Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 18
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 18

by Bart Schultz

plaint was not that historical criticism was valueless (though he sometimes

  made it sound that way), but that it was insufficient by itself to solve the

  “deepest problems of human life.” The exasperation that he vented over

  his inconclusive results scarcely conveyed just how indebted he was and

  would remain to Strauss and Renan. After all, Seeley’s shortcomings were

  shared by many more orthodox figures, such as Bishop Mansel, another

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  object of Sidgwick’s critical talents. Of Mansel’s Bampton Lectures, he

  wrote: “He really is a well-meaning man, and il a raison for the most

  part against Metaphysicians. But he talks of Revelation as if the Bible

  had dropped from the skies ready translated into English; he ignores all

  historical criticism utterly.” (M ) And in a review of , in which he

  anticipates a number of arguments he would later marshall against the ide-

  alists, he challenges Mansel’s apparent claim that, theological beliefs being

  designed to guide practice rather than to satisfy reason, the contradiction

  between two such beliefs is no argument against them:

  It is no use to say that it is restricted to the interpretation of Revelation: for the deduction of dogma from Scripture is a process of reasoning, which has always

  been guided by the maxim that different texts of Scripture must be made mutually

  consistent. Now either this maxim is invalid, in which case the creeds must crumble

  again into a chaos of texts: or if it is valid, we require some criterion to distinguish the contradictions that we ought to embrace. Such a criterion Mansel never offers:

  and he seems to deal in a perfectly arbitrary manner with the antinomies which

  beset the exercise of our reason when it strives to attain the absolute.

  This hardly seems like a profession of the uselessness of historical crit-

  icism, and it is in fact more in keeping with Sidgwick’s general attitude,

  evident in many other works, than the impatience expressed in some of his

  letters. Before embarking on his biblical criticism, he could complacently

  say that a man “impressed with the Divine Government and the Divine

  sympathy” by “reading simply and candidly the New Testament, will end

  by being more orthodox than at first one thinks possible when one feels

  one’s indignation kindled against Persecuting Bishops” (M ). No such

  claim could have passed his pen after his exposure to Renan and Strauss.

  Although Sidgwick did at one time or another toy with going whole-

  heartedly with “Maurice and Broad Church,” his fundamental objections

  to that position formed a more conspicuous feature of his theological twists

  and turns. They were given cogent expression in an  review of a book

  by one of Maurice’s disciples:

  [T]he key to Mr. Hutton’s theology, as it is to that of his master, Mr. Maurice . . .

  may be expressed thus: ‘God is immediately or intuitively, but not adequately,

  made known to us: and what is made known of Him is more than can be expressed

  in propositions, or communicated from one man to another.’ This seems to me

  an appropriate account of our apprehension of Divine, as of much other, fact:

  but I am unable to see how it furnishes the barrier against scepticism which

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  Mr. Maurice and Mr. Hutton seem to find in it. The ‘sources of our faith’ may be

  indefinitely wider than that ‘evidences of our convictions’: but when the diversities of faith cause any one to enquire into the truth or falsehood of his own, a rational

  answer must indicate ‘evidences’ and not ‘sources.’ Mr. Hutton sees this, and

  offers ‘really universal reasons’ for believing the Incarnation. These are the old

  combination of psychological and historical premisses: only miracles are omitted

  from the latter. ‘We have need of believing in a Filial God: and Jesus claimed to be

  and was recognised as such.’ In explaining the former premiss Mr. Hutton rather

  confounds emotional want with intellectual anticipation: even if it be true that our

  spiritual yearnings cannot be satisfied without this belief, the presumption thus

  obtained cannot be compared with the presumption that a friend or a chemical

  substance will act in a given way. The exposition of these spiritual needs, as

  Mr. Hutton apprehends them, is highly interesting: but they seem to me too

  idiosyncratic to constitute ‘really universal reasons.’ Who, except him, ‘knows’

  that the ‘free will of all men (except Jesus) is intrinsically indifferent,’ and that ‘self-sacrifice is not indigenous in man’? If we long to institute a complete comparison

  of the spiritual effects of pure theism and Christianity, we find the materials too

  scanty: so that Mr. Hutton’s method of psychological proof, even if cogent, is as

  yet inapplicable.

