Anger and Forgiveness

Home > Other > Anger and Forgiveness > Page 5
Anger and Forgiveness Page 5

by Martha C. Nussbaum


  gists such as Lazarus and James Averill should agree on this. They have

  thought long and hard about the concept, and it would be surprising if

  they had made an obvious error. Still, let us think again. Anger is not the

  only emotion that contains a double movement. Many emotions contain

  a backward- looking appraisal while also having associated action ten-

  dencies oriented toward a future goal.

  Compassion, for example, looks at the bad fate that has befallen some-

  one else; but it also has an associated future- directed action tendency.

  When I feel compassion for a person who is suffering, I often imagine

  helping that person, and in many cases I do it. Daniel Batson’s research

  shows that this tendency toward helping behavior is quite powerful, if

  the helpful action is ready at hand and not very costly. But the connec-

  tion between compassion and helping is typically understood as con-

  tingent and causal, rather than conceptual. Philosophical definitions of

  compassion (from Aristotle and the Stoics through Smith and Rousseau

  to Schopenhauer) do not suggest that the helping tendency is part and

  parcel of the emotion, something without which one could not be said to

  experience compassion.34 I think this is probably correct: the connection

  is indeed causal and external rather than conceptual and internal. We

  can feel compassion for people even when there is nothing to be done

  for them: people who have been drowned in a flood, to take just one

  example, or distant people whom we can imagine no way of helping.

  With anger, however, the future- oriented aim is standardly thought

  to be part of the emotion, something without which there is pain of some

  sort, but not anger. (Butler, we recall, holds that anger’s internal goal is

  the misery of our fellow humans.) We must figure out, first, whether this

  is correct— whether there really is a conceptual connection in this case,

  and not simply a causal connection as in others. Second, we must figure

  out how, more precisely, the pain is connected to the strike- back response.

  Let’s be clear, first, about what the claim is. The claim is not that

  anger conceptually involves a wish for violent revenge; nor is it that

  anger involves the wish to inflict suffering oneself upon the offender. For

  I may not want to get involved in revenge myself: I may want someone

  else, or the law, or life itself, to do it for me. I just want the doer to suffer. And the suffering can be quite subtle. One might wish for a physical

  injury; one might wish for psychological unhappiness; one might wish for

  Anger

  23

  unpopularity. One might simply wish for the perpetrator’s future (your

  unfaithful ex’s new marriage, for example) to turn out really badly. And

  one can even imagine as a type of punishment the sheer continued exis-

  tence of the person as the bad and benighted person he or she is: that is

  how Dante imagines hell. All that I am investigating here (and ultimately

  accepting, with one significant qualification) is that anger involves, con-

  ceptually, a wish for things to go badly, somehow, for the offender, in a

  way that is envisaged, somehow, however vaguely, as a payback for the

  offense. They get what they deserve.

  So let’s investigate this, considering a range of different cases. And

  let us start from a basic scenario: Offender O has raped Angela’s close

  friend Rebecca on the campus where both Angela and Rebecca are stu-

  dents. Angela has true beliefs about what has occurred, about how seri-

  ously damaging it is, and about the wrongful intentions involved: O,

  she knows, is mentally competent, understood the wrongfulness of

  his act, etc. (I choose rape rather than murder, in order to leave Angela

  with a wider range of possible actions and wishes than would typically

  be the case with murder. And I choose a friend in order to give Angela

  more latitude about how to position herself toward the offense and the

  offender.) Most rapes take place in the context of intimate relationships.

  But because for me this domain has special complexity, involving issues

  of trust and grief that relations with strangers do not, let me imagine the

  case as a (conceptually simpler) stranger- rape, or at any rate not rape in

  the context of an ongoing intimate relationship involving trust and deep

  emotion.

  Case 1. Angela feels pain at Rebecca’s rape. She feels that her circle of concern, what she deeply cares about, has been severely damaged, and

  she believes, correctly, that the damage was wrongful. She now take steps

  to mitigate the damage: she spends time with Rebecca, she makes efforts

  to support her in therapy, in general she devotes a great deal of energy to

  mending Rebecca’s life— and thus to mending the breach in her own cir-

  cle of concern. So far, Angela’s emotion appears to be grief/ compassion,

  and I think the standard definitions are correct when they suggest that it

  is not anger, even though the occasion for the grief is a wrongful act. We

  should notice that in this case the primary focus of Angela’s emotion is

  the loss and pain caused to Rebecca, rather than the criminal act itself,

  and to that extent her emotion seems to have Rebecca, not the rapist, as

  its target.

