MindStar

Home > Other > MindStar > Page 24
MindStar Page 24

by Michael A Aquino


  indignantly, then turns to pages #1050-1. And

  what sort of demonstration of this second

  postulate does he offer?

  STRANGER: On the other hand, will we not also

  be ready to assert that we do in fact hear words

  spoken and see acts done which at one time

  exceed the essentially right measure and at

  another time fall short of it? Is it not just this

  matter of attaining the due measure which

  marks off good men from bad in human society?

  The Chimæra: That’s not much of a proof. The words or

  actions that impress one observer as ideal may

  strike another as excessive or inadequate.

  Similarly “good” and “bad” are subjective terms.

  Plato is guilty of a non sequitur.

  The Sphinx: True. If the stranger had been talking with

  someone like Protagoras instead of the docile

  young Socrates, The Statesman would have

  floundered [and foundered] right there.

  The Chimæra: Note that, immediately after making

  that statement, Plato tries to reinforce it by

  denying that statecraft - or any other art - can exist

  without it. Thus he assumes that statecraft has

  already been proved to be an absolute standard,

  when in fact it has not. Two unproved statements

  cannot be used to prove each other, and so Plato is

  guilty of a second logical fallacy, generally known

  as interdependence.

  The Sphinx: Since the rest of The Statesman hinges

  upon young Socrates’ blind disregard of these two

  fallacies, is there a point in our discussing it

  further? What we have uncovered here is not some

  - 223 -

  relatively-unimportant digression. The subsequent

  structure of The Statesman is one of peeling away

  inadequate manifestations of statesmanship,

  leaving, theoretically, the Form itself at the core. If

  there is not an agreed-upon Form, then the

  peeling-away process is pointless.

  The Chimæra: To be fair to Plato, let us examine his

  idea of the Form of statesmanship. He turns to

  page #1077.

  STRANGER: If you will view the three arts we

  have spoken of as a group with a common

  character, you will be bound to see that none of

  them has turned out to be itself the art of

  statesmanship. This is because it is not the

  province of the real kingly art to act for itself,

  but rather to control the work of the arts which

  instruct us in the methods of action. The kingly

  art controls them according to its power to

  perceive the right occasions for undertaking and

  setting in motion the great enterprises of state.

  The other arts must do what they are told to do

  by the kingly art ... It is a universal art, and so

  we call it by a name of universal scope. That

  name is one which I believe to belong to this art

  and this alone, the name of “statesmanship”.

  The Sphinx: On the whole, that’s not a bad definition.

  And, I might add, there is nothing in it which

  necessitates the existence of an absolute standard

  for statesmanship. A statesman can simply be a

  person who is relatively skilled at emphasizing,

  directing, and applying the various arts and

  sciences of a state or community.

  The Chimæra: So it would seem. In view of Plato’s

  attack on “arch-Sophists” as being the leaders of

  - 224 -

  all but the perfect [Form] government, one might

  suspect that he insisted upon an absolute standard

  of government just so that he could attribute

  everything less than that to Sophistry. Having

  delivered such an uncomplimentary blow to both

  Sophists and politicians, Plato could quietly

  abandon the notion of an absolute governmental

  standard. In fact, the definition that I just quoted

  is thoroughly relativistic and cannot be applied in

  terms of absolute standards.

  The Sphinx: And just how do you draw that conclusion?

  The Chimæra: If each subordinate art in a community

  possesses its own standard of absolute perfection,

  a raising or lowering of the application of that art

  by the statesman would cause excess or deficiency

  in the art itself. For example, the military art

  involves winning battles and wars. If the

  statesman, for the good of the entire community,

  prevents the military from conducting battles or

  wars, the military art itself experiences a

  deficiency. At a later date, if the military does go to

  war, that deficiency will be evident as inexperience

  in combat. Similarly, if the statesman orders the

  military to fight too many battles or wars, excess

  will occur. The military will become inefficient

  through demoralization and attrition. To permit

  the military to function at an ideal level, a

  statesman would have to allow a level of

  continuous or intermittent warfare. This,

  obviously, would not be ideal for the state as a

  whole.

  - 225 -

  The Sphinx: Your point being that the ideal level of a

  subordinate art as a thing in itself is at odds with

  its ideal application by the statesman’s art.

  The Chimæra: Yes, and there’s more to it than that. If

  there is an ideal standard or level for both

  component arts and the statesman’s art, then the

  maintenance of that standard or level over a

  period of time should ensure continuous and ideal

  prosperity for the state as a whole, correct?