  Much as Sidgwick admired the Mauricean passion for unity, he was

  too sharply aware of conflict and difference to go along with that version

  of Platonized Christianity. For what if what is being apprehended is only

  the God of theism, rather than that of Christianity in its more proper

  forms? Perhaps the unifying intuition was more Platonic than Christian.

  Or perhaps it was more Socratic than Platonic, something simpler and even

  less amenable to articulation than Plato’s eternal forms. Maurice’s appeal

  to conscience was a wonderfully sophisticated and liberal-minded one, but

  for all that, it was still an appeal to conscience, and for practical purposes

  useless. Sidgwick, who found that his conscience “was more utilitarian

  than most,” sought a way of actually reconciling conflicting “evidences”

  (M ). Sympathetic, conversational soul searching required more tools

  with which to work. Jesus was no more above criticism than Socrates, and

  the criticism often ran on parallel tracks.

  He even sticks up for Goethe, against Hutton’s account. In a most

  revealing passage, he urges that Hutton is

  even betrayed here and there into phrases which have a touch of impatient

  Philistinism. To talk of Goethe’s “sickly pottering” about the “pyramid of his ex-

  istence” is surely an inadequate manner of speaking of the apostle of self-culture.

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  And on the whole the critic seems to lean too much to the common error, which

  in one passage he resists, of taking the Goethe of the autobiography for the real

  Goethe. No one was ever fascinated by the hero of W
ahrheit und Dichtung. The

  charm of Goethe depends on the rare harmony of strikingly contrasted qualities,

  the poise and balance of strongly conflicting impulses: the intellect of driest light, yet with perpetual vision of a radiantly coloured world: the nature responsive to

  all gales of emotion and breezes of sentiment, yet using all as forces to carry it in its “unhasting unresting” course – which we only see by comprehensive comparison of his studied and unstudied utterances, and his life as seen and felt by his

  contemporaries.

  Of this essay, Noel wrote to Sidgwick, “It is wonderfully terse, pregnant,

  to the point. I suppose nothing has ever been said about Goethe more to

  the point than the last sentences.”

  The criticisms of the Mauricean vision were telling, and profoundly

  suggestive of the course of Sidgwick’s theological probing. Even in ,

  impatient with his historical work, he had urged that what is “required

  is psychological experiments in ethics and intuitive Theism: that is what

  on the whole the human race has got to do for some years” (M ).

  The call for such experiments was serious: he had long held that more

  work needed to be done on the psychology of religious belief – indeed,

  on psychology generally – if one were to argue with any plausibility

  as to just what kind of religious belief humanity might require. After all,

  there “is no proof against there being a Mind & Heart behind phenomena,”

  and, Sidgwick confessed, “the contemplation of this hypothesis answers

  to a need now existing in my nature, and the experience of thousands tes-

  tifies that such contemplation generates an abiding , with

  all its attendant noblenesses and raptures.” But what was the mean-

  ing of this need and this effect? Was the human condition one of abject

  superstition, demanding totem and taboo? Was it less superstitious but

  nonetheless inherently prone to some minimal faith in a just universe,

  such that the suffering of innocents was only apparent and righteous-

  ness would in the long run receive its reward? Was some sort of faith,

  even if incapable of rational demonstration, essential to human flourish-

  ing or functioning? How far away from earlier religions might civiliza-

  tion progress? What if Socrates, for example, turned out to be simply

  a schizoid combination of critical acumen and primitive idolatry? One

  could not make either Mauricean or Comtean claims until such issues were

  sorted out.

