Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion

Home > Other > Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion > Page 47
Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion Page 47

by John W. Loftus

According to the first lines in the Qur'an, Allah (simply the Arabic for "god") is

  beneficent and merciful, a judge, and one who keeps humans on the right path.

  More specifically, Islam provides the standard for determining what behaviors

  are good or bad. An action is fard if it is obligatory; performing the action is

  meritorious, and not performing it is punishable. An action is halal if it is

  allowed or permitted, but not required; performing the action is neither good nor

  bad, moral nor immoral. An action is makruh if it is disapproved, though not

  forbidden. Finally, an action is haram if it is forbidden or prohibited or unlawful;

  performing the action has negative religious consequences.

  Among the foods that are halal are milk, honey, fish, fruits, vegetables, and

  meat-as long as it is sacrificed according to Muslim ritual (throat slit and drained

  of blood, never strangled or bludgeoned to death). A foodstuff is haram if it

  contains or comes into contact with blood, pigs, dogs, reptiles, alcohol, animals

  with protruding canine teeth, or animals won by betting or gambling. But

  ingestion is hardly the only area of moral concern. A man should not wear gold

  ornaments or silk clothes, although a woman may; women should not wear tight

  or transparent clothing, and in more than a few societies, should be veiled from

  head to toe to show their modesty and preserve their honor. No one should alter

  their physical features in pursuit of beauty, and all excess is disapproved. Gold

  and silver utensils are haram, as are pure silk sheets and bedspreads. Keeping

  dogs inside the house as pets is forbidden, too, as are songs that praise wine and

  encourage drinking, all forms of gambling and lottery, and movies that depict or

  incite sex, greed, crime, deviance, or false belief.

  Just to show how very "moral" Islam is, in May 2009 Saudi Arabia actually

  held a "Miss Beautiful Morals" pageant. The contestants were all heavily veiled,

  as is proper, since the women were not being judged on their physical beauty

  (and would definitely not be seen in bathing suits by strange men). Rather, as

  pageant founder Khadra al-Mubarak asserted, "The idea of the pageant is to

  measure the contestants' commitment to Islamic morals.... The winner won't

  necessarily be pretty. We care about the beauty of the soul and the morals."20

  And the categories in which the women were judged included "discovering your

  inner strength," "the making of leaders," and "Mom, paradise is at your feet."

  Now there is a commitment to morality the likes of which Western Christianity

  has not achieved.

  Outside the Western/Abrahamic religions, Hinduism is premised on the

  concept of dharnaa, the transcendent order of the universe and the duty that it

  imposes on humans. Failure to act in accordance with the dharma generates

  karma, which functions like a kind of moral weight or dirt or rust on the atman

  or soul. The entire caste system, the division of society into different and

  unequal social and occupational groups, is a moral imperative, resting on the

  spiritual purity or impurity of individuals; and many moral regulations go along

  with it, including who may or may not marry or even eat with someone else.

  One's specific moral demands depend on one's caste status: if one is pariah, one's

  moral duty is to perform dirty jobs; and if one is kshatriya, one's moral duty is to

  lead, to fight, to kill, and to die. The Bhagavad Gita, the beloved sacred tale of

  the warrior Arjuna, affirms that neither killing nor dying is a moral problem for

  the kshatriya warrior, since it is by definition meritorious, even mandatory, that a

  soldier slay and be slain and, even more fundamentally, the soul cannot be

  injured by death anyhow.

