The Big Picture

Home > Other > The Big Picture > Page 59
The Big Picture Page 59

by Carroll, Sean M.

person put a Big Bird doll inside one of two boxes in front of him. Then that

  29

  person leaves the room, and another one comes in and switches Big Bird

  30

  from the first box to the second one. The second person leaves and the first

  31

  returns. Leonardo is smart enough to know both that Big Bird is in the

  32

  second box, and that the first person “believes” that it’s in the first box.

  33

  The experimenter then asks, “Leo, can you find where I think Big Bird

  34

  is?” This is a query about metacognition, thinking about thinking. Leon-

  35S

  ardo correctly points to the first box, corresponding to his model of the

  36N

  experimenter’s beliefs. But while pointing at the first box, Leonardo also

  346

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 346

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  W h At t h I n K S ?

  sneaks a quick glance at the second box, where Big Bird is actually located.

  01

  This wasn’t programmed behavior; it was something that the robot learned

  02

  from interacting with humans.

  03

  Whether you are a fish crawling onto land, a robot dealing with experi-

  04

  menters in the lab, or a person interacting with other people, it is helpful to

  05

  have models of the world around you, including other organisms and their

  06

  models. Awareness of ourselves and others, and the ability to communicate

  07

  and interact on a number of levels, are useful capacities to have as we work

  08

  to survive in a complicated world.

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  18

  19

  20

  21

  22

  23

  24

  25

  26

  27

  28

  29

  30

  31

  32

  33

  34

  S35

  N36

  347

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 347

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  01

  02

  03

  40

  04

  05

  The Hard Problem

  06

  07

  08

  09

  10

  11

  12

  13

  14

  15

  16

  17

  life on Earth has undergone a series of dramatic phase transitions.

  Self- replicating organisms, cell nuclei, multicellular life, climbing

  onto land, the origin of language— all of these represent important

  new capacities that changed what life was capable of. The appearance of

  18

  consciousness is arguably the most interesting phase transition of all, the

  19

  beginning of a new kind of way for matter to organize itself and behave.

  20

  Not only can atoms organize themselves into complex, self- sustaining pat-

  21

  terns, but those patterns acquire a capacity for self- awareness and the ability

  22

  to think about their place in the cosmos.

  23

  Unless something much deeper is going on. As philosopher Thomas Na-

  24

  gel has put it, “The existence of consciousness seems to imply that . . . the

  25

  natural order is far less austere than it would be if physics and chemistry

  26

  accounted for everything.” (It was Nagel who really emphasized that “what

  27

  it is like” to feel something is the kind of thing a complete theory should be

  28

  able to explain. His famous example was that we can’t know what it is like

  29

  to be a bat, but the point is more general.) On this view, we shouldn’t hope

  30

  to explain conscious experience purely in terms of the physical behavior of

  31

  the quantum fields in the Core Theory, since consciousness transcends the

  32

  physical world.

  33

  It’s not hard to understand why someone might feel this way. Fine, the

  34

  thinking goes, I can accept that the universe exists and obeys natural laws

  35S

  without appealing to anything outside. I have no trouble believing that life

  36N

  is a complex network of interlocking chemical reactions that began

  348

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 348

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  t h E h A R d PR O b l E M

  spontaneously and evolved through natural selection over billions of years.

  01

  But surely I am more than just a bunch of atoms knocking into one another

  02

  under the influence of gravity and electromagnetism. I perceive, I feel—

  03

  there is something that it is like to be me, something uniquely personal and

  04

  experiential, a rich inner life that can’t possibly be accounted for by un-

  05

  thinking matter in motion, no matter how many atoms you congregate

  06

  together. The issue has been dubbed the mind- body problem: how can we

  07

  hope to account for mental reality using only physical concepts?

  08

  As with the origin of life and the origin of the universe, we can’t claim

  09

  to have a full understanding of the nature of consciousness. The study of

  10

  how we think and feel, not to mention how to think about who we are, is

  11

  in its relative infancy. As neuroscientist and philosopher Patricia Church-

  12

  land has put it, “We’re pre- Newton, pre- Kepler. We’re still sussing out that

  13

  there are moons around Jupiter.”

