Randal Marlin

Home > Other > Randal Marlin > Page 29
Randal Marlin Page 29

by Propaganda

existence of bindingness not related to consequential considerations.

  Kantian theory in particular is a form of deontology based on rationality. Kant

  thought that rightness or wrongness was determinable in the light of a certain test of

  rationality, presented in two forms. The first was the principle of universalizability: if

  you want to know whether an action is right or wrong, first ask what the underlying

  justificatory “maxim” behind the action is. For example, if you are tempted to steal,

  you might ask yourself what is implied by telling yourself that it is right to steal. One

  CHAPTER 4: ETHICS AnD PRoPAgAnDA 141

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 141

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  such answer is: “It is right to enrich myself, in whatever way I feel like, whenever I feel the urge to do so.” Now ask whether that “maxim” can be universalized. As a rational

  being, you must recognize that others are rational beings similar to yourself. If you

  reason that you have a right to enrich yourself in that way, so may they because, insofar

  as you are claiming rationality for your action, so may they. But can you accept that

  others have a right to steal from you? Clearly not. So the universalizability test reveals

  that the maxim does not survive rational scrutiny. It fails the test, and the action of

  stealing is deemed immoral. The second form of the test concerns whether our action

  shows respect for other people as ends in themselves rather than simply as a means

  to ends of our own. If we steal another’s goods, we are not valuing that person for his

  or her own sake but are treating them solely as a means to our gratification, ignoring

  their needs and wants. Judicial murder—the murder of an innocent person for expe-

  diency—treats the victim solely as a means to the ends of others and not as an end in

  himself. It is irrational to treat ourselves as worthy ends while denying such worthiness

  to others who possess the relevant attributes for worthiness. Kant thought the relevant

  attribute was rationality, but we may call the relevant fact that of being human.

  Ethical egoism is the theory that enlightened selfishness is the right basis for determining morality. A major advantage to arguing from this stance is that a frequent

  rejoinder to claims about ethical obligations—“Why should I be moral?”—is not

  difficult to answer. If you can show that something is to a person’s advantage, they

  have an attractive reason for doing that thing. Normally, we think of selfishness as the

  antithesis of morality. “You are being selfish!” is usually said reprovingly, not approv-

  ingly. Hence, the key word for defence of this is “enlightened.” The ethical egoist does

  not barge in ahead of others or grab the largest slice of cake, because that kind of

  selfishness brings the rebuke of others who are likely to exact some kind of sanction.

  Quite apart from that, it is possible to develop sensibilities that enable one to expe-

  rience pleasure in the happiness of others. It is not difficult to see that egoism, so

  interpreted, appears to be no great threat to morality, despite the negative associations

  with the word “selfish.” A problem with relying on this theory is that control ing our

  unenlightened impulses may be so difficult that the mere thought that we will benefit

  from doing so may be insufficient to bring about the desired effects on our behaviour.

  By contrast, visions of punishment and rewards in an afterlife may have an effective

  impact (though Bentham observed that the lack of propinquity diminishes the force

  of these appeals). The egoist may also be restrained by such visions, but the message

  from the Christian account of the afterlife has not favoured the egoistically motivated

  person. Nietzsche was scornful about the hypocrisy involved in adopting superficially

  a humble, self-sacrificing stance merely as a means to achieving superiority in an after-

  life, and on this point he may well have reflected Jesus’ primary message, which had to

  do with love rather than rewards and punishments (though he includes reference to

  these as well). Acting from motives of fear or gain seems less honourable than acting

  out of a genuine desire to help others, a desire based on a cultivated sense of empathy.

  142 PROPAGANDA AND THE ETHICS OF PERSUASION

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 142

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  If we take this last turn, we seem to land in the paradox that enlightened egoism leads to the requirement that we think non-egoistically. For if we don’t, we are liable, such is

  our nature, to engage in unenlightened selfish behaviour since we would lack sufficient

  counterweight to our impulses.

  Utilitarianism is a very popular theory, especially in relation to public planning

  policy. The idea of this theory is, first, that the morality of actions is determinable in

  the light of the amount of happiness and unhappiness that they create, taking into

  account all the people affected and counting them all equally. If one contemplates a

  range of possible actions at any given time, the right one is that which will maximize

  overall happiness (one word for this is “optimific,” but it has an awkward sound). There

  are many questions about utilitarianism. Is pleasure to be identified with happiness, as

  Bentham thought? If so, should we alter our understanding of pleasure, or of happiness,

  or both, and in what way? What happens to individual human rights if our sole guide

  is the overall net benefit? Consider such cases as that of Robin Hood, who stole from

  the rich to benefit the poor; it seems the net benefit to the poor is greater than the lack

  of benefit to the rich, but is that a sufficient reason for giving Robin Hood the morally

  approved go-ahead? The matter is complicated by many considerations. The act of rob-

  bery causes great consternation in the victims and a very unpleasant sense of insecurity

  that persists long after the event. The rich may fight back in ways that make the poor

  worse off. One lawless act provokes others. The utilitarian does not have to bow to the

  simplistically formulated case, producing an over-simplified ethical conclusion.