  Buddhism has an elaborate and demanding set of behavioral strictures; one

  could argue with justification that Buddhism is more morality than religion. The

  very beginning of the Buddha's teaching is the "Eightfold Path," the discipline to

  observe right view, right intention, right speech, right action, right livelihood,

  right effort, right mindfulness, and right concentration. These "rights" go beyond

  the Judeo-Christian requirement to eschew lies and false witness: to observe

  right speech, the Buddhist must abstain from lies and deceit as well as slander

  and malicious words as well as harsh or hurtful words as well as idle chatter. But

  the Eightfold Path is only the most general of moral rules. The Buddhist should

  obey the ten precepts, to avoid harming any living thing, taking anything not

  freely given, misbehaving sexually, speaking falsely, ingesting alcohol or drugs,

  eating untimely meals, dancing/singing/miming, using garlands or perfumes or

  other adornments, sitting in high seats, and accepting gold or silver. Actually, the

  list of Buddhist ethical regulations is much more extensive.

  Jainism may have the most stringent morality of all. A religion related to

  Hinduism and Buddhism, Jainism condemns all injuring of all living beings,

  even insects and microbes-the concept of ahimsa or no-harm. This is why some

  Jains can be seen wearing masks and drinking through a strainer lest they

  swallow an insect, or sweeping the path ahead of them with a small broom lest

  they trample one. Ajain must minimally be a vegetarian, but that is only the

  beginning: they should eat only plants that are already dead, so as to avoid

  injuring the plant. They cannot be farmers because farming harms living things;

  they should not be blacksmiths because the hammering hurts the anvil and the

  bench. They must also, like Buddhists, avoid attachment to life, whether this be

  food, clothing, family members, or their own body. Jams who commit

  themselves to a more rigorous religious life also renounce travel, owning

  weapons, eating during night time, and contact with their spouse; they pledge to

  meditate frequently during the day, live a monk's life as frilly as possible, and

  ultimately become a complete ascetic by dwelling naked in the forest and dying

  proudly of self-starvation.

  These are only some of the major "world religions." Every ancient and tribal

  religion included its own moral standards, some similar to Christianity, some

  foreign to Christianity, some absurd to Christianity. And the feeling was mutual.

  MORALITY WITHOUT RELIGION

  While religions have a lot-and a lot of different-moral compunctions, morality is

  not limited to religion. If we understand morality properly, as one expression of

  the human concern to organize one's (and others') behavior according to

  standards of appraisal, then there are at least four other potential bases for moral

  determination and moral evaluation: nature, reason, philosophy, and culture.

  There are many people who assert that morality is "natural" or "real" or

  "objective," and therefore independent of religion; in fact, they use (supposedly)

  natural/real/objective standards to judge, and often to reject, religious "morality."

  I am not, for reasons not manageable in this chapter but hopefully obvious in this

  chapter, one of these people; morality is too diverse and contradictory to be

  natural or real or objective, and the total lack of agreement on moral answers-or

  even moral questionscontradicts the noti
on of a single "real" morality (as it does

  the notion of a single "real" language). Nevertheless, for those who use nature or

  reality as their standard of moral judgment, theirs is no more inadequate and no

  more ridiculous than some religious standard.21

  Related to the idea of real morality is the idea of rational morality, that is, that

  one can determine the morality of one's and others' actions by reason and

  analysis. By starting from the relevant facts, one applies logic and critical

  thinking, possibly weighs the alternatives, and chooses the "moral" course of

  action. To be sure, this begs the question of which are the relevant facts and of

  how to weigh the alternatives. For instance, I asked a moral rationalist to explain

  the morality of abortion to me, and he answered that a fetus does not have a

  complete and functioning brain, that only beings with complete and functioning

  brains are persons, and therefore that it was morally acceptable to terminate a

  fetus. The problem with this manner of "reasoning" is that it stipulates the key

  terms of the debate (is a complete and functioning brain the definition of

  "personhood," and is lack of personhood a justification for killing?) and ignores

  issues of interest and of value conflicts. Even so, this approach is not inferior to,

  and is often superior to, religious brands of morality.

  Philosophers since Socrates have struggled with the problem of "the good."