  The Sphinx: Theoretically, yes.

  The Chimæra: But conditions outside that state will

  vary. A neighboring state may go to war against it,

  for example.

  The Sphinx: That would necessitate an alteration of

  certain component arts - such as materiel

  production, resource allocation, and military

  activity - by the statesman, if he is to perform his

  ideal role.

  The Chimæra: But this means exceeding or falling

  below the ideal standards of the individual

  component arts. In other words, the ideal

  standards of a component art by itself and the

  ideal level of that art as a factor in the overall

  community do not coincide. Therefore, if Plato

  insists upon absolute standards, he places his

  statesman in the position of having to

  continuously violate the absolute standards of

  component arts for the sake of his own art.

  The Sphinx: I suppose Plato would argue that the ideal

  standards of the component arts would include

  - 226 -

  consideration for the proper level of those arts

  within the community as a whole.

  The Chimæra: That still begs the question. The posture

  of the community must change as its external

  environment changes. Therefore the component

  arts will be subject to continuous revision of their

  levels of activity and emphasis. They become

  factors relative to the community, just as the

  community becomes a factor relative to its
r />   external environment. Q.E.D.

  The Sphinx: So Plato’s definition of statesmanship is

  valid only if both that art and the subordinate arts

  are assumed to be variable and relativistic. How

  intriguingly Sophistic!

  The Chimæra: ... All of which brings us back to the

  basic “relativity vs. absolutism” issue between

  [what Plato would call] Sophistry and Philosophy

  respectively. In a purely practical sense we cannot

  continue to use those terms as Plato did, because

  “ s o p h i s t r y ” n o w c o n v e y s t h e i m a g e o f

  charlatanism, while “philosophy” embraces

  relativistic as well as absolutist theories.

  The Sphinx: True. The basic issue still remains, but the

  old labels are no longer accurate. Why do you

  suppose Plato felt so strongly that absolute

  standards (Forms) existed?

  The Chimæra: It probably started with what he

  believed to be common sense. Our senses seem to

  tell us that the world around us is made up of

  reliable and permanent phenomena. A chair can

  be counted upon to remain a chair, a desk a desk.

  - 227 -

  The Sun and the planets behave regularly.

  Relativism carried to its logical conclusion would

  deny these things. How could the Sophists say that

  “man is the measure of all things” as they walked

  about on the solid and permanent ground of

  Greece? Man cannot decide that the ground will be

  there one minute and transmute into water the

  next. Plato must have felt that he was arguing a

  case for the way things actually are, even if he

  encountered difficulties in justifying that position

  logically.

  The Sphinx: To be quite precise, a chair does not

  remain a chair nor a desk a desk. Both are

  undergoing continuous molecular breakdown,

  which is not apparent to humans because they

  normally experience sensory input at a relatively

  swifter rate. Nor are astronomical bodies truly

  constant; they only seem that way, again because

  of the relative differences in their rates of change

  and in human perceptive powers. At the other end

  of the scale, there are phenomena that occur too

  swiftly for human senses to register them. So they

  seem “instantaneous”. So how dependable is

  Plato’s “actual world”?

  The Chimæra: I am tempted to say that, relatively

  speaking [from the human point of view], the

  world appears to adhere to absolute laws.

  The Sphinx: Now that is an interesting statement! You

  mean that the human ability to perceive relative

  change exists in a comparatively small range, and

  that phenomena changing at rates beneath or

  above that range appear to be instantaneous or

  permanent, as the case may be.

  - 228 -

  The Chimæra: I suppose so.

  The Sphinx: Can we not identify anything that is truly

  permanent? That is in fact absolute and not

  relative?

  The Chimæra: That was Einstein’s problem. He was

  able to postulate only one thing that was absolute -

  the speed of light. But in that he was wrong.

  The Sphinx: Wrong? Kindly explain!

  The Chimæra: We run the risk of straying rather far

  from The Statesman.

  The Sphinx: But not from our ultimate topic.

  Remember that we are trying to get a grip on true

  conceptual analysis, and to do that we had better

  resolve this relative/absolute issue once and for

  all. According to the Platonic school of thought,

  political science has an absolute standard, just as

  physical laws do. That is the argument of The

  Statesman. So now we have said that Einstein

  reduced physics to only one absolute - the speed of

  light - and you dispute even that. I for one

  consider a resolution of this germane. If you

  destroy absolutism in the physical world, then the

  basis for attempting to parallel the “absolute

  physical world” with an “absolute political world”

  disappears altogether. So proceed.