  Case 2. Angela feels pain at Rebecca’s rape, etc. She does all the things that she did in Case 1, thus expressing her compassion. But she also focuses

  on the wrongfulness of the act, and her pain includes a special pain directed at the wrongful act— to some extent distinct from her pain at Rebecca’s suffering. This additional pain leads her to want to do something about that

  24

  Anger and Forgiveness

  wrongfulness. So Angela forms a group to support rape victims, and she

  gives money to such groups. She also campaigns for better public safety

  measures to prevent rape and for better treatment of the problem of sexual

  violence on her campus. (Again, I abstract from the special complexities

  of rape in the context of intimate relationships involving trust and love.)

  Should we call Angela’s emotion anger because it focuses not only on

  Rebecca’s pain but also on the wrongfulness of the act, and has an outward

  movement aimed at something like a righting of the wrong? It is an inter-

  esting case, but I think that we typically would not call Angela’s emotion

  anger. I am inclined to see it as a type of morally inflected compassion—

  not very different, really, from a compassion for one hungry acquaintance

  that leads me to campaign for better welfare support for all. As in Case 1,

  the emotion does not have the offender as its target; its target is Rebecca,

  and other women in Rebecca’s position. The offender comes into it only

  because stopping similar harms is Angela’s goal for the future. Angela is

  thus thinking of general utility (and in Case 2 the Utilitarian idea of anger’s limits appears for the first time).

  Case 3. Angela feels pain, etc., as in Cases 1 and 2. As in Case 2, she focuses on the wrongfulness of O’s act, and she may campaign for general

  measures to prevent that sort of damage in future. But she also focuses,

  this time, on O. She seeks to mend the damage by making the offender suffer.

  Because h
er circle of concern is damaged, she wants something to happen to O (whether through legal or extralegal means). Here we finally seem to

  have arrived at anger, as the philosophical tradition understands it: a retaliatory and hopeful outward movement that seeks the pain of the offender

  because of and as a way of assuaging or compensating for one’s own pain.

  The question now is, Why? Why would an intelligent person think

  that inflicting pain on the offender assuages or cancels her own pain?

  There seems to be some type of magical thinking going on. In reality,

  harsh punishment of the offender rarely repairs a damage. Adding O’s

  pain to Rebecca’s does not do anything to ameliorate Rebecca’s situation,

  so far as one can see. In a TV interview after his father’s murder, Michael

  Jordan was asked whether, if they ever caught the murderer, Jordan

  would want him executed. Jordan sadly replied, “Why? That wouldn’t

  bring him back.”35 This eminently sensible reply is rare, however, and

  perhaps only someone whose credentials in the area of masculinity are as

  impeccable as Jordan’s would dare to think and say it.36

  Ideas of payback have deep roots in the imaginations of most of us.

  Ultimately they probably derive from metaphysical ideas of cosmic bal-

  ance that are hard to shake off, and that may be part of our evolutionary

  endowment.37 Indeed the first preserved fragment of Western philoso-

  phy, the famous words of the Greek thinker Anaximander, dating from

  the sixth century BCE, is based on just such a powerful analogy between

  Anger

  25

  the institution of punishment and the alternations of the seasons: they are

  said to “pay penalty and reparation” to one another for their sequential

  encroachments, as the hot and dry drive out the cold and wet (not so suc-

  cessfully, however, in Chicago). We think this way naturally, for whatever

  reason. Many cherished literary works contain such ideas of “comeup-

  pance,” which give us intense aesthetic pleasure.38 Whether the pleasure

  we take in such narratives derives from antecedent cosmic- balance think-

  ing or whether narratives of this sort (the entirety of the detective- story

  genre, for example) nourish and augment our tendency to think in such

  ways, we cannot say. Probably both. But we do think in such ways, and

  we do take pleasure in narratives in which the doer suffers, purport-

  edly balancing the horrible act that occurred. Aesthetics, however, like

  our evolutionary prehistory, can be misleading. Our satisfaction does not

  mean that such ways of thinking make sense. They really do not. Raping

  O does not undo the rape of Jennifer. Killing a killer does not bring the

  dead to life.39

  This brings us to an alternative to this type of magical thinking

  which at first seems rational: a focus on the idea of personal slighting or

  diminution.

  Case 4. Angela is pained, etc. She believes that O’s bad act is not only a wrongful act that seriously damaged someone dear to her, but also an

  insult or denigration of her. She thinks something like, “This guy thinks

  that he can insult my friend’s dignity with impunity, and, insofar as he

  thinks this, he thinks that he can push me around— that I’ll just sit by while my friend is insulted. So he diminishes me and insults my self- respect.”