  They have made little headway and will make no more so long as they insist on

  finding the good way to act or live, but the exercise shows that one can

  philosophize about ethics and morality without reference to religion. In fact, in

  his dialogue entitled Euthyphro, Plato stalled on whether an action is good

  because some god(s) ordain(s) it or whether the god(s) ordain(s) it because it is

  good. The dilemma is crucial because if an action is good with or without god(s),

  then we do not need god(s) to tell us what is good; we can philosophize it out for

  ourselves. And if an action is good only because some god(s) say(s) that it is,

  then the action is not good in itself; its goodness is purely arbitrary and

  contingent on the whim of the god(s).

  Since Plato's time, philosophers have offered a number of analyses of morality

  or ethics. One popular approach to morality is personal interest or egoism:

  people do, or should do, what is best for themselves; interestingly, early (and

  some modern) theorists of capitalism see informed egoism as the principle on

  which markets in particular and societies in general do and should operate.

  (Others regard egoism as the very antithesis of morality.) Utilitarianism argues

  that the best and most ethical course of action is the one that promises to produce

  the most pleasure and the least pain, presumably for the most people (or else it is

  just egoism again): humans thus become moral calculators, adding up pleasures,

  subtracting pains, and arriving at the most congenial sums. The fact that moral

  choices often cost pleasure and cause pain complicates this calculation, and of

  course how one compares relative pleasures and pains (say, mine against yours)

  is a problem.

  Immanuel Kant argued that morality flows from the perception of duty, that

  some actions are required of us simply because they are required of us. Moral

  actions are "imperatives," he said, and "categorical" imperatives at that. A

  hypothetical imperative is the sort of requirement that relates means to ends: if

  you want to drive a nail into a board, it is a hypothetical imperative to use a

  hammer. A categorical imperative is not a means to an end. In fact, Kant insists

  that we should not treat other people as means at all; rather, we should think

  about the maxim underlying our action-for example, the maxim underlying my

  aversion to stealing is "you should not steal"-as if it were a universal rule. The

  maxims of moral action are universal or universalizable rules.

  Aristotle, on the other hand, appraised behavior in terms of virtue, which is

  part of the character of persons. Living and acting virtuously was, as they say, its

  own reward-the cause and the effect of moral choices. A person who lived in the

  condition of eudaimonia (wellbeing, happiness, flourishing) behaved in ways to

  express and perpetuate this healthy state; of course, the person had to be

  educated and trained to be virtuous in the first place. Among the virtues were the

  eight "moral virtues" of prudence, justice, fortitude, courage, liberality,

  magnificence, magnanimity, and temperance. Further, a virtue was always the

  middle way between two vices (in the case of courage, the vices would be

  cowardice and foolhardiness).

  Other philosophical grounds for morality have been proposed, including

  justice and fairness and human rights. All of these really amount to little more

  than synonyms for morality and to formalizations of a particular form or view of

  morals or ethics. But Aristotle's observation about the training of virtue raises

  the point about the cultural basis of morality. Culture, of which religion is

  inevitably a part, is a source of behavioral expectations and behavioral appraisal

  far beyond the part contributed by religion. Any culture provides all kinds of

  norms for human comportment, from what clothes to wear to how to eat at the

  dinner table to how to treat other people. Some of these norms are influenced by

  or derived from a culture's religion, and some have no relation to the religion at

  all. Indeed, "moral" reactions often take the form more of cultural disdain than

  supernatural disapproval-it is more a matter of "what we do or don't do around

  here" than "what the supernatural beings want."

  MORALITY WITHOUT HUMANITY

  Humans-especially but not exclusively religious humans-have a tendency to

  imagine that morality is some unique human gift, sublime, ethereal, even

  "spiritual" or "supernatural." This is one reason why many (like C. S. Lewis)

  have been inclined to attribute "the moral sense," the very possibility of having

  morality or being a moral species along with the details of any specific moral

  system, to some source outside of humanity. Morality seems to them

  unprecedented in the natural world, transcendent and inexplicable.