  The Chimæra: All right. According to Einstein’s second

  fundamental postulate of the Special Theory of

  Relativity, the velocity of light is always constant

  relative to an observer, no matter how fast the

  observer and the light source may be separating or

  - 229 -

  converging. A derived equation states that, when

  an object is moving with respect to an observer,

  the mass of the object becomes greater, the

  amount of increase depending upon the relative

  velocity of object and observer. As the mass of the

  object increases, its length along the axis of its

  direction will decrease. At the speed of light, the

  object’s mass becomes infinite, and its length

  shrinks to zero. Since an infinite-plus amount of

  energy would be required to raise the speed of an

  infinite mass beyond the speed of light, such

  hyper-light speed is not possible.

  The Sphinx: So states the Special Theory.

  The Chimæra: Now, internally the Special Theory is

  consistent, because it treats the speed of light as a

  constant and incorporates a series of equations

  which rely upon that constant and are consistent

  with one another. As the Special Theory applies to

  phenomena which are substantially below the

  speed of light, it is practical. The interrelationship

  of mass and energy relative to 186,000 miles per

  second (the Einstein speed of light constant) has

  been formulated as E=mc2 and put into practice

  through nuclear fission.

  The Sphinx: Where, then, lies the fault?

  The Chimæra: The Achilles’ Heel of the Special Theory

  is that, while applying the principle of relativity to

  everything else except the speed of light, it thereby

  treats the speed of light as an exception to the

  rule. An exception to a rule of physics is an

  indication that the rule is inadequate to cover all

  known phenomena. Einstein’s decision to treat the

  - 230 -

  speed of light as a constant was based upon the

  difference between the speed of light and non-

  light-wave-related phenomena being so vast as to

  make sub-186,000 mps light speed impossible to

  detect; and also upon the inability of science to

  detect anything traveling faster than 186,000

  mps.

  The Sphinx: Why this emphasis upon the word

  “detect”?

  The Chimæra: Detection and existence are two

  different things, and that difference is crucial to

  my argument. Now consider this hypothesis: If

  light waves from a stationary source travel at

  186,000 mps, and those light waves are the only

  means an observer located elsewhere has for

  detection of that source, what would happen if the

  source were to begin moving away from the

  observer at 186,001 mps? Those light waves that

  are the sole source of the observer’s information


  would no longer reach that observer. The waves

  are now receding from him at 1 mps. As far as the

  observer can detect, the light-source vanished

  when its speed exceeded the speed of light. But did

  the source in fact cease to exist? It did not. [And its

  presence may be detectable by observing warps in

  radiation waves and emissions affected by it - a

  possible explanation of the “black hole”

  phenomenon.]

  The Sphinx: What about light-sources that are

  proceeding in directions other than diametrically

  away from an observer?

  - 231 -

  The Chimæra: As for an object approaching an

  observer at 186,000+ mps, it would arrive before it

  could be detected at any distance as a moving

  object, because humans do not possess

  instruments that can identify approaching light

  speeds in excess of 186,000 mps - which would be

  the only means of identifying the object’s

  approach. If the source were to proceed at a

  tangent to an observer, it will seem to compress as

  it approaches the speed of light. The explanation

  for this illusion is more complex, but I may

  approximate it by saying that the lateral

  movement/oscillation of the emitted light waves is

  less detectable as the lateral speed of the object

  approaches 186,000 mps. At 186,000 mps the

  waves are no longer detectable as waves - merely

  as radiation; hence the illusion that the source has

  transmutated from matter to energy.

  The Sphinx: In fact, then, the Special Theory contains

  its own invalidation. It states that everything is

  relative, but it cannot exist as a formula without at

  least one absolute constant - which, upon

  examination, proves to be relative itself. Which

  leaves only one question: If it is wrong, why does

  E=mc2 work?

  The Chimæra: Because the values which are plugged

  into that formula are so far below 186,000 mps

  that the speed of light might as well be treated as a

  constant. For equations that include values closer

  to 186,000 mps, the formula becomes increasingly

  less accurate. Hence the preposterous calculation

  that a mass at 186,000 mps becomes infinite. That

  is simply the result of the formula’s intrinsic

  distortion.

  - 232 -

  The Sphinx: This is all very unsettling. So everything is

  relative?

  The Chimæra: Let’s not jump to conclusions.

  Remember what we decided concerning Plato’s

  own proof of absolute Forms?

  The Sphinx: Yes. I referred to the Platonic Academy’s

 

‹ Prev