The Big Picture

Home > Other > The Big Picture > Page 55
The Big Picture Page 55

by Carroll, Sean M.


  22

  you as your conscious perceptions. Typically, what you experience as “now”

  23

  corresponds to what was actually happening some tens or hundreds of mil-

  24

  liseconds in the past.

  25

  Estonian- Canadian psychologist Endel Tulving suggested the term

  26

  chronesthesia, or “mental time travel.” One of Tulving’s contributions was

  27

  the distinction between two different kinds of memory: semantic memory,

  28

  which refers to general knowledge (Gettysburg was the site of an important

  29

  battle in the American Civil War), and episodic memory, which captures

  30

  our recollection of personal experiences (I visited Gettysburg when I was in

  31

  high school). Mental time travel, Tulving suggested, is related to episodic

  32

  memory: imagining the future is a similar conscious activity to recalling

  33

  events in the past.

  34

  Recent work in neuroscience has lent credence to this idea. Researchers

  S35

  have been able to use functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) and

  N36

  323

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 323

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  positron emission tomography (PET) scans to pinpoint regions in the brain

  02

  that are active while subjects are conducting various mental tasks. Interest-

  03

  ingly, the tasks of “remember yourself in a particular situation in the past”

  04

  and “imagine yourself in a particular hypothetical situation in the future”

  05

  are seen to engage a very similar set of subsystems in the brain. Episodic

  06

  memory and imagination engage the same neural machinery.

  07

  Memories of past experiences, it turns out, are not like a video or film

  08

  recording of an event, with individual sounds and images stored for each

  09

  moment. What’s stored is more like a script. When we remember a past

  10

  event, the brain pulls out the script and puts on a little performance of the

  11

  sights and sounds and smells. Part of the brain stores the script, while oth-

  12

  ers are responsible for the stage settings and props. This helps explain why

  13

  memories can be completely false, yet utterly vivid and real- seeming to us—

  14

  the brain can put on a convincing show from an incorrect script just as well

  15

  as an accurate one. It also helps explain how our chronesthetic ability to

  16

  imagine future events might have developed through natural selection.

  17

  Evolution, always looking to work with existing materials, constructed our

  18

  powers of imagination out of our existing capacity to remember the past.

  19

  While a capacity for mental time travel is important for some aspects of

  20

  consciousness, it certainly isn’t the whole story. Kent Cochrane was an am-

  21

  nesiac, famous in the psychology literature as the patient “K. C.” When he

  22

  was thirty years old, K. C. suffered a serious motorcycle accident. He sur-

  23

  vived, but during surgery he lost parts of his brain, including the hippocam-

  24

  pus, and his medial temporal lobes were severely damaged. Afterward, he

  25

  retained his semantic memory but completely lost his episodic memory. His

  26

  ability to form new memories was almost completely absent, much like the

  27

  character of Leonard Shelby in the movie Memento. K. C. knew that he

  28

  owned a particular car, but had no recollection of ever driving in it. His

  29

  basic mental capacities were intact, and he had no trouble carrying on

  30

  a conversation. He just couldn’t remember anything he had ever seen

  31

  or done.

  32

  There’s little question that K. C. was “conscious” in some sense. He

  33

  was awake, aware, and knew who he was. But consistent with the connec-

  34

  tion between memory and imagination, K. C. was completely unable to

  35S

  contemplate his own future. When asked about what would happen tomor-

  36N

  row or even later that day, he would simply report that it was blank. His

  32 4

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 324

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  C R AW l I n g I n t O C O n S C I Ou S n E S S

  personality underwent a significant change after the accident. He had, in

  01

  some sense, become a different person.

  02

  There is some evidence that episodic memory doesn’t develop in chil-

  03

  dren until they are about four years old, around the time they also seem to

  04

  develop the capacity for modeling the mental states of other people. At

  05

  younger ages, for example, children can learn new things, but they have

  06

  trouble associating new knowledge with any particular event; when quizzed

  07

  about something they just learned, they will claim that they have always

  08

  known it. Tulving has argued that true episodic memory, and the associated

  09

  capacity for imagination and mental time travel, might be unique to hu-

  10

  mans. It’s an intriguing hypothesis, but the current state of the art doesn’t

  11

  let us say for sure. We know that rats, for example, after trying and failing

  12

  to reach some food, will continue to think about how to reach it after the

  13

  food has been removed, which might be interpreted as a kind of planning.

