Army of None

Home > Other > Army of None > Page 16
Army of None Page 16

by Paul Scharre


  But the operators in the Patriot trailer didn’t know this. All they saw was a ballistic missile headed their way. In response, the commander ordered the battery to bring its launchers from “standby” to “operate.”

  The unit was operating in manual mode for anti-radiation missiles, but auto-fire mode for ballistic missiles. As soon as the launcher became operational, the auto-fire system engaged: BOOM-BOOM. Two PAC-3 missiles launched automatically.

  The two PAC-3 missiles steered toward the incoming ballistic missile, or at least to the spot where the ground-based radar told them it should be. The missiles activated their seekers to look for the incoming ballistic missile, but there was no missile.

  Tragically, the missiles’ seekers did find something: a U.S. Navy F/A-18C Hornet fighter jet nearby. The jet was piloted by Lieutenant Nathan White, who was simply in the wrong place at the wrong time. White’s F-18 was squawking IFF and he showed up on the Patriot’s radar as an aircraft. It didn’t matter. The PAC-3 missiles locked onto White’s aircraft. White saw the missiles coming and called it out over the radio. He took evasive action, but there was nothing he could do. Seconds later, both missiles struck his aircraft, killing him instantly.

  ASSESSING THE PATRIOT’S PERFORMANCE

  The Patriot fratricides are an example of the risks of operating complex, highly automated lethal systems. In a strict operational sense, the Patriot units accomplished their mission. Over sixty Patriot fire units were deployed during the initial phase of the war, forty from the United States and twenty-two from four coalition nations. Their mission was to protect ground troops from Iraqi ballistic missiles, which they did. Nine Iraqi ballistic missiles were fired at coalition forces; all were successfully engaged by Patriots. No coalition troops were harmed from Iraqi missiles. A Defense Science Board Task Force on the Patriot’s performance concluded that, with respect to missile defense, the Patriot was a “substantial success.”

  On the other hand, in addition to these nine successful engagements, Patriots were involved in three fratricides: two incidents in which Patriots shot down friendly aircraft, killing the pilots, and a third incident in which an F-16 fired on a Patriot. Thus, of the twelve total engagements involving Patriots, 25 percent were fratricides, an “unacceptable” fratricide rate according to Army investigators.

  The reasons for the Patriot fratricides were a complex mix of human error, improper testing, poor training, and unforeseen interactions on the battlefield. Some problems were known—IFF was well understood to be an imperfect solution for preventing fratricides. Other problems, such as the potential for the Patriot to misclassify an aircraft as an anti-radiation missile, had been identified during operational testing but had not been corrected and were not included in operator training. Still other issues, such as the potential for electromagnetic interference to cause a false radar track, were novel and unexpected. Some of these complications were preventable, but others were not. War entails uncertainty. Even the best training and operational testing can only approximate the actual conditions of war. Inevitably, soldiers will face wartime conditions where the environment, adversary innovation, and simply the chaos, confusion, and violence of war all contribute to unexpected challenges. Many things that seem simple in training often look far different in the maw of combat.

  One thing that did not happen and was not a cause of the Patriot fratricides is that the Patriot system did not fail, per se. It didn’t break. It didn’t blow a fuse. The system performed its function: it tracked incoming targets and, when authorized, shot them down. Also, in both instances a human was required to give the command to fire or at least to bring the launchers to operate. When this lethal, highly automated system was placed in the hands of operators who did not fully understand its capabilities and limitations, however, it turned deadly. Not because the operators were negligent. No one was found to be at fault in either incident. It would be overly simplistic to blame the fratricides on “human error.” Instead, what happened was more insidious. Army investigators determined the Patriot community had a culture of “trusting the system without question.” According to Army researchers, the Patriot operators, while nominally in control, exhibited automation bias: an “unwarranted and uncritical trust in automation. In essence, control responsibility is ceded to the machine.” There may have been a human “in the loop,” but the human operators didn’t question the machine when they should have. They didn’t exercise the kind of judgment Stanislav Petrov did when he questioned the signals his system was giving him regarding a false launch of U.S. nuclear missiles. The Patriot operators trusted the machine, and it was wrong.