  Here the connection between pain and retaliation is made through the

  Aristotelian idea that the eudaimonistic ego- damage O has inflicted is

  a kind of humiliation or down- ranking. No matter how implausible it is

  to read O’s act as a down- ranking of Angela (given that O doesn’t know

  Angela, or even Rebecca), Angela sees O’s harm to her friend as an ego-

  wound that lessens Angela’s status. She therefore thinks that lowering O

  through pain and even humiliation will right the balance.40

  Many cultures, past and present, think this way all the time. In most

  major sports we find an emphasis on retaliation for injury, and players

  are thought wimpy and unmanly to the extent that they do not strike

  back so far as the rules permit (and a little beyond that). Even though

  it is obvious that injuring one player does not take away the injury to

  another, it is a different story if one focuses not on injury but on ranking

  and humiliation: the retaliatory hit is plausibly seen as taking away the

  humiliation of the first hit. Slighting in the sense of diminution reaches

  a broad class of cases, even if not all cases where anger is involved. It

  is very easy for people to shift mentally from a eudaimonistic concern

  (this is part of my circle of concern, what I care about) to a narcissistic

  26

  Anger and Forgiveness

  status- focused concern (this is all about me and my pride or rank). In

  such cases, a retaliatory strike- back is thought symbolically to restore the balance of status, manliness, or whatever.

  Jean Hampton, whose analysis is very close to mine, puts it this

  way: if people are secure, they won’t see an injury as a diminishment;

  but people are rarely this secure. They secretly fear that the offense has

  revealed a real lowness or lack of value in themselves, and that putting

  the offender down will prove that the offender has made a mistake.41

  I feel her account does not cover all the cases: more straightforwardly,

  people may simply care a great deal about public standing, and they can

  see quite clearly that to be pushed around has indeed diminished that.

  Even in her subset of the cases, the fear she describes is much more plau-

  sible if the value people care about is relative status, which is easily dam-

  aged, than if it is some inner worth or value, which is not.

  All of a sudden, the retaliatory tendency makes sense and is no longer

  merely magical. To someone who thinks this way, in terms of diminution

  and status- ranking, it is not only plausible to think that retaliation atones for or annuls the damage, it is actually true. If Angela retaliates successfully (whether through law or in some other way, but always focusing on

  status- injury), the retaliation really does effect a reversal that annuls the injury, seen as an injury of down- ranking. Angela is victorious, and the

  previously powerful offender is suffering in prison. Insofar as the salient

  feature of O’s act is its low ranking of Angela, the turnabout effected by

  the retaliation really does put him down and her (relatively) up.

  Notice that things make sense only if the focus is purely on relative status, rather than on some intrinsic attribute (health, safety, bodily integrity, friendship, love, wealth, good academic work, some other achievement)

  that has been jeopardized by the wrongful act, and that might incidentally

  confer status. Retaliation does not confer, or restore, those things. It’s only if she thinks purely in terms of relative status that she can plausibly hope

  to effect a reversal through a strike- back that inflicts pain of some type on the offender. (Thus people in academic life who love to diss scholars who

  have criticized them, and who believe that this does them some good, have

  to be focusing only on reputation and status, since it’s obvious that injuring someone else’s reputation does not make your own work better than it was

  before, or correct whatever flaws the other person has found in it.)

  It’s
clear that Angela need not think that the injury she has suffered is

  a down- ranking. That is why Aristotle’s definition is too narrow. Indeed,

  in this case it seems odd for her to do so, given that O is a stranger who

  does not know her connection with Rebecca. But this way of seeing injury

  is very common, and very common even in cases where people are eager

  to deny that this is really what is going on.42 That is why Aristotle’s defi-

  nition is helpful.

  Anger

  27

  At this point I must introduce a distinction that will be important

  in later chapters. There is a special status that good political institutions rightly care about: equal human dignity. Rape can be seen, plausibly, as a

  dignitary injury, not just an injury to bodily integrity. It is right for legal institutions to take this into account in dealing with rapists and rape victims. However, notice that equal dignity belongs to all, inherently and

  inalienably, and is not a relative or competitive matter. Whatever hap-

  pens to the rapist, we should not wish his equal human dignity to be vio-

  lated any more than we approve his violation of the victim’s dignity. And

  it is most important to see that pushing his dignity down does not push

  the victim’s up. Dignity is not a zero- sum game; in that way it is utterly

  different from relative status.43

  Suppose Angela does not think this way, but stops at Case 3. Then,

  insofar as her emotion is anger and not simply some combination of grief

  and compassion, she does initially wish some sort of bad result for the

  offender, and she does initially think (magically) that this will set things

  right, somehow counterbalancing or even annulling the offense. It is

  human to think this way. However, if she is really focusing on Rebecca

  and not on her own status- injury, she is likely to think this way only

  briefly. Magical fantasies of replacement can be very powerful, but in

  most sane people they prove short- lived. Instead, she is likely to take a

  mental turn toward a different set of future- directed attitudes. Insofar

  as she really wants to help Rebecca and women in Rebecca’s position,

  she will focus on the responses characteristic of Cases 1 and 2: helping

  Rebecca get on with her life, but also setting up help groups, trying to

  publicize the problem of campus rape, and urging the authorities to deal

 

‹ Prev