  14

  But nothing we do know about consciousness should lead us to doubt

  15

  the ordinary, naturalist conception of the world that has been so exception-

  16

  ally successful in other contexts. As of right now, nothing about the mind-

  17

  body problem should persuade us that the laws of physics need updating,

  18

  amending, or augmenting.

  19

  20

  •

  21

  Like “life,” consciousness is less a unified conception and more a collection

  22

  of related attributes and phenomena. We are aware of ourselves, as distinct

  23

  from the outside world. We can contemplate alternative futures. We experi-

  24

  ence sensations. We can reason abstractly and symbolically. We feel emo-

  25

  tions. We can call up memories, tell stories, and sometimes lie. The

  26

  simultaneous working of all these aspects contributes to being conscious,

  27

  and some aspects are going to be easier to explain in purely physical terms

  28

  than others.

  29

  Consider the color red.
It is a useful concept, one that can apparently be

  30

  recognized universally and objectively, at least by sighted people who are

  31

  not prevented from seeing red by color blindness. The operational instruc-

  32

  tion “stop when the light is red” can be understood without ambiguity. But

  33

  there is the famous lurking question: do you and I see the same thing when

  34

  we see something red? That’s the question of phenomenal consciousness—

  S35

  what is it like to experience redness?

  N36

  349

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 349

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  The word qualia (plural of “quale,” which is pronounced KWAH- lay) is

  02

  sometimes used to denote the subjective experience of the way something

  03

  seems to us. “Red” is a color, a physically objective wavelength of light or

  04

  appropriate combination thereof; but “the experience of the redness of red”

  05

  is one of the qualia we would like to account for in a complete understand-

  06

  ing of consciousness.

  07

  Australian philosopher David Chalmers has famously emphasized the

  08

  difference between what he calls the Easy Problems and the Hard Problem

  09

  of consciousness. The Easy Problems are manifold— explaining the differ-

  10

  ence between being awake and asleep, how we sense and store and integrate

  11

  information, how we can recall the past and predict the future. The Hard

  12

  Problem is explaining qualia, the subjective character of experience. It can

  13

  be thought of as those aspects of consciousness that are irreducibly first-

  14

  person; what we personally feel, not how we act and respond as seen by the

  15

  rest of the world. The Easy Problems are about functioning; the Hard Prob-

  16

  lem is about experiencing.

  17

  It’s the Hard Problem that poses an apparent challenge to a purely phys-

  18

  ical understanding of the world. The Easy Problems aren’t easy, but they are

  19

  squarely in the wheelhouse of conventional scientific investigation. We

  20

  don’t have a finished understanding of how photons impinging on our

  21

  retinas while we are looking at a fish end up conjuring the notion of “fish”

  22

  in our brains. But the path to getting there seems pretty neuroscientifically

  23

  straightforward. The Hard Problem, by contrast, seems like an entirely dif-

  24

  ferent kettle of those fish. We can poke around in the brain all we like, but

  25

  how in the world do we expect that to help us understand our inner, wholly

  26

  subjective, experience? How can a collection of quantum fields evolving in

  27

  accordance with the Core Theory be said to have “inner experience” at all?

  28

  Many experts on consciousness think of these two issues, in the words

  29

  of Peter Hankins, as “the Easy Problem (which is hard), and the Hard Prob-

  30

  lem (which is impossible).” But some think the Hard Problem is not only

  31

  pretty easy; it really isn’t a problem at all— just a matter of conceptual con-

  32

  fusion. Discussions between the two camps can be frustrating; there’s noth-

  33

  ing more disheartening than someone telling you that the problem you

  34

  think is most important and central isn’t really a problem at all.

  35S

  As poetic naturalists, that’s basically what we’ll be doing. The attri-

  36N

  butes of consciousness, including our qualia and inner subjective

  350

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 350

  20/07/2016 10:02:54

  t h E h A R d PR O b l E M

  experiences, are useful ways of talking about the effective behavior of the

  01

  collections of atoms we call human beings. Consciousness isn’t an illusion,

  02

  but it doesn’t point to any departure from the laws of physics as we cur-

  03

  rently understand them.