  14

  Their mental activity involves the hippocampus, which is associated with

  15

  episodic memory in humans. Our ability to imagine the future is incredibly

  16

  detailed and rich, but it’s not hard to imagine how it might have evolved

  17

  gradually over the span of many generations.

  18

  19

  •

  20

  There’s so much we don’t know about the development of consciousness, it’s

  21

  easy to be dubious of any particular theory. Was crawling out of the water

  22

  and onto land a pivotal step along the way, as Malcolm MacIver suggests,

  23

  or is that just another fish story?

  24

  We should be skeptical; that’s our job. There are aquatic animals that

  25

  seem to be much smarter than your average goldfish. Whales and dolphins,

  26

  of course, but those are mammals that descended from land animals— so

  27

  their intelligence actually provides evidence for the hypothesis, not against

  28

  it. Octopuses are quite intelligent by many standards. T
hey have the biggest

  29

  brains of any invertebrate (animals without spinal cords), although still

  30

  only about one- thousandth the number of neurons that a human has. An

  31

  octopus might not be able to do crossword puzzles, but it can solve certain

  32

  simple challenges, such as opening a jar to get at food that’s inside.

  33

  MacIver notes that octopuses, while underwater creatures, seem to max-

  34

  imize the extent of their sensory capacities. They have very large eyes, and

  S35

  tend to remain still while executing complex tasks. It’s dangerous being an

  N36

  325

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 325

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  octopus; from the point of view of a predatory sea- dweller, you are a vulner-

  02

  able bag of delicious nutrients. To survive, they have had to develop innova-

  03

  tive defensive strategies, camouflaging themselves by changing skin color

  04

  and emitting clouds of ink when forced to flee. Intelligence is a part of that

  05

  defensive arsenal; an octopus will hide among rocks and coral when it

  06

  sleeps, often arranging pieces so as to better shield itself from view. Perhaps

  07

  the evolutionary pressure that led to large octopus brains was of a com-

  08

  pletely different type from that which led to land- dwelling animals.

  09

  Whatever the importance of climbing onto land might have been, it did

  10

  not lead immediately to animals that could write sonnets and prove math-

  11

  ematical theorems. Four hundred million years is a long time. The evolution

  12

  of consciousness as we now know it took many steps. Chimpanzees can

  13

  think and execute a plan, such as building a structure in order to get to a

  14

  banana that is out of reach. That’s a kind of imaginative thought, though

  15

  certainly not the whole story.

  16

  We can conceive of many moments in the evolutionary history of con-

  17

  sciousness ultimately leading to the exquisite complexity of our current

  18

  mental capacities. As the reducibly complex mousetrap reminds us, we

  19

  shouldn’t let the intimidating sophistication of the final product trick us

  20

  into thinking that it couldn’t have come about via numerous small steps.

  21

  22

  23

  24

  25

  26

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  35S

  36N

  32 6

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 326

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  01

  02

  38

  03

  04

  The Babbling Brain

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  I

  13

  t’s an image familiar from countless TV hospital dramas: the patient

  14

  lying on their back, head placed inside an intimidating- looking medi-

  15

  cal apparatus meant to peer inside their brain. Most often it will be an

  16

  MRI machine, which will produce beautiful images of brain activity by

  17

  tracking the flow of blood. In my case it was an MEG machine: magneto-

  18

  encephalography. By measuring the appearance of magnetic fields just out-

  19

  side my skull, this beast was going to test whether or not I had a brain, and

  20

  whether my brain could indeed have thoughts.

  21

  I passed. I like to think the outcome wasn’t really in doubt, but it’s good

  22

  to have these things verified by science.

