MindStar

Home > Other > MindStar > Page 12
MindStar Page 12

by Michael A Aquino


  Party holds to be truth is truth.

  “It is impossible to see reality except by looking

  through the eyes of the Party. That is the fact that you

  have got to relearn, Winston. It needs an act of self-

  destruction, an effort of the will. You must humble

  yourself before you can become sane.” 39

  Earth in the 21st century CE remains predominantly a

  mixture of both the religious and post-religious telos-

  ignorant. Like those chained in the darkness of Plato’s

  Cave, they can see and think no further than the old

  superstitions, fears, and social constriction of “free will”.

  Only through initiation can the few Elect of their number

  cast off these chains and awaken to the true and non-

  destructive enlightenment of telos.

  E. Historical Non- Telos: Determinism

  As noted above, the alternative to Mechanistic free

  will is determinism, which, as the term implies, denies

  all conscious volition in the OU (which includes all

  human activity). This is the “cold, dead extreme” of

  existence, in which there is nothing but cause/effect,

  stimulus/response - all of which, were one to take all

  factors into account, result in inevitable, predictable

  outcomes.

  Determinism became fashionable in the scientific

  community with the advent of Newtonian physics, which

  39 Orwell, George, 1984. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company,

  1949, pages #205-206.

  - 111 -

  enthusiasts sought to extend beyond natural phenomena

  to all event interactions, including those of human

  beings. This resulted in the notion that human thoughts

  and emotions could be not just predicted but controlled

  by identifying and manipulating the environmental,

  physiological, and psychological factors that govern them.

  On the scale of human communities and nations,

  determinism was loosely present in the East in such

  concepts as Taoism, in which the universe and everything

  in it rolled inexorably onward through time, with

  everything in it locked to that mechanism. There is

  accordingly no personal discretion possible for Taoists:

  The most one can do is to sense and harmonize with the

  Tao, so as not to be overwhelmed by it.

  In the West determinism got off to a slow start,

  b e c a u s e i t w a s a n t i t h e t i c a l t o e s t a b l i s h

  religions’ (principally Judæo-Christianity) belief in a

  creative and active God. And, of course, in the related

  belief that his human creatures had brought “original sin”

  upon themselves through Adam & Eve’s making a [free

  will] choice. If there were no need for God, and if A&E

  had no responsibility for an “inevitable choice”, then the

  entire religious control system evaporates: There is no

  deity to be vengeful; no humans deserving of vengeance.

  With the Enlightenment and the eclipse of literal

  religious belief, however, came the notion that there was

  a predictability, a mechanism in human affairs. This was

  associated with another supposition: that history was

  “progressing” through time from the primitive to the

  sophisticated. Interpretations of these perceptions would

  take several forms, from the abstract to the neo-religious.

  1. Empiricism

  David Hume (1711-1776) is the father of modern

  empiricism, which holds philosophical and political

  - 112 -

  values to be determined by habit and by their apparent

  utility, not by abstract virtues or ideals.

  Cosmologically Hume adhered to deism. The mere

  existence of a political system or institution, according to

  this approach, demonstrates that it has a part in God’s

  overall scheme of things. If it didn’t have such a part, it

  wouldn’t have come into existence. What that scheme

  might be is not addressed by Hume, hence political

  philosophy and systems cannot be measured critically

  according to it.

  L o o k i n g a t t h e h u m a n m i n d , H u m e s e e s

  perceptions, which consist of impressions “when we

  hear, see, feel, love, hate, desire, or will”; and ideas

  “when we reflect upon a passion or an object which is not

  present”.

  Impressions are more “strong” and “lively” than ideas.

  All ideas are derived from impressions. As a blind man

  cannot have an idea of a color nor a deaf man an idea of

  music, so “we can never think of anything which we have

  not seen [or otherwise sensed] without us or felt in our

  own minds”. We cannot have factual knowledge of

  anything which can be conceived otherwise. Since it is

  possible to think that the Sun will not rise tomorrow, we

  cannot know that it necessarily will. The laws of nature

  which say that it will might change between now and

  then.

  Mathematics and geometry are examples of things in

  which principles cannot be conceived otherwise. One

  cannot think of a triangle whose internal angles do not

  add to 180°.

  What Hume is getting at is that much of what

  previous philosophers had considered necessary cause-

  and-effect relationships is not that at all, but simply

  habit. “All reasonings [about causation] are nothing but

  the effects of custom; and custom has no influence, but

  - 113 -

  by enlivening the imagination, and giving us a strong

  conception of any object.”