  This attitude is a combination of hubris, ignorance of the world around us, and

  more than a small dose of Christian exclusivism-the suggestion that humans are

  unlike anything else in existence. But humans are not unlike anything else in

  existence; we are natural beings too, a species that developed historically and

  continuously from nonhuman precursors. And just as we can find traces (clear

  and strong traces) of our physical characteristics in other species, so we can find

  traces of our psychological and even moral characteristics in them as well.

  The question that is generally not asked in the discussion of morality, but that

  should be asked, is not "what is the basis of morality?" and certainly not "what is

  the true morality?" and not, as some well-intentioned thinkers have done, "why

  be moral?" Asking "why be moral?" is no more sensible than asking "why be

  linguistic?" or "why be bipedal?" Rather, the correct question is why are humans

  a moral speci
es? That is, what is it about us that makes us the kind of beings who

  are capable of "morality," who have "moral" interests and invent "moral"

  systems?

  A great deal of literature has accumulated over the last couple of decades to

  address this question, although Darwin predicted it more than 130 years ago. In

  his The Descent of Man, first published in 1871, he mused that morality was not

  really such a mystery at all but rather that "any animal whatever, endowed with

  well-marked social instincts, the parental and filial affections being here

  included, would inevitably acquire a moral sense or conscience."22 If this is so,

  then we should expect to find rudiments, evolutionary traces, or "building

  blocks" of "morality" in the nonhuman natural world. And of course we do.

  The details of the research into the evolution of morality are too vast and too

  varied to explore in depth here. All we need to establish is that some ancestral

  precursors to morality can be found in nonhuman species. Since Darwin, an

  accelerating line of investigation has developed, as early as Edward

  Westermarck's 1908 The Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas and

  reaching critical mass with E. O. Wilson's 1975 Sociobiology: The New

  Synthesis. Since then, the effort has yielded conceptual and empirical studies

  like Peter Singer's 1981 The Expanding Circle, Robert Wright's 1994 The Moral

  Animal: The New Science of Evolutionary Psychology, Marc Hawser's 2000

  Wild Minds: What Animals Really Think, and his 2006 Moral Minds: How

  Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong, Michael Shermer's

  aforementioned The Science of Good and Evil, Richard Joyce's 2006 The

  Evolution of Morality, and the many works of primatologist Frans de Waal,

  including Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved.

  The core of this research is that "morality" is not utterly unique to humans but

  has its historical/ evolutionary antecedents and its biological bases. "Morality"

  does not appear suddenly out of nowhere in humans but emerges gradually with

  the emergence of certain kinds of beings living certain kinds of lives. This is not

  to assert that animals have frill-blown "morality" any more than they have full-

  blown language. It is to assert that, just as some prehuman beings have

  "linguistic" capacities, some prehuman beings also have "moral" capacities.

  The key to the evolutionary theory of morality is that social beings tend

  reasonably to develop interests in the behavior of others and capacities to

  determine and to influence that behavior. This might start most obviously with

  offspring: parents of many species show concern for their offspring,

  disadvantage themselves for their offspring (for instance, by spending time

  feeding them), and put their own lives at risk for their offspring (the notorious

  problem of "altruism"). Some species exhibit these same behaviors toward adult

  members of the "family," or toward adult members of the larger social group, or

  ultimately, in humans, to all members of the species and perhaps to other species

  as well. In this regard, human "morality" is an extension of more "short-range"

  helping behaviors.

  With such costly but prosocial behaviors, we have taken a long step toward

  "morality." Or, as Shermer puts it, the capacity and tendency to have "moral

  sentiments" or moral concerns evolved out of the "premoral" feelings and

  tendencies of prehuman species. Frans de Waal and other animal watchers have

  accordingly gathered an enormous amount of data on prehuman "morality,"

  including sharing, indications of "fairness," gratitude, self-sacrifice, sympathy

  and comforting, and many more. O'Connell has been able to catalogue hundreds

  of reported cases of "empathy" and "moral" behavior in chimps,23 and it has

 

‹ Prev