  23

  My brain scan was carried out by neuroscientist David Poeppel in his lab

  24

  at New York University. Unlike fMRI, which makes beautiful pictures but

  25

  doesn’t have great time resolution, MEG isn’t very good at telling you where

  26

  processes are located in the brain, but it can distinguish when they happen

  27

  down to a few milliseconds.

  28

  That’s important, because our brains are intricately connected multi-

  29

  level systems that take time to do their work. Individual neural events hap-

  30

  pen several times per millisecond, but it takes tens of milliseconds for

  31

  several of them to accumulate to sufficient strength for your brain to sit up

  32

  and say, “Hey! Something’s happening!”— a conscious perception.

  33

  In the brain, most of the hard work of thinking is done by the neurons.

  34

  They are joined by glial cells, which help support and protect the neurons.

  S35

  Glial cells may play a role in how neurons talk to one another, but the

  N36

  327

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 327

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  Isofield Contour Map

  02

  L

  R

  03

  04

  05

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  Sink Source

  13

  20 fT/Step

  14

  15

  A map of the magnetic fields just outside my brain, generated by listening to

  a beeping sound. (Courtesy of David Poeppel lab, New York University)

  16

  17

  18

  information- carrying signals in the brain are carried by the neurons. A

  19

  typical neuron will come equipped with two types of appendages: a large

  20

  number of dendrites, which receive signals from outside, and (usually just

  21

  one) axon, down which signals are sent. The body of a neuron is less than a

  22

  tenth of a millimeter across, but axons can range from one millimeter all

  23

  the way up to a full meter long. When a neuron wants to send a signal, it

  24

  “fires” by pumping an electrochemical signal down its axon. That signal is

  25

  received by other neurons at connection points known as synapses. Most

  26

  synapses consist of a dendrite connecting to an axon, but the brain is a

  27

  messy place, so various other kinds of connections are possible.

  28

  So neurons talk to each other by squirting electrically charged mole-

  29

  cules from the axon of one to a dendrite on another. As any physicist will

  30

  tell you, charged particles in motion generate magnetic fields. When ar />
  31

  thought happens in my brain, this corresponds to charged particles hop-

  32

  ping between neurons, creating a faint magnetic field that extends just a bit

  33

  outside my skull. By detecting these magnetic fields, an MEG machine can

  34

  pinpoint exactly when my neurons do their firing.

  35S

  Poeppel and his colleagues are using this technique to study perception,

  36N

  cognition, and the workings of language in the brain. Sitting there in the

  32 8

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 328

  20/07/2016 10:02:52

  t h E b A b b l I n g b R A I n

  MEG, I listened to various meaningless beeps and boops, and the techni-

  01

  cian was able to track how long it took before I consciously perceived the

  02

  auditory signal as a sound— tens of milliseconds, in a cascade of interre-

  03

  lated cortical responses.

  04

  I was most impressed by something much more prosaic— these probes

  05

  attached to my skull could sense me thinking. What we call a “thought” cor-

  06

  responds directly and unmistakably to the motion of certain charged par-

  07

  ticles inside my head. That’s an amazing, humbling fact about how the

  08

  universe works. What would Descartes and Princess Elisabeth have thought?

  09

  Very few people today would deny that thinking is somehow related to

  10

  what goes on in the brain. The divide is between those who believe that

  11

  “thinking” is just a way of talking about the physical processes in the brain

  12

  like the ones my MEG detected, and those who believe that we need to add

  13

  some additional ingredients over and above the physical. It’s worth doing a

  14

  little thinking of our own about how brains actually work, to help under-

  15

  stand why the physical picture is so compelling.

  16

  17

  •

  18

  The brain is a network of interconnected neurons. We talked briefly in

  19

  chapter 28 about how complex structures can arise by gradual agglomera-

  20

  tion of smaller units into ever- larger ones, preserving the existence of inter-

  21

  esting structure on all scales. The brain is a great example.

  22

  The conventional view of what happens in the brain is that it’s not

  23

  the neurons themselves that encode information but the way they are

  24

  connected to one another. Every neuron is connected to some other neu-

  25

  rons, and not to others; that’s what defines the network structure of the

  26

  brain, known as its connectome.

 

‹ Prev