  When considering virtue and vice, Hume starts with

  the notion that they must either be relations (resulting

  from the comparison of ideas) or factual matters

  (inferences). He finds that he cannot accept them as

  either. Therefore they are simply irrational, non-factual

  passions. Hume sees reason as a device used to satisfy

  passions, not something which is superior or prior to

  them. “Reason is and ought only to be the slave of the

  passions, and can never pretend to any other office than

  to serve and obey them.”

  Hume considers the morally good as what one ought

  to do according to prevailing passionate custom. It

  cannot be ascertained by dispassionate reasoning.

  Reason may be used to discover the “fitting” - the most

  practical or sensible approach - but not the “morally

  good”. Hence virtue and vice are products of sentiment.

  Virtue is not approved because it is virtue; it is

  considered to be virtue because it meets with passionate

  approval.

  The good is identical with the pleasant, but not

  necessarily with one’s own immediate personal pleasure.

  Examples of what Hume considers virtues: (1) Useful to

  others: justice, generosity, beneficence, honesty. (2)

  Useful to self: prudence, frugality, temperance, industry.

  (3) Pleasant to others: modesty, wit, decency. (4)

  Pleasant to self: self-esteem, glory.

  We approve of such “virtues” because we are moved

  by a sense of humanity or benevolence. This is not a

  “natural instinct”, but rather the result of a sympat
hy

  which humans feel for one another - a transference of the

  applicability of others’ predicaments into one’s own

  frame of reference. Social justice is sought not out of

  simple, direct self-interest, but rather because we feel

  - 114 -

  that even remote injustices will act to harm the

  cooperative society.

  Hume’s objection to social contract theory is that he

  thinks it is simply historically false. Rulers don’t consider

  their authority as based upon the consent of the ruled,

  nor do subjects feel sovereign.

  Hume also objected to social contract theory on the

  grounds that it was based upon reform of humans by

  reason. Hume argues for strong governments and

  preservation of systems based upon their historical

  durability. He is thus a conservative.

  The Christian political thinkers had God/Christ-based

  values. The social contract thinkers had reason-based

  values. Hume has endeavored to deal with politics by

  ignoring the former and denying the actual validity of the

  latter. He thus finds himself in a no-man’s-land of

  subjective opinion. His somewhat clumsy solution is to

  endorse and preserve values simply because they have

  been around for a long time (i.e. conservatism). Strict

  conservatives tend to be Hume-like, just as radicals tend

  to oppose values based upon non-rational sentiment and

  to favor ideals based upon reason. This is not to say that

  much of their “reasoning” isn’t guilty of the weaknesses

  which Hume identifies.

  2. Dialectic Idealism

  Europe in the early 19th century was influenced

  significantly by budding forces of Romanticism,

  nationalism, and liberalism.

  The first represented a rejection of the “cult of reason”

  espoused by the social contract theorists of the

  Enlightenment, in favor of a more emotional approach to

  social and cultural issues.

  The second represented a growing identification of

  the individual with a nation or state, as opposed to with a

  - 115 -

  city or monarch. This was particularly significant in the

  cases of Germany and Italy, which until now had

  remained largely fragmented.

  The third represented a general impatience with

  archaic aristocratic systems as justifying a state’s

  existence. The Enlightenment and the Age of Revolution

  had opened the door to critical analysis of state systems,

  not just to their glorification.

  Georg W.F. Hegel (1770-1831) developed his theories

  o f d i a l e c t i c i d e a l i s m a n d o r g a n i c i s m b y

  approximately 1816, when he held a professorship at the

  University of Heidelberg. His two principal concepts are

  defined as follows:

  (1) Hegel conceives the universe as the

  manifestation of God’s mind seeking

  complete self-realization through a process

  called dialectic idealism. This is

  occasionally [and more precisely] called the

  dialectic of absolute spirit. As applied

  to Earth, it is the concept that the history of

  the world consists of part of the spirit of

  God, manifesting itself through the

  collective spirits of mankind, moving

  onwards through logic (the dialectic)

  towards complete self-understanding. An

  existing idea (thesis) is criticized and

  partially refuted by its opposite (antithesis),

  resulting in a more perfect concept

  (synthesis).

  (2) The organic state is the manifestation or

  appearance of God in the material world. [It

  is not identical with God; it is a “reflection”

  of the dialectic of his mind. Accordingly it

  proceeds in ways and towards goals which

  - 116 -

  are not necessarily the sum total of the ways

  and goals of the individual human minds

  within it.

