Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 413
20/07/2016 10:02:56
T H E B IG PIC T U R E
01
Wheatley and Jonathan Haidt did a study in which they hypnotized sub-
02
jects to feel a strong sense of revulsion at certain innocuous words such as
03
“often” and “take.” They were then told simple stories about people who did
04
nothing particularly wrong from any reasonable ethical perspective. When
05
those stories contained the words they had been primed to react to, not
06
only did they feel disgust, but they also judged the actions of the people in
07
the stories to be somehow morally wrong. Without being able to articulate
08
exactly why, the subjects were convinced that the people being described
09
were somehow up to no good.
10
Clashes between universal ethical guidelines and our personal moral
11
sentiments would be okay, if we thought that our sentiments were merely
12
crude approximations to the more transcendent truths captured by those
13
guidelines. In that case, so much the worse for our sentiments. But if we
14
envision the project of moral philosophy as systematizing and rationalizing
15
our sentiments, rather than replacing them with an objective truth, then
16
such approaches have a bigger problem. Talking about morality might not
17
be so cut-and-dried.
18
•
19
20
Deontology and consequentialism, and for that matter virtue ethics and
21
various other approaches, all capture something real about our moral im-
22
pulses. We want to act in good ways; we want to make the world a better
23
place; we want to be good people. But we also want to make sense and be
24
internally consistent. That’s hard to do while accepting all of these compet-
25
ing impulses at once. In practice, moral philosophies tend to pick one ap-
26
proach and apply it universally. And as a result of that, we often end up with
27
conclusions that don’t sit easily with the premises we started with.
28
It may be that the kind of moral code that fits most people the best isn’t
29
based on a strict construal of any one approach, but takes bits and pieces
30
from all of them. Consider a kind of “soft consequentialism,” where the
31
value of actions depends on their consequences, but also to some degree on
32
the actions themselves. Or imagine that we allow ourselves to place greater
33
value on helping people we know and care about than on helping those
34
farther away. These need not be seen as “mistakes”; they could be part of a
35S
complex and multifaceted, but internally consistent, way of realizing our
36N
basic moral inclinations.
4 14
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 414
20/07/2016 10:02:56
C O n S t Ru C t I n g g O O d n E S S
Or— someone could be a perfectly moral person who based their behav-
01
ior on a small set of absolute rules, whether it was a particular flavor of
02
utilitarianism or adherence to the categorical imperative, because that’s
03
what they felt was the best fit to their inner convictions. And that’s okay.
04
The moral systems we construct serve our own purposes.
05
Abraham was commanded by God to do something horrible. It was a
06
great challenge to his humanity, but given his view of the world, the correct
07
course of behavior was clear: if you are certain that God is telling you to do
08
something, that’s what you do. Poetic naturalism refuses to offer us the
09
consolation of objective moral certainty. There is no “right” answer to the
10
trolley problem. How you should act depends on who you are.
11
12
•
13
Ay, there’s the rub. We want there to be objective solutions to our dilem-
14
mas, as surely as there are theorems in mathematics or experimental discov-
15
eries in science. As good Bayesians, aware of our bias toward claims that we
16
would like to be true, this desire should make us especially skeptical of at-
17
tempts to found objective morality on a natural basis. But as human beings,
18
it often makes us all too readily accepting.
19
The worry is that, if morality is constructed, everyone will construct
20
whatever they like, and what they like won’t actually be very good. It’s an
21
ancient concern, usually directed at believers in the wrong religion or no
22
religion at all. Tertullian, an early Christian thinker from Africa who is
23
recognized as a Father of the Church, explained that an atomist like the
24
Greek philosopher Epicurus couldn’t be a good person. The problem is that
25
for Epicurus, life ends at death, so suffering is ephemeral, while Christians
26
believe in hell, so for them it’s forever. Why should anyone strive to be good
27
if there were no promise of an eternal reward, nor threat of eternal pun-
28
ishment?
29
30
Think of these things, too, in the light of the brevity of any
31
punishment you can inflict— never to last longer than till death.
32
On this ground Epicurus makes light of all suffering and pain,
33
maintaining that if it is small, it is contemptible; and if it is
34
great, it is not long- continued. No doubt about it, we, who re-
S35
ceive our awards under the judgment of an all- seeing God, and
N36
4 15
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 415
20/07/2016 10:02:56
T H E B IG PIC T U R E
01
who look forward to eternal punishment from Him for sin,—
02
we alone make real effort to attain a blameless life.
03
04
The modern version of this worry is that, if we were to accept that mo-
05
rality is constructed, individuals will run around giving in to their worst
06
instincts, and we would have no basis on which to condemn obviously bad
07
things like the Holocaust. After all, somebody thought it was a good idea,
08
and without objective guidance how can we say they were wrong?
09
The constructivist answers that just because moral rules are invented by
10
&nb
sp; human beings, that doesn’t make them any less real. The rules of basketball
11
are also invented by human beings, but once invented they really exist.
12
People even argue over what the “right” rules should be. When James Nai-
13
smith invented the game, the ball was thrown into peach baskets, and had
14
to be retrieved by hand each time a shot was made. Only later did they real-
15
ize that the game would be improved by replacing the basket with a hoop.
16
That made the game “better,” in the sense that it did a better job at fulfilling
17
its purpose as a game. The rules of basketball aren’t objectively defined,
18
waiting out there in the universe to be discovered; but they aren’t arbitrary
19
either. Morality is like that: we invent the rules, but we invent them for
20
sensible purposes.
21
The problem arises when we imagine people whose purposes— whose
22
foundational moral sentiments and commitments— are radically at odds
23
with ours. What are we to do with someone who just wants to play hockey
24
rather than basketball? In sports we might seek out different people to play
25
with, but when it comes to morality we all have to live together here on this
26
Earth.