  04

  05

  •

  06

  There are a number of thought experiments that try to illustrate how hard

  07

  the Hard Problem really is. A famous one is Mary the Color Scientist, a

  08

  colorful (as it were) instantiation of what’s known as the knowledge argu-

  09

  ment. It was introduced by Australian philosopher Frank Jackson in the

  10

  1980s, with the goal of showing that there must be something in the world

  11

  other than just physical facts. It’s right up there with Searle’s Chinese Room

  12

  on the list of famous thought experiments in which philosophers lock peo-

  13

  ple into strange rooms in order to illustrate some feature of consciousness.

  14

  Mary is a brilliant scientist who has been brought up under certain bi-

  15

  zarre circumstances. She lives in a room that she has never left, and that

  16

  room is completely devoid of color. Everything in the room is black, white,

  17

  or some shade of gray. Her own skin is painted white, and all of her clothes

  18

  are black. Curiously, given her environment, Mary grows up to become a

  19

  specialist in the science of color. She has access to all of the equipment she

  20

  would want, as well as to the entirety of the scientific literature on the sub-

  21

  ject of color. All of the color illustrations have been reduced to grayscale.

  22

  Eventually, Mary knows everything there is to know about color, from

  23

  a physical point of view. She knows about the physics of light, and about the

  24

  neuroscience of how the eye transmits signals to the brain. She’s read up on

  25

  art history, color theory, and the agricultural expertise involved in growing

  26

  a perfect red tomato. She’s just never seen the color red.

  27

  Jackson asks, what happens when Mary decides to leave her room and

  28

  actually sees colors for the first time? In particular, does she learn anything 29

  new? He claims she does.

  30

  31

  What will happen when Mary is released from her black and

  32

  white room or is given a color television monitor? Will she learn

  33

  anything or not? It seems just obvious that she will learn some-

  34

  thing about the world and our visual experience of it. But then

  S35

  is it inescapable that her previous knowledge was incomplete.

  N36

  351

  Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 351

  20/07/2016 10:02:5
4

  T H E B IG PIC T U R E

  01

  But she had all the physical information. Ergo there is more to

  02

  have than that, and Physicalism is false.

  03

  04

  Mary can know all of the physical facts about color, but there is still

  05

  something she doesn’t know: “what it is like” to experience the color red.

  06

  Therefore, there are more kinds of things in the world than merely physical

  07

  things. The argument is not merely saying that we don’t yet know how

  08

  to explain Mary’s new experience in physical terms. The claim is that no

  09

  such explanation can possibly exist.

  10

  Like the Chinese Room, Mary’s predicament relies on a thought-

  11

  experiment setup that sounds relatively innocent, but is wildly implausible

  12

  in practice. “All of the physical facts about color” is an awful lot of facts.

  13

  Here is a physical fact about color: when I cut my finger while chopping

  14

  onions last week, my blood was red. Does Mary know that I cut my finger

  15

  while chopping onions last week? Does she know the position and momen-

  16

  tum and frequency of every photon of visible light in the whole universe?

  17

  What about the past and future of the universe? Like “an omniscient, om-

  18

  nipotent, and omnibenevolent being,” the phrase “all the physical facts

  19

  about color” conjures a certain vague impression in our minds, but it’s far

  20

  from clear that this expression corresponds to any well- defined concept.

  21

  •

  22

  23

  Vagueness about physical facts isn’t the biggest problem with citing Mary

  24

  as evidence for the existence of features of the universe that aren’t purely

  25

  physical. The real issue is with slipperiness in the definitions of “knowl-

  26

  edge” and “experience.”

  27

  Let’s consider Mary’s predicament from a poetic- naturalism perspective.

  28

  There is some fundamental description of our world, in terms of an evolv-

  29

  ing quantum wave function or perhaps something deeper. The other con-

  30

  cepts we appeal to, such as “rooms” and “red,” are part of vocabularies that

  31

  provide useful approximate models for certain aspects of that underlying

  32

  reality in an appropriate domain of applicability. So we invent, for example,

  33

  the concept of a “person,” which maps onto the underlying reality in a par-

  34

  ticular way— a way that might be difficult to precisely define in principle

  35S

  but is easy to recognize in practice.

 

‹ Prev