  In many ways Hegel is a reaction (antithesis &

  synthesis) to Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). Bishop

  Berkeley’s subjective idealism had held that nothing

  could be known objectively - that knowledge is limited to

  subjective impressions. Kant refines this into what is

  called critical idealism, in which human consciousness

  is subdivided into sensation, understanding, and

  pure reason. Sensations and understanding of them

  and consequences of them can be proven, Kant says, but

  pure reason (concepts unsupported by sensations) cannot

  be conclusive. It is “beyond causality”.

  Hegel overcomes Kant’s problem by making “pure

  reason” a necessary and intrinsic characteristic of God/

  the universe. All history is “logical”. If it sometimes seems

  illogical, it is because we don’t see it as clearly and

  comprehensively as God does. The task of philosophy,

  therefore, is one of understanding, of logical analysis -

  and not one of creation of abstract, ideal political

  systems.

  Hege further introduced the concept of the

  phenomenology of mind as a variation on the

  Platonic “pyramid of thought” concept. 40 With Hegel, of

  course, the mind develops forward through time

  (historically); whereas with Plato the levels of thought are

  measures of excellence irrespective of time or

  progression. Hegel’s phenomenology of mind begins with

  consciousness, which is everyday experience (action

  40 In his Republic Plato stratified thought as eikasia (primitive

  emotion), pistis (ordinary active/reactive thinking), dianoia (precise,

  logical, enlightened thought), and nœsis (intuition and apprehension

  of the transcendent Forms (Egyptian neteru) and the perfect Good

  ( Agathon).

  - 117 -

  and reaction to events) without self-consciousness. We

  take the truth of conscious experiences for granted; Hegel

  calls this sense-certainty.

  As soon as one pauses to reflect on conscious

  experiences, one moves to self-consciousness. At the

  same time there comes an awareness of other selves,

  other minds. This is very close to Hobbes’ concept of the

  state of nature. The antagonism is because “they exist and

  are not me”. Therefore I wish to control them and not to

  be controlled by them. I wish recognition by them; I do

  not wish to recognize them in return. Thus there comes

  into being the political “master/slave relationship”.

  The next step in the dialectic involves a personal

  internalization of the master/slave relationship, as

  exemplified in Hellenistic stoicism and skepticism. The

  inconsistency this produces between internal and

  external life goes on to produce the rages and hypocrisies

  of medieval Christianity. In the Reformation the internal

  is seen as relevant to, and in command of the external.

  There is still the problem of conflict between individual

  wills, which, if undisciplined through organization and

  government, would run wild in anarchy “… since any

  institution whatever is antagonistic to the abstract self-


  consciousness of equality”.

  As consciousness gives way to self-consciousness,

  questions of morality ( Moralität) arise in contrast to

  custom or social convention ( Sittlichkeit). How to aspire

  to morality?

  The answer is that one apprehends it through the

  modern state. Hegel’s concept of the state is that it is the

  embodiment of the spirit of those who constitute it; its

  leaders must consider this spirit and not simply their own

  desires when guiding it. Correspondingly individuals

  must seek in this spirit ( Volksgeist) a guide for their

  personal morality.

  - 118 -

  Human society is an artificial machine which works

  for the goals of the spiritual state. Individualism and

  rights against a government are considered by Hegel to

  limit freedom: Since they reduce the scope and power of

  the whole, they serve to limit possibility.

  Similarly Hegel feels contempt for democracy. It

  reduces questions of relevance to the state to resolution

  by simple “counting of noses”, i.e. voting, in which all

  opinions are not of the same intellectual merit. [Hegel

  prefers a monarchy. This preference is a weak area of his

  thought, since it is not really justified. Why should an

  accident of birth make one any better a judge of the

  Volksgeist?]

  For Hegel there are no absolute values. Values are

  products of history; they are validated by their success.

  Thus Hegel overcomes Hume’s objection to morality. The

  “social contract” theorists - Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau

  - felt that man made the state. Hegel reversed this, saying

  that the state is prior to man. He thus conceived the most

  advanced and complex metaphysical statement of man as

  a product and subject of his environment. Unlike B.F.

  Skinner and other environmental materialists, however,

  Hegel postulated a deliberate, universal intelligence

  behind the historical process.

  3. Will to Power

  Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) completed and

  published his major theoretical works Also Sprach

  Zarathustra and Beyond Good and Evil ca. 1885. He was

  an atheist and a materialist, insisting that the universe

  [or world] of appearances is the only true one. He carries

  this principle into his assessment of humanity by denying

  any “dual existence” within the body (i.e. soul vs. physical

  body). Man is a unified, material being.

  - 119 -

 

‹ Prev