Selected Prose of T. S. Eliot

Home > Other > Selected Prose of T. S. Eliot > Page 7
Selected Prose of T. S. Eliot Page 7

by Frank Kermode


  1 Studies in Elizabethan Drama. By Arthur Symons.

  ESSAYS O F GENERAl. I ZA T I O N

  1 9 1 8- 1 9 3 0

  •

  men's mouths . . . she is a woman to the last . . . so she dies . . . the plays

  ends with a touch of grave pity

  :

  . · .

  Presented in this rather unfair way, torn apart like the leaves

  of an artichoke, the impressions of Mr. Symons come to resemble

  a common type of popular literary lecture, in which the stories of

  plays or novels are retold, the motives of the characters set forth,

  and the work of art therefore made easier for the beginner. But

  this is not Mr. Symons' reason for writing. The reason why we

  find a similarity between his essay and this form of education is

  that Antony and Cleopatra is a play with which we are pretty well

  acquainted, and of which we have, therefore, our own impressions. We can please ourselves with our own impressions of the characters and their emotions ; and we do not find the impressions

  of another person, however sensitive, very significant. But if we

  can recall the time when we were ignorant of the French symbolists, and met with The Symbolist Moveme1Zt in Literature, we remember that book as an introduction to wholly new feelings,

  as a revelation. After we have read Verlaine and Laforgue and

  Rimbaud and return to Mr. Symons' book, we may find that our

  own impressions dissent from his. The book has not, perhaps, a

  permanent value for the one reader, but it has led to results of

  permanent importance for him.

  The question is not whether Mr. Symons' impressions are

  'true' or 'false'. So far as you can isolate the 'impression', the pure

  feeling, it is, of course, neither true nor false. The point is that

  you never rest at the pure feeling; you react in one of two ways,

  or, as I believe Mr. Symons does, in a mixture of the two ways.

  The moment you try to put the impressions into words, you

  either begin to analyse and construct, to 'eriger en lois', or you

  begin to create something else. It is significant that Swinburne,

  by whose poetry Mr. Symons may at one time have been influenced, is one man in his poetry and a different man in his criticism ; to this extent and in this respect only, that he is

  satisfying a different impulse ; he is criticizing, expounding,

  arranging. You may say this is not the criticism of a critic, that it

  is emotional, not intellectual - though of this there are two

  opinions, but it is in the direction of analysis and construction, a

  beginning to 'eriger en lois', and not in the direction of creation.

  So I infer that Swinburne found an adequate outlet for the

  creative impulse in his poetry ; and none of it was forced back and

  out through his critical prose. The style of the latter is essentially

  a prose style ; and Mr. Symons' prose is much more like Swinburne's poetry than it is like his prose. I imagine - though here

  �me's thought is moving in almost complete darkness - that Mr.

  52

  THE P ERFECT CR I T I C

  Symons i s far more disturbed, far more profoundly affected, by

  his reading than was Swinburne, who responded rather by a

  violent and immediate and comprehensive burst of admiration

  which may have left him internally unchanged. The disturbance

  in Mr. Symons is almost, but not quite, to the point of creating ;

  the reading sometimes fecundates his emotions to produce something new which is not criticism, but is not the expulsion, the ejection, the birth of creativeness.

  The type is not uncommon, although Mr. Symons is far

  superior to most of the type. Some writers are essentially of the

  type that reacts in excess of the stimulus, making something new

  out of the impressions, but suffer from a defect of vitality or an

  obscure obstruction which prevents nature from taking its course.

  Their sensibility alters the object, but never transforms it. Their

  reaction is that of the ordinary emotional person developed to an

  exceptional degree. For this ordinary emotional person, experiencing a work of art, has a mixed critical and creative reaction.

  It is made up of comment and opinion, and also new emotions

  which are vaguely applied to his own life. The sentimental

  person, in whom a work of art arouses all sorts of emotions which

  have nothing to do with that work of art whatever, but are

  accidents of personal association, is an incomplete artist. For in

  an artist these suggestions made by a work of art, which are

  purely personal, become fused with a multitude of other suggestions from multitudinous experience, and result in the production of a new object which is no longer purely personal, because it is a

  work of art itself.

  It would be rash to speculate, and is perhaps impossible to

  determine, what is unfulfilled in Mr. Symons' charming verse

  that overflows into his critical prose. Certainly we may say that in

  Swinburne's verse the circuit of impression and expression is

  complete ; and Swinburne was therefore able, in his criticism, to

  be more a critic than Mr. Symons. This gives us an intimation

  why the artist is - each within his own limitations - oftenest to be

  depended upon as a critic ; his criticism will be criticism, and not

  the satisfaction of a suppressed creative wish - which, in most

  other persons, is apt to interfere fatally.