27
We might hope, in the spirit of Kant, that simple logical requirements
28
of internal consistency would lead every rational person to construct the
29
same moral rules, even starting from slightly different initial feelings. But
30
that hope seems slim indeed. Sharon Street imagines an “internally coher-
31
ent Caligula,” who takes pleasure in the suffering of others. Such a monster
32
need not be illogical or inconsistent; they just have fundamental attitudes
33
with which we cannot agree. We’re not going to reason them out of their
34
stance. If they act on their impulses in ways that bring harm to others, we
35S
should respond as we actually do in the real world: by preventing them
36N
from doing so. When criminals refuse to be deterred, we put them in jail.
4 16
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 416
20/07/2016 10:02:56
C O n S t Ru C t I n g g O O d n E S S
As a practical matter, the worries associated with constructivism are
01
somewhat overblown. Most people, in most circumstances, want to think
02
of themselves as doing good rather than evil. It’s not clear what operational
03
benefit would be gained by establishing morality as an objective set of facts.
04
Presumably we envision a person or group who was relatively rational, but
05
disagreed with us about morality, whom we could sit down with over coffee
06
and convince of the mistake they were making. In practice the recom-
07
mended strategy for a constructivist would be essentially the same: sitting
08
down and talking with the person, appealing to our common moral beliefs,
09
attempting to work out a mutually reasonable solution. Moral progress is
10
possible because most people share many moral sentiments; if they don’t,
11
reasoning with them wouldn’t help much no matter what.
12
If instead the worry is that we can’t justify stepping in to prevent im-
13
moral actions, that simply isn’t an issue for constructivists. If, upon rational
14
reflection, we decide that something is deeply wrong, there is no reason why
15
we cannot work to prevent it from happening, regardless of whether our
16
decision is based on external criteria or our own inner convictions. Again,
17
this is no more or less than what really happens in the world.
18
Deciding how to be good isn’t like solving a math puzzle, or discovering
19
a new fossil. It’s like going out to dinner with a group of friends. We think
20
about what we want for our individual selves, talk to others about their
21
desires and how we can work together, and reason about how to make it
22
happen. The group may include both vegetarians and omnivores, but with
23
a good- faith effort there’s no reason everyone can’t be satisfied.
24
25
•
26
I once found myself on a panel at a large interdisciplinary meeting, attended
27
by people from the worlds of business, science, politics, and the arts. The
28
purpose of the panel was to discuss morality in the modern world. I had
29
been invited not because of any particular expertise in moral matters, but
30
it was a conference where most of the participants tended to be religious,
31
and I was known not to be; my job was to be the token atheist. And when
32
the time came for me to speak, the single question I was asked was: “What
33
do you think would be the best argument against your atheism?” The other
34
panelists, by contrast, were offered a chance to say something positive and
S35
constructive about their moral positions. There is a lurking suspicion in
N36
4 17
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 417
20/07/2016 10:02:56
T H E B IG PIC T U R E
01
many corners that naturalists are objects of curiosity but not to be taken
02
seriously when it comes to talking about values.
03
Here in the early years of the twenty- first century, a majority of philoso-
04
phers and scientists are naturalists. But in the public sphere, at least in the
05
United States, on questions of morality and meaning, religion and spiritu-
06
ality are given a preeminent place. Our values have not yet caught up to our
07
best ontology.
08
They had better start catching up. When it comes to deciding how to
09
live, we’re like that first fish flapping up onto land: faced with a new world
10
of challenges and opportunities, and not yet really adapted to it. Technol-
11
ogy has given us enormous power to shape our world for better or for worse,
12
and by any reasonable estimate we are only at the very beginning of the
13
associated changes. We’re going to be faced with the kinds of moral ques-
14
tions that our ancestors could not possibly have contemplated, from
15
human- machine interfacing to the exploration of new planets. Engineers
16
working on self- dr
iving cars have already begun to realize that the software
17
is going to have to be programmed to solve certain kinds of trolley problems.
18
Poetic naturalism doesn’t tell us how to behave, but it warns us away
19
from the false complacency associated with the conviction that our morals
20
are objectively the best. Our lives are changing in unpredictable ways; we
21
need to be able to make judgments with clear eyes and an accurate picture
22
of how the world operates. We don’t need an immovable place to stand; we
23
need to make our peace with a universe that doesn’t care what we do, and
24
take pride in the fact that we care anyway.
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35S
36N
4 18
Big Picture - UK final proofs.indd 418
20/07/2016 10:02:56
01
02
49
03
04
Listening to the World
05
06
07
08
09
10
11
12
t
13
he idea of “Ten Commandments” is a deeply compelling one. It
14
combines two impulses that are ingrained in our nature as human
15
beings: making lists of ten things, and telling other people how to
16
behave.
17
The most famous such list is found in the Hebrew Bible. It’s a compila-
18
tion of instructions for the Israelite people, handed from God to Moses
19
atop Mount Sinai. The commandments are found twice, once in Exodus
20
and once in Deuteronomy. In neither case is the list numbered, and the
21
wording between the two appearances is slightly different. As a result, there
22
is no agreement on what “The Ten Commandments” actually are. Jews,
23
Orthodox Christians, Catholics, and different Protestant denominations
24
quote slightly different lists. Lutherans, for example, don’t include the tra-
25
ditional prohibition against graven images, and split the coveting of thy
26
neighbor’s house into a commandment all its own, rather than grouping it
27
with the coveting of thy neighbor’s wife and thy neighbor’s servants. What
28
matters is that there are ten of them.
29
Inevitably, schools of thought outside the traditional religious main-
30
stream have borrowed the Ten Commandments idea, and proposed their
The Big Picture Page 70