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  In his early Apostolic days, Sidgwick had read a paper entitled “Is Prayer

  a Permanent Function of Humanity?” – it was a question that epitomized

  much of his thinking, during the sixties and beyond, and one to which he

  would return at the very end of his life. He wondered whether there were

  not some psychological natures so “healthy, finely moulded, well nerved,

  symmetrical” that they could do without the practice of supplication and

  all that went with it. Moreover, he suspected that such natures “might

  feel in reading history as if mankind had gone to sleep after the bright

  sunny days of Athenian life and were just waking up again after the long

  nightmare of mediaeval superstition.” Sidgwick predictably goes on to

  confess that he feels the opposing case “with much more force,” since one

  could argue from “the virtue and happiness that religion has produced in

  the unsymmetrical and weak to the still greater effects of the same kind, it

  might produce in the symmetrical and strong.” (CWC) And the religious

  have an edge over the symmetrical people in facing the trials of old age

  and death. Yet even so, the doubts were there, and had been watered by

  the example of the ancient Athenians. And by that of Goethe and those

  of Sidgwick’s friends who followed him.

  These issues, with their psychological, sociological, and anthropological

  orientations, were coming at Sidgwick from all sides – from Darwin,

  Maurice, Mill, Renan, Comte, and others – and they would continue to

  haunt him for the rest of his life. But he gave them a novel twist, carrying

  them in directions never quite anticipated by his predecessors.

  For Sidgwick, psychology meant, in large part, parapsychology. The

  crucial questions could not be fully addressed without consideration of a

  much wider range of evidence than had previously been treated of. Perhaps

  personal survival of death was one of the elements of truth in Christianity,

  to be separated from the husk of legend. Perhaps Maurice was at least

  right in thinking that one must address sympathetically the evidences of all

  the world religions, including, of course, the Socratic. Maurice, however,

  thought that “disembodied spirits” belonged “to the realm of fancy and

  not of fact. Our Lord took all pains while He was on earth to show how

  much He cared for bodies.” Here he was in an odd accord with Renan, who

  also had no time for ghosts. But for Sidgwick, the natural reply was that

  it was just as dogmatic to go along uncritically with materialistic science

  as it was to go along with orthodox religion. What evidence was there for

  ghosts? For the miraculous as a permanent function of the universe? Just

  possibly, Maurice did not take the Socratic Daimon seriously enough.

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  In , in a singularly illuminating letter to his friend Roden Noel,

  Sidgwick explained:

  Only I happened to read Lecky in the Long. You know the book – History of

  Rationalism. With the perverseness that sometimes characterises me I took up

  the subject from entirely the opposite point of view to Lecky, and determined to

  investigate the evidence for medieval miracles, as he insists it is not an investigation of this evidence, but merely the progress of events, march of mind, etc. which

  has brought about our present disbelief in them. The results have, I confess,

  astonished myself. I keep silence at present even from good words, but I dimly

  foresee that I shall have to entirely alter my whole view of the universe and

  admit the “miraculous,” as we call it, as a permanent element in human history and experience. You know my “Spiritualistic” ghost-seeing tendencies. These all

  link on, and the Origins of all religions find themselves explained. However, as I

  say, I keep silence at present; I am only in the middle of my inquiries. (M )

  Curiously enough, this venture was in part an inheritance from Benson.

  Among the discussion societies that Sidgwick had joined as an undergrad-

  uate, there was also the Ghost Society, devoted to the collection and critical

  examination of ghost stories. It had been founded by Benso
n and some

  friends during his undergraduate tenure, and thus Sidgwick had been

  steadily accumulating the results of collective research on the subject for

  a decade prior to the  letter. A letter to his sister in  explains that

  “my ghostological investigations are flourishing; I have taken unto myself

  associates here, and am prosecuting my researches with vigour; meeting

  with failures and vexatious exaggerations but still getting a good deal of

  real matter.”

  As his diary reveals, the theological relevance of this subject – something

  Benson ultimately rejected – had come home to him early on: “Why should

  not God be willing to give us a few glimpses of the unseen worlds which

  we all believe exist.” This was an interest that apparently endured intact

  through all his theological wanderings. In , he wrote to Dakyns: “In

  Theology I am much as ever: I have not yet investigated Spiritualism,

  but I am still bent upon doing so as soon as I have the opportunity”

  (M ). And again, in , “As to Spiritualism, do not speak of it: I

  have not progressed, but am in painful doubt; still, I have some personal

  experiences and much testