Various Works

Home > Nonfiction > Various Works > Page 125
Various Works Page 125

by Aristotle


  knowledge' both intends, and by his language indicates, the property

  that belongs by nature, and so 'an animal capable of receiving

  knowledge' would not be upset or shown in that respect not to be a

  property of man.

  Moreover, as regards all the things that are called as they are

  primarily after something else, or primarily in themselves, it is a

  job to render the property of such things. For if you render a

  property as belonging to the subject that is so called after something

  else, then it will be true of its primary subject as well; whereas

  if you state it of its primary subject, then it will be predicated

  also of the thing that is so called after this other. Thus (e.g.) if

  any one renders , coloured' as the property of 'surface', 'coloured'

  will be true of body as well; whereas if he render it of 'body', it

  will be predicated also of 'surface'. Hence the name as well will

  not be true of that of which the description is true.

  In the case of some properties it mostly happens that some error

  is incurred because of a failure to define how as well as to what

  things the property is stated to belong. For every one tries to render

  as the property of a thing something that belongs to it either

  naturally, as 'biped' belongs to 'man', or actually, as 'having four

  fingers' belongs to a particular man, or specifically, as

  'consisting of most rarefied particles' belongs to 'fire', or

  absolutely, as 'life' to 'living being', or one that belongs to a

  thing only as called after something else, as 'wisdom' to the

  'soul', or on the other hand primarily, as 'wisdom' to the 'rational

  faculty', or because the thing is in a certain state, as

  'incontrovertible by argument' belongs to a 'scientist' (for simply

  and solely by reason of his being in a certain state will he be

  'incontrovertible by argument'), or because it is the state

  possessed by something, as 'incontrovertible by argument' belongs to

  'science', or because it is partaken of, as 'sensation' belongs to

  'animal' (for other things as well have sensation, e.g. man, but

  they have it because they already partake of 'animal'), or because

  it partakes of something else, as 'life' belongs to a particular

  kind of 'living being'. Accordingly he makes a mistake if he has

  failed to add the word 'naturally', because what belongs naturally may

  fail to belong to the thing to which it naturally belongs, as (e.g.)

  it belongs to a man to have two feet: so too he errs if he does not

  make a definite proviso that he is rendering what actually belongs,

  because one day that attribute will not be what it now is, e.g. the

  man's possession of four fingers. So he errs if he has not shown

  that he states a thing to be such and such primarily, or that he calls

  it so after something else, because then its name too will not be true

  of that of which the description is true, as is the case with

  'coloured', whether rendered as a property of 'surface' or of

  'body'. So he errs if he has not said beforehand that he has

  rendered a property to a thing either because that thing possesses a

  state, or because it is a state possessed by something; because then

  it will not be a property. For, supposing he renders the property to

  something as being a state possessed, it will belong to what possesses

  that state; while supposing he renders it to what possesses the state,

  it will belong to the state possessed, as did 'incontrovertible by

  argument' when stated as a property of 'science' or of the

  'scientist'. So he errs if he has not indicated beforehand that the

  property belongs because the thing partakes of, or is partaken of

  by, something; because then the property will belong to certain

  other things as well. For if he renders it because its subject is

  partaken of, it will belong to the things which partake of it; whereas

  if he renders it because its subject partakes of something else, it

  will belong to the things partaken of, as (e.g.) if he were to state

  'life' to be a property of a 'particular kind of living being', or

  just of 'living being. So he errs if he has not expressly

  distinguished the property that belongs specifically, because then

  it will belong only to one of the things that fall under the term of

  which he states the property: for the superlative belongs only to

  one of them, e.g. 'lightest' as applied to 'fire'. Sometimes, too, a

  man may even add the word 'specifically', and still make a mistake.

  For the things in question should all be of one species, whenever

  the word 'specifically' is added: and in some cases this does not

  occur, as it does not, in fact, in the case of fire. For fire is not

  all of one species; for live coals and flame and light are each of

  them 'fire', but are of different species. The reason why, whenever

  'specifically' is added, there should not be any species other than

  the one mentioned, is this, that if there be, then the property in

  question will belong to some of them in a greater and to others in a

  less degree, as happens with 'consisting of most rarefied particles'

  in the case of fire: for 'light' consists of more rarefied particles

  than live coals and flame. And this should not happen unless the

  name too be predicated in a greater degree of that of which the

  description is truer; otherwise the rule that where the description is

  truer the name too should be truer is not fulfilled. Moreover, in

  addition to this, the same attribute will be the property both of

  the term which has it absolutely and of that element therein which has

  it in the highest degree, as is the condition of the property

  'consisting of most rarefied particles' in the case of 'fire': for

  this same attribute will be the property of 'light' as well: for it is

  'light' that 'consists of the most rarefied particles'. If, then,

  any one else renders a property in this way one should attack it;

  for oneself, one should not give occasion for this objection, but

  should define in what manner one states the property at the actual

  time of making the statement.

  Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has stated a thing as a

  property of itself: for then what has been stated to be a property

  will not be a property. For a thing itself always shows its own

  essence, and what shows the essence is not a property but a

  definition. Thus (e.g.) he who has said that 'becoming' is a

  property of 'beautiful' has rendered the term as a property of

  itself (for 'beautiful' and 'becoming' are the same); and so

  'becoming' could not be a property of 'beautiful'. For constructive

  purposes, on the other hand, see if he has avoided rendering a thing

  as a property of itself, but has yet stated a convertible predicate:

  for then what is stated not to be a property will be a property.

  Thus he who has stated 'animate substance' as a property of

  'living-creature' has not stated 'living-creature' as a property of

  itself, but has rendered a convertible predicate, so that 'animate

  substance' would be a property of 'living-creature'.

  Next, in the case of things consisting of
like parts, you should

  look and see, for destructive purposes, if the property of the whole

  be not true of the part, or if that of the part be not predicated of

  the whole: for then what has been stated to be the property will not

  be a property. In some cases it happens that this is so: for sometimes

  in rendering a property in the case of things that consist of like

  parts a man may have his eye on the whole, while sometimes he may

  address himself to what is predicated of the part: and then in neither

  case will it have been rightly rendered. Take an instance referring to

  the whole: the man who has said that it is a property of the 'sea'

  to be 'the largest volume of salt water', has stated the property of

  something that consists of like parts, but has rendered an attribute

  of such a kind as is not true of the part (for a particular sea is not

  'the largest volume of salt water'); and so the largest volume of salt

  water' could not be a property of the 'sea'. Now take one referring to

  the part: the man who has stated that it is a property of 'air' to

  be 'breathable' has stated the property of something that consists

  of like parts, but he has stated an attribute such as, though true

  of some air, is still not predicable of the whole (for the whole of

  the air is not breathable); and so 'breathable' could not be a

  property of 'air'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see

  whether, while it is true of each of the things with similar parts, it

  is on the other hand a property of them taken as a collective whole:

  for then what has been stated not to be a property will be a property.

  Thus (e.g.) while it is true of earth everywhere that it naturally

  falls downwards, it is a property of the various particular pieces

  of earth taken as 'the Earth', so that it would be a property of

  'earth' 'naturally to fall downwards'.

  6

  Next, look from the point of view of the respective opposites, and

  first (a) from that of the contraries, and see, for destructive

  purposes, if the contrary of the term rendered fails to be a

  property of the contrary subject. For then neither will the contrary

  of the first be a property of the contrary of the second. Thus

  (e.g.) inasmuch as injustice is contrary to justice, and the lowest

  evil to the highest good, but 'to be the highest good' is not a

  property of 'justice', therefore 'to be the lowest evil' could not

  be a property of 'injustice'. For constructive purposes, on the

  other hand, see if the contrary is the property of the contrary: for

  then also the contrary of the first will be the property of the

  contrary of the second. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as evil is contrary to

  good, and objectionable to desirable, and 'desirable' is a property of

  'good', 'objectionable' would be a property of 'evil'.

  Secondly (h) look from the point of view of relative opposites and

  see, for destructive purposes, if the correlative of the term rendered

  fails to be a property of the correlative of the subject: for then

  neither will the correlative of the first be a property of the

  correlative of the second. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'double' is

  relative to 'half', and 'in excess' to 'exceeded', while 'in excess'

  is not a property of 'double', exceeded' could not be a property of

  'half'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the

  correlative of the alleged property is a property of the subject's

  correlative: for then also the correlative of the first will be a

  property of the correlative of the second: e.g. inasmuch as 'double'

  is relative to 'half', and the proportion 1:2 is relative to the

  proportion 2:1, while it is a property of 'double' to be 'in the

  proportion of 2 to 1', it would be a property of 'half' to be 'in

  the proportion of 1 to 2'.