  ROBUTOPIA VS. ROBOPOCALYPSE

  We have two intuitions when it comes to autonomous systems, intuitions that come partly from science fiction but also from our everyday experiences with phones, computers, cars, and myriad other computerized devices.

  The first intuition is that autonomous systems are reliable and introduce greater precision. Just as autopilots have improved air travel safety, automation can also improve safety and reliability in many other domains. Humans are terrible drivers, for example, killing more than 30,000 people a year in the United States alone (roughly the equivalent of a 9/11 attack every month). Even without fully autonomous cars, more advanced vehicle autopilots that allow cars to drive themselves under most conditions could dramatically improve safety and save lives.

  However, we have another instinct when it comes to autonomous systems, and that is one of robots run amok, autonomous systems that slip out of human control and result in disastrous outcomes. These fears are fed to us through a steady diet of dystopian science fiction stories in which murderous AIs turn on humans, from 2001: A Space Odyssey’s HAL 9000 to Ex Machina’s Ava. But these intuitions also come from our everyday experiences with simple automated devices. Anyone who has ever been frustrated with an automated telephone call support helpline, an alarm clock mistakenly set to “p.m.” instead of “a.m.,” or any of the countless frustrations that come with interacting with computers, has experienced the problem of “brittleness” that plagues automated systems. Autonomous systems will do precisely what they are programmed to do, and it is this quality that makes them both reliable and maddening, depending on whether what they were programmed to do was the right thing at that point in time.

  Both of our intuitions are correct. With proper design, testing, and use, autonomous systems can often perform tasks far better than humans. They can be faster, more reliable, and more precise. However, if they are placed into situations for which they were not designed, if they aren’t fully tested, if operators aren’t properly trained, or if the environment changes, then autonomous systems can fail. When they do fail, they often fail badly. Unlike humans, autonomous systems lack the ability to step outside their instructions and employ “common sense” to adapt to the situation at hand.

  This problem of brittleness was highlighted during a telling moment in the 2011 Jeopardy! Challenge in which IBM’s Watson AI took on human Jeopardy champions Ken Jennings and Brad Rutter. Toward the end of the first game, Watson momentarily stumbled in its rout of Jennings and Rutter in response to a clue in the “Name the Decade” category. The clue was, “The first modern crossword is published and Oreo cookies are introduced.” Jennings rang in first with the answer, “What are the 20s?” Wrong, said host Alex Trebek. Immediately afterward, Watson rang in and gave the same answer, “What is 1920s?” A befuddled Trebek testily replied, “No, Ken said that.”

  I’m not particularly good at Jeopardy, but even I knew, “What are the 1920s?” was the wrong answer once Jennings guessed wrong. (The correct answer is the 1910s.) Watson hadn’t been programmed to listen to other contestants’ wrong answers and adjust accordingly, however. Processing Jennings’ answer was outside of the bounds of Watson’s design. Watson was superb at answering Jeopardy questions under most conditions, but its design was brittle. When an atypical event occurred that Watson’s design didn’t account for, such as Ken Jennin
gs getting a wrong answer, Watson couldn’t adapt on the fly. As a result, Watson’s performance suddenly plummeted from superhuman to super-dumb.

  Brittleness can be managed when the person using an autonomous system understands the boundaries of the system—what it can and cannot do. The user can either steer the system away from situations outside the bounds of its design or knowingly account for and accept the risks of failure. In this case, Watson’s designers understood this limitation. They just didn’t think that the ability to learn from other contestants’ wrong answers would be important. “We just didn’t think it would ever happen,” one of Watson’s programmers said afterward. Watson’s programmers were probably right to discount the importance of this ability. The momentary stumble proved inconsequential. Watson handily defeated its human counterparts.