  Ostensibly opposed to the utilitarian is the rights upholder, who maintains that

  for the sake of stability and order, rights such as property rights need to be entrenched

  to a point where they are not subject to undermining by some pleasure-pain calcu-

  lus favouring forced, illegal redistribution. But the utilitarian can incorporate that

  argument into the theory by noting that stability has its own quantum of utilitar-

  ian weight, which needs to be added in. So the seeming opposition between rights

  upholder and utilitarian may not survive more extensive analysis.

  Another, more macabre case posits three children who will die if they don’t get a

  new lung, kidney, and heart respectively and soon. There is a seriously ill person with

  brain damage but healthy organs otherwise. Should that person be killed to save the

  lives of the others? The utilitarian is asked whether an affirmative answer is acceptable

  to the theory. If it is, the theory seems subversive of law and order. Of course, the utili-

  tarian could respond by saying, “Law and order are very important for the common

  good, and a utilitarian cannot countenance acts that would undermine the system

  and produce chaos.” Whatever the problems of detail, u
tilitarianism has a very strong

  attractive force overall, and in a secular or multicultural society its principles form a

  large part of the reasoning for policy decisions. The question is whether utilitarian-

  ism nevertheless leaves out an important part of the moral story. If it does, then in

  regularly appealing to the principle of utilitarianism, the policy-maker risks blindness

  as to its deficiencies.

  CHAPTER 4: ETHICS AnD PRoPAgAnDA 143

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 143

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  Over two millennia ago Plato supplied us with a model for reasoning about ethics. In his Republic, the question “What is justice?” was discussed, and one of the

  answers supplied was that justice is repaying one’s debts. However, Socrates asked

  whether one should give back a deadly weapon borrowed from a friend when the

  friend came for it drunk, intending to kill someone. The answer, in the negative,

  showed that the principle of justice has at least one exception and, therefore, cannot

  be relied on always to give the correct answer. The col ision between intuitions about

  a particular case and principles that seem otherwise sound is a common experience in

  moral thinking. We have to find a way to balance those intuitions against principles,

  which will need some kind of reformulation. The goal is to bring the two into what

  the contemporary philosopher John Rawls called “reflective equilibrium.”2

  Ethics is also concerned with character and virtue. If we suppose that utilitarian-

  ism is correct, we may find that the best course of action, so determined, could involve

  a politician having to break a promise. Assurances given at election time may later

  appear to him or her to be contrary to the public interest. We may find ourselves judg-

  ing the actions of the politician favourably but still dislike the character of a person

  who is readily able to abandon personal commitments.

  THE MoRALITy oF LyIng

  In the history of morality, lying has generally been viewed with disfavour. St.

  Augustine, St. Thomas Aquinas, and Kant all argued that lying is immoral, with no

  exceptions, although with varying degrees of turpitude depending on the lie. Yet, there

  are many other philosophers who argue that lying may be the right and even the mor-

  ally obligatory course of action to take under exceptional circumstances. Some believe

  that lies are wrong only to those to whom truth is “owed,” and they maintain that not

  everybody is entitled to the truth from another person. More recently, David Nyberg

  argued that lying is part of everyday experience and that it is frequently, and not just

  exceptionally, the right thing to do. Nyberg concentrates on how to separate harmful

  and immoral lies from those that are harmless and beneficial. By talking about lying

  in general, he thinks, we lose the right perspective on those lies that are especially

  harmful. He prefers a “bottom-up” approach to the question of lying, that is to say,

  an approach that is generated by consideration of real-life experiences and seeks to

  formulate rules out of those experiences.3 This is different from a “top-down” model,

  which seeks to find general principles first and then apply them to individual cases.

  Sisella Bok is among those philosophers who allow for the moral justification of lies

  but only in very exceptional circumstances. Her book, Lying: Moral Choice in Public

  and Private Life,4 serves as a foil for Nyberg, since it continues the practice of earlier moralists of arguing from general principle down to individual cases.

  144 PROPAGANDA AND THE ETHICS OF PERSUASION

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 144

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  Even if we disagree with the earlier moralists, it is valuable to start with their insights. It is sometimes more instructive to take a theory that is rejected and show

  why it was rejected than to ignore it altogether.

