful of them inter-

  12

  acting with one another, as studied by particle physicists, and a slightly dif-

  13

  ferent set of rules that they obey when they come together to make a person.

  14

  This is called strong emergence, which we’ll discuss in the next chapter.

  15

  There’s no direct evidence that this is true for human beings, but it might

  16

  help you avoid the ramifications of having all of human behavior described

  17

  in principle by the known rules of particle physics, if those are the kinds of

  18

  ramifications you find unpleasant.

  19

  These non- hierarchical domains of applicability are not the situation we

  20

  most often encounter in discussions of emergence. It is far more common

  21

  to find situations like the leftmost one in the diagram, where one theory is

  22

  appropriate in a subset of the domain of another theory, perhaps in a nested

  23

  chain of multiple theories. Indeed, this is closest to the notion of a “hierar-

  24

  chy of sciences,” introduced by French philosopher Auguste Comte in the

  25

  nineteenth century. In this view, we start with physics at the most micro-

  26

  scopic and comprehensive level; out of that emerges chemistry, and then

  27

  biology, and then psychology, and finally sociology.

  28

  It is this hierarchical picture that leads people to talk about “levels”

  29

  when they discuss emergence. Lower levels are more microscopic, fine-

  30

  grained descriptions, while higher levels are more macroscopic and coarse-

  31

  grained. That can be convenient when it happens, but what matters is not

  32

  the existence of a hierarchy but the existence of different ways of talking

  33

  that describe the same underlying world, and are compatible with each

  34

  other when their domains of applicability overlap.

  35S

  36N

  104

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 104

  20/07/2016 10:02:42

  01

  02

  13

  03

  04

  What Exists, and What Is Illusion?

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  A

  13

  uguste Comte helped coin the term “sociology,” and put it at the

  14

  top of his pyramid of science; he thought of the study of societies

  15

 

‹ Prev