  Problems can arise when human users don’t anticipate these moments of brittleness, however. This was the case with the Patriot fratricides. The system had vulnerabilities—misclassifying an anti-radiation missile as an aircraft, IFF failures, and electromagnetic interference causing “ghost track” ballistic missiles—that the human operators were either unaware of or didn’t sufficiently account for. As a result, the human user’s expectations and the system’s actual behavior were not in alignment. The operators thought the system was targeting missiles when it was actually targeting aircraft.

  AUTONOMY AND RISK

  One of the ways to compensate for the brittle nature of automated systems is to retain tight control over their operation. If the system fails, humans can rapidly intervene to correct it or halt its operation. Tighter human control reduces the autonomy, or freedom, of the machine.

  Immediate human intervention is possible for semiautonomous and human-supervised systems. Just because humans can intervene, however, doesn’t mean they always do so when they should. In the case of the Patriot fratricides, humans were “in the loop,” but they didn’t sufficiently question the automation. Humans can’t act as an independent fail-safe if they cede their judgment to the machine.

  Effective human intervention may be even more challenging in supervised autonomous systems, where the system does not pause to wait for human input. The human’s ability to actually regain control of the system in real time depends heavily on the speed of operations, the amount of information available to the human, and any time delays between the human’s actions and the system’s response. Giving a driver the ability to grab the wheel of an autonomous vehicle traveling at highway speeds in dense traffic, for example, is merely the illusion of control, particularly if the operator is not paying attention. This appears to have been the case in a 2016 fatality involving a Tesla Model S that crashed while driving on autopilot.

  For fully autonomous systems, the human is out of the loop and cannot intervene at all, at least for some period of time. This means that if the system fails or the context changes, the result could be a runaway autonomous process beyond human control with no ability to halt or correct it.

  This danger of autonomous systems is best illustrated not with a science fiction story, but with a Disney cartoon. The Sorcerer’s Apprentice is an animated short in Disney’s 1940 film Fantasia. In the story, which is an adaptation of an eighteenth-century poem by Goethe, Mickey Mouse plays the apprentice of an old sorcerer. When the sorcerer leaves for the day, Mickey decides to use his novice magic to automate his chores. Mickey enchants a broomstick, causing it to sprout arms and come to life. Mickey commands the broomstick to carry pails of water from the well to a cistern, a chore Mickey is supposed to be doing. Soon, Mickey is nodding off, his chores automated.

  As Mickey sleeps, the cistern overfills. The job is done, but no one told the broomstick to stop. Mickey wakes to find the room flooded and the broomstick fetching more water. He commands the broomstick to halt, but it doesn’t comply. Desperate, Mickey snatches an axe from the wall and chops the broomstick to pieces, but the splinters reanimate into a horde of broomsticks. They march forth to bring even more water, an army of rogue autonomous agents out of control. Finally, the madness is stopped only by the return of the sorcerer himself, who disperses the water and halts the broomsticks with a wave of his arms.

  With the original German poem written in 1797, The Sorcerer’s Apprentice may be the first example of autonomy displacing jobs. It also shows the danger of automation. An autonomous system may not perform a task in the manner we want. This could occur for a variety of reasons: malfunction, user error, unanticipated interactions with the environment, or hacking. In the case of Mickey’s problem, the “software” (instructions) that he bewitched the broomstick with were flawed because he didn’t specify when to stop. Overfilling the cistern might have been only a minor annoyance if it had happened once, however. A semiautonomous process that paused for Mickey’s authorization after each trip to the well would have been far safer. Having a human “in the loop” would have mitigated the danger from the faulty software design. The human can act like a circuit breaker, catching harmful events before they cascade out of control. Making the broomstick fully autonomous without a human in the loop wasn’t the cause of the failure, but it did dramatically increase the consequences if something went wrong. Because of this potential to have a runaway process, fully autonomous systems are inherently more hazardous than semiautonomous ones.