  Before considering what the proper critical reaction of artistic

  sensibility is, how far criticism is 'feeling' and how far 'thought',

  and what sort of 'thought' is permitted, it may be instructive to

  prod a little into that other temperament, so different from Mr.

  Symons', which issues in generalities such as that quoted ncar the

  beginning of this article.

  53

  ESSAYS OF GENERAL.I ZATION

  1 9 1 8- 1 9 3 0

  •

  I I "

  'L'ecri1:ain de st)'le abstrait est presque toujours un

  sentimental, du moins un sensitif. L'ecri·vain artiste n'est

  presque jamais un sentimental, et Ires rarement un sensitif.'

  -LE PROBLEME DU STYLE

  The statement already quoted, that 'poetry is the most highly

  organized form of intellectual activity,' may be taken as a specimen of the abstract style in criticism. The confused distinction which exists in most heads between 'abstract' and 'concrete' is

  due not so much to a manifest fact of the existence of two types

  of mind, an abstract and a concrete, as to the existence of another

  type of mind, the verbal, or philosophic. I, of course, do not

  imply any general condemnation of philosophy ; I am, for the

  moment, using the word 'philosophic' to cover the unscientific

  ingredients of philosophy ; to cover, in fact, the greater part of the

  philosophic output of the last hundred years. There are two ways

  in which a word may be 'abstract'. lt may have (the word 'activity',

  for example) a meaning which cannot be grasped by appeal to

  any of the senses ; its apprehension may require a deliberate

  suppression of analogies of visual or muscular experience, which

  is none the less an effort of imagination. 'Activity' will mean for

  the trained scientist, if he employ the term, either nothing at all

  or something still more exact than anythi
ng it suggests to us. If we

  are allowed to accept certain remarks of Pascal and Mr. Bertrand

  Russell about mathematics, we believe that the mathematician

  deals with objects - if he will permit us to call them objects -

  which directly affect his sensibility. And during a good part of

  history the philosopher endeavoured to deal with objects which

  he believed to be of the same exactness as the mathematician's.

  Finally Hegel arrived, and if not perhaps the first, he was certainly the most prodigious exponent of emotional systematization, dealing with his emotions as if they were definite objects which

  had aroused those emotions. His followers have as a rule taken for

  granted that words have definite meanings, overlooking the

  tendency of words to become indefinite emotions. (No one who

  had not witnessed the event could imagine the conviction in the

  tone of Professor Eucken as he pounded the table and exclaimed

  Was ist Geist ? Geist ist . . .

  ) If verbalism were confined to professional philosophers, no harm would be done. But their corruption has extended very far. Compare a mediaeval theologian or mystic, compare a seventeenth-century preacher, with any

  'liberal' sermon since Schleiermacher, and you will observe that

  54

  THE PERFECT CR I T I C

  words have changed their meanings. What they have lost is

  definite, and what they have gained is indefinite.

  The vast accumulations of knowledge - or at least of information - deposited by the nineteenth century have been responsible for an equally vast ignorance. When there is so much to be known,

  when there are so many fields of knowledge in which the same

  words are used with different meanings, when every one knows a

  little about a great many things, it becomes increasingly difficult

  for anyone to know whether he knows what he is talking about

  or not. And when we do not know, or when we do not know

  enough, we tend always to substitute emotions for thoughts. The

  sentence so frequently quoted in this essay will serve for an

  example of this process as well as any, and may be profitably

  contrasted with the opening phrases of the Posterior Analytics.

  Not only all knowledge, but all feeling, is in perception. The

  inventor of poetry as the most highly organized form of intellectual activity was not engaged in perceiving when he composed this definition ; he had nothing to be aware of except his own

  emotion about 'poetry'. He was, in fact, absorbed in a very

  different 'activity' not only from that of Mr. Symons, but from

  that of Aristotle.

  Aristotle is a person who has suffered from the adherence of

  persons who must be regarded less as his disciples than as his

  sectaries. One must be firmly distrustful of accepting Aristotle in

  a canonical spirit ; this is to lose the whole living force of him. He

  was primarily a man of not only remarkable but universal intelligence ; and universal intelligence means that he could apply his intelligence to anything. The ordinary intelligence is good only

  for certain classes of objects ; a brilliant man of science, if he is

  interested in poetry at all, may conceive grotesque judgments :

  like one poet because he reminds him of himself, or another

  because he expresses emotions which he admires ; he may use art,

  in fact, as the outlet for the egotism which is suppressed in his

  own speciality. But Aristotle had none of these impure desires to

  satisfy ; in whatever sphere of interest, he looked solely and steadfastly at the object ; in his short and broken treatise he provides an eternal example - not of laws, or even of method, for there is no

  method except to be very intelligent, but of intelligence itself

  swiftly operating the analysis of sensation to the point of principle

  and definition.