  St. Augustine

  St. Augustine (354–430) might be taken as the originator, in the Western world, of a

  certain tradition which, despite recognizing that in special circumstances there can be

  very strong moral reasons in favour of lying, and despite sympathy for the plight of

  people caught in such special circumstances, stil refuses to accept and teach categori-

  cally that it is ever morally right to do so. He approves of some actions that might be

  thought by others to be lies but does so only if, in his view, some essential feature of a

  lie is lacking. Truth to him is so vital that he is unwilling to have truck with even well-

  motivated lies, but he does not roundly condemn them either. Augustine is quite at ease

  with the idea that human beings might have to sin in a small way from time to time.

  Augustine inclines toward a narrow definition of the lie. It is not enough for a

  person to say something false, knowing it to be false; the person must do so with the

  intention to deceive, or there is no lie. An obvious case of not lying is the ironic rejoin-

  der to an improbable statement, such as “Yes, and pigs fly.” More problematic is the

  case in which a politician says, “I will not seek the nomination,” knowing that people

  will judge by the very fact of the pronouncement that he will seek it. This would seem

  not to be a lie, on Augustine’s account, because what the candidate says engenders true

  belief, and the candidate (we will suppose) knows this.5 For a similar reason, stories

  made up for jocular purposes are not lies, nor are fictional writings: “No one has been

  so illiterate as to think that similar fables of Aesop, related for the same purpose, ought

  to be called lies.”6 Although narrow in one sense, Augustine’s view of what constitutes

  a lie is broader in another, for he also holds that a person can lie not only by words but

  by any outward manifestation contrary to what he or she believes.

  Augustine presents us with a nice puzzle about lies and truth-telling. Suppose

  you know that down one fork in the road there are bandits, while there are no bandits

  along the other fork. You tell someone who never believes what you say that bandits

  lie in wait down the fork where you know there are none. You do this so that the

  person, disbelieving you, will take the safe road and not come to harm. Do you lie?

  Do you do something wrong? You surely do not do any wrong; indeed, if you told the

  truth the person would end up in great harm. Do you lie? Not if lying includes the

  intention to deceive. Now consider the case where, out of malice, you tell the person

  that there are no bandits down the road where there are no bandits, knowing that the

  person will take the dangerous road and come to grief and wanting this to happen.

  Should this be considered a lie? Do you do something wrong? Clearly, Augustine

  says, you do something wrong. However, if we strictly hold to the definition of a lie as

  the saying of what one knows to be false in order to deceive, then there is no lie here

  CHAPTER 4: ETHICS AnD PRoPAgAnDA 145

  BV-Propaganda-Interior-04.indd 145

  9/5/13 4:52 PM

  either, because you are not saying what you know to be false, even though you speak the truth only to deceive.7

  We will certainly avoid lies, Augustine writes, if we say what is true and deserving

  of belief, if there is a need to express the truth, and if we want to convince people of

  what we say. Th
e inclusion of the idea of a “need to express the truth” is an impor-

  tant moral consideration, and, interestingly, it is reflected in the Anglo-American law

  of libel, which allows the existence of “qualified privilege” for people to say publicly

  things that are in the public interest to know. Certain defences against a libel suit are

  open to those with qualified privilege but are denied to those who defame merely out

  of a desire to gossip or increase circulation of a scandal sheet.

  There is still no lie, in Augustine’s view, either if we merely say something false

  believing it to be true, or if we hold something to be true that we don’t know to be true

  but don’t know to be false either, or if we believe what is not worthy of belief, or if we

  express an opinion without a need to do so. In other words, there are factors that can

  seriously taint what we say with immorality but that do not amount to lying. One of

  the great scholarly sins is to present as true something for which there is no evidence.

  At least with a lie, there will be some means of showing the statement false. When a

  totally unsupported claim is made in an area where no evidence exists for or against

  the claim, it is annoyingly unrefutable in the straightforward way of demonstrating

  its falseness. By detaching in this way the question of ignorant and deceptive com-

  munications from that of ful -blown lies, Augustine has done a useful service. It helps

  to show that, to be morally wrong, deceptive communication does not have to involve

  what are, strictly speaking, lies. The immorality can be linked to negligence regarding

  ascertaining of truth in circumstances where the truth matters (as distinct from harm-

  less jokes, for example). The concepts of negligence and recklessness are useful for sort-

  ing out the ethics of what Harry Frankfurt cal ed “bul shitting,” meaning presenting

  things as true without having serious concern for whether they are in fact true,8 and

  what political satirist Stephen Colbert referred to as “truthiness,” meaning the quality

  that “facts,” ideas, or doctrines have of seeming or feeling true at a gut level whether

  or not there is any objective evidence to support them.9 Negligence or recklessness

  regarding the truth of what we believe can have seriously harmful consequences, so

 

‹ Prev