  Putting an autonomous system into operation means accepting the risk that it may perform its task incorrectly. Fully autonomous systems are not necessarily more likely to fail than semiautonomous or supervised autonomous ones, but if they do, the consequences—the potential damage caused by the system—could be severe.

  TRUST, BUT VERIFY

  Activating an autonomous system is an act of trust. The user trusts that the system will function in the manner that he or she expects. Trust isn’t blind faith, however. As the Patriot fratricides demonstrated, too much trust can be just as dangerous as too little. Human users need to trust the system just the right amount. They need to understand both the capabilities and limitations of the system. This is why Bradford Tousley from DARPA TTO cited test and evaluation as his number one concern. A rigorous testing regime can help designers and operators better understand how the system performs under realistic conditions. Bob Work similarly told me that test and evaluation was “central” to building trustworthy autonomous systems. “When you delegate authority to a machine, it’s got to be repeatable,” he said. “The same outcome has to happen over and over and over again. . . . So, what is going to be our test and evaluation regime for these smarter and smarter weapons to make sure that the weapon stays within the parameters of what we expect it to do? That’s an issue.”

  The problem is that, even with simulations that test millions of scenarios, fully testing all of the possible scenarios a complex autonomous system might encounter is effectively impossible. There are simply too many possible interactions between the system and its environment and even within the system itself. Mickey should have been able to anticipate the cistern overflowing, but some real-world problems cannot be anticipated. The game of Go has more possible positions than atoms in the universe, and the real world is far more complex than Go. A 2015 Air Force report on autonomy bemoaned the problem:

  Traditional methods . . . fail to address the complexities associated with autonomy software . . . There are simply too many possible states and combination of states to be able to exhaustively test each one.

  In addition to the sheer numerical problem of evaluating all possible combinations, testing is also limited by the testers’ imagination. In games like chess or go, the set of possible actions is limited. In the real world, however, autonomous systems will encounter any number of novel situations: new kinds of human error, unexpected environmental conditions, or creative actions by adversaries looking to exploit vulnerabilities. If these scenarios can’t be anticipated, they can’t be tested.

  Testing is vital to building confidence in how autonomous systems will behave in real-world environments, but no amount of t
esting can entirely eliminate the potential for unanticipated behaviors. Sometimes these unanticipated behaviors may pleasantly surprise users, like AlphaGo’s 1 in 10,000 move that stunned human champion Lee Sedol. Sometimes these unanticipated actions can be negative. During Gary Kasparov’s first game against Deep Blue in 1997, a bug in Deep Blue caused it to make a nonsense random move in the forty-fourth move of the game. One of Deep Blue’s programmers later explained, “We had seen it once before, in a test game played earlier in 1997, and thought it was fixed. Unfortunately, there was one case that we had missed.” When playing games like Jeopardy, chess, or go, surprising behaviors may be tolerable, even interesting flukes. When operating high-risk automated systems where life or death is at stake, unexpected actions can lead to tragic accidents, such as the Patriot fratricides.

  WHEN ACCIDENTS ARE NORMAL

  To better understand the risks of autonomous weapons, I spoke with John Borrie from the UN Institute for Disarmament Research (UNIDIR). UNIDIR is an independent research institute within the United Nations that focuses on arms control and disarmament issues. Borrie authored a recent UNIDIR report on autonomous weapons and risk and he’s worked extensively on arms control and disarmament issues in a variety of capacities—for the New Zealand government, the International Committee of the Red Cross, and UNIDIR—and on a host of technologies: cryptography, chemical and biological weapons, and autonomy. This made him well positioned to understand the relative risks of autonomous weapons.

  Borrie and I sat down on the sidelines of the UN talks on autonomous weapons in Geneva in 2016. Borrie is not an advocate for a preemptive ban on autonomous weapons and in general has the sober demeanor of a professor, not a firebrand activist. He speaks passionately (though in an even-tempered, professorial cadence) in his lilting New Zealand accent. I could imagine myself pleasantly nodding off in his class, even as he calmly warned of the dangers of robots run amok.

 

‹ Prev