  It is far less Aristotle than Horace who has been the model for

  criticism up to the nineteenth century. A precept, such as Horace,

  or Boileau gives us, is merely an unfinished analysis. It appears as

  a law, a rule, because it does not appear in its most general form ;

  it is empirical. When we understand necessity, as Spinoza knew,

  55

  ESSAYS O F GENERAl,.. I ZA T I O N

  1 9 1 8- 1 93 0

  ·

  we are free because we assent. The dogmatic critic, who lays

  down a rule, who affirms a value, has left his labour incomplete.

  Such statements may often be justifiable as a saving of time ; but

  in matters of great importance the critic must not coerce, and he

  must not make judgments of worse and better. He must simply

  elucidate : the reader will form the correct judgment for himself.

  And again, the purely 'technical' critic - the critic, that is, who

  writes to expound some novelty or impart some lesson to practitioners of an art - can be called a critic only in a narrow sense. He may be analysing perceptions and the means for arousing perceptions, but his aim is limited and is not the disinterested exercise of intelligence. The narrowness of the aim makes easier the

  detection of the merit or feebleness of the work ; even of these

  writers there are very few - so that their 'criticism' is of great

  importance within its limits. So much suffices for Campion.

  Dryden is far more disinterested ; he displays much free intelligence ; and yet even Dryden - or any literary critic of the seventeenth century - is not quite a free mind, compared, for instance, with such a mind as Rochefoucauld's. There is always a tendency

  to legislate rather than to inquire, to revise accepted laws, even to

  overturn, but to reconstruct out of the same material. And the

  free intelligence is that which is wholly devoted to inquiry.

  Coleridge, again, whose natural abilities, and some of whose

  performances, are probably more remarkable than those of any

  other modern critic, cannot be estimated as an intelligence completely free. The nature of the restraint in his case is quite different from that which limited the seventeenth-century critics,

  and is much more personal. Coleridge's metaphysical interest was

  quite genuine, and was, like most metaphysical interest, an affair

  of his emotions. But a literary critic should have no emotions

  except those immediately provoked by a work of art - and these

  (as I have already hinted) are, when valid, perhaps not to be

  called emotions at all. Coleridge is apt to take leave of the data of

  criticism, and arouse the suspicion that he has been diverted into

  a metaphysical hare-and-hounds. His end does not always appear

  to be the return to the work of art with improved perception and

  intensified, because more conscious, enjoyment ; his centre of

  interest changes, his feelings are impure. In the derogatory sense

  he is more 'philosophic' than Aristotle. For everything that

  Aristotle says illuminates the literature which is the occasion for

  saying it ; but Coleridge only now and then. It is one more

  instance of the pernicious effect of emotion.

  Aristotle had what is called the scientific mind - a mind which,

  as it is rarely found among scientists except in fragments, might

  better be called the intelligent mind. For there is no other

  s6

  THE PERFECT CR I T I C

  intelligence than this, and so far as artists and men o f letters are

  intelligent (we may doubt whether the level of intell
igence among

  men of letters is as high as among men of science) their intelligence is of this kind. Sainte-Beuve was a physiologist by training; but it is probable that his mind, like that of the ordinary scientific

  specialist, was limited in its interest, and that this was not,

  primarily, an interest in art. If he was a critic, there is no doubt

  that he was a very good one ; but we may conclude that he earned

  some other name. Of all modern critics, perhaps Remy de

  Gourmont had most of the general intelligence of Aristotle. An

  amateur, though an excessively able amateur, in physiology, he

  combined to a remarkable degree sensitiveness, erudition, sense of

  fact and sense of history, and generalizing power.

  We assume the gift of a superior sensibility. And for sensibility

  wide and profound reading does not mean merely a more extended pasture. There is not merely an increase of understanding, leaving the original acute impression unchanged. The new

  impressions modify the impressions received from the objects

  already known. An impression needs to be constantly refreshed

  by new impressions in order that it may persist at all ; it needs to

  take its place in a system of impressions. And this system tends

  to become articulate in a generalized statement of literary beauty.

  There are, for instance, many scattered lines and tercets in the

  Divine Comedy which are capable of transporting even a quite

  uninitiated reader, just sufficiently acquainted with the roots of

  the language to decipher the meaning, to an impression of overpowering beauty. This impression may be so deep that no subsequent study and understanding will intensify it. But at this point the impression is emotional ; the reader in the ignorance which we

  postulate is unable to distinguish the poetry from an emotional

  state aroused in himself by the poetry, a state which may be

  merely an indulgence of his own emotions. The poetry may be an

  accidental stimulus. The end of the enjoyment of poetry is a pure

  contemplation from which all the accidents of personal emotion

  are removed ; thus we aim to see the object as it really is and find a

  meaning for the words of Arnold. And without a labour which is

  largely a labour of the intelligence, we are unable to attain that

  stage of vision amor intellectualis Dei.

 

‹ Prev