  Thirdly (c) for destructive purposes, see if an attribute

  described in terms of a state (X) fails to be a property of the

  given state (Y): for then neither will the attribute described in

  terms of the privation (of X) be a property of the privation (of Y).

  Also if, on the other hand, an attribute described in terms of the

  privation (of X) be not a property of the given privation (of Y),

  neither will the attribute described in terms of the state (X) be a

  property of the state (Y). Thus, for example, inasmuch as it is not

  predicated as a property of 'deafness' to be a 'lack of sensation',

  neither could it be a property of 'hearing' to be a 'sensation'. For

  constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if an attribute

  described in terms of a state (X) is a property of the given state

  (Y): for then also the attribute that is described in terms of the

  privation (of X) will be a property of the privation (of Y). Also,

  if an attribute described in terms of a privation (of X) be a property

  of the privation (of Y), then also the attribute that is described

  in terms of the state (X) will be a property of the state (Y). Thus

  (e.g.) inasmuch as 'to see' is a property of 'sight', inasmuch as we

  have sight, 'failure to see' would be a property of 'blindness',

  inasmuch as we have not got the sight we should naturally have.

  Next, look from the point of view of positive and negative terms;

  and first (a) from the point of view of the predicates taken by

  themselves. This common-place rule is useful only for a destructive

  purpose. Thus (e.g.) see if the positive term or the attribute

  described in terms of it is a property of the subject: for then the

  negative term or the attribute described in terms of it will not be

  a property of the subject. Also if, on the other hand, the negative

  term or the attribute described in terms of it is a property of the

  subject, then the positive term or the attribute described in terms of

  it will not be a property of the subject: e.g. inasmuch as 'animate'

  is a property of 'living creature', 'inanimate' could not be a

  property of 'living creature'.

  Secondly (b) look from the point of view of the predicates, positive

  or negative, and their respective subjects; and see, for destructive

  purposes, if the positive term falls to be a property of the

  positive subject: for then neither will the negative term be a

  property of the negative subject. Also, if the negative term fails

  to be a property of the negative subject, neither will the positive

  term be a property of the positive subject. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as

  'animal' is not a property of 'man', neither could 'not-animal' be a

  property of 'not-man'. Also if 'not-animal' seems not to be a property

  of 'not-man', neither will 'animal' be a property of 'man'. For

  constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the positive term

  is a property of the positive subject: for then the negative term will

  be a property of the negative subject as well. Also if the negative

  term be a property of the negative subject, the positive will be a

  property of the positive as well. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is a

  property of 'not-living being' 'not to live', it would be a property

  of 'living being' 'to live': also if it seems to be a property of

  'living b
eing' 'to live', it will also seem to be a property of

  'not-living being' 'not to live'.

  Thirdly (c) look from the point of view of the subjects taken by

  themselves, and see, for destructive purposes, if the property

  rendered is a property of the positive subject: for then the same term

  will not be a property of the negative subject as well. Also, if the

  term rendered be a property of the negative subject, it will not be

  a property of the positive. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'animate' is a

  property of 'living creature', 'animate' could not be a property of

  'not-living creature'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand,

  if the term rendered fails to be a property of the affirmative subject

  it would be a property of the negative. This commonplace rule is,

  however, deceptive: for a positive term is not a property of a

  negative, or a negative of a positive. For a positive term does not

  belong at all to a negative, while a negative term, though it

  belongs to a positive, does not belong as a property.

  Next, look from the point of view of the coordinate members of a

  division, and see, for destructive purposes, if none of the

  co-ordinate members (parallel with the property rendered) be a

  property of any of the remaining set of co-ordinate members

  (parallel with the subject): for then neither will the term stated

  be a property of that of which it is stated to be a property. Thus

  (e.g.) inasmuch as 'sensible living being' is not a property of any of

  the other living beings, 'intelligible living being' could not be a

  property of God. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see

  if some one or other of the remaining co-ordinate members (parallel

  with the property rendered) be a property of each of these co-ordinate

  members (parallel with the subject): for then the remaining one too

  will be a property of that of which it has been stated not to be a

  property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is a property of 'wisdom' to be

  essentially 'the natural virtue of the rational faculty', then, taking

  each of the other virtues as well in this way, it would be a

  property of 'temperance' to be essentially 'the natural virtue of

  the faculty of desire'.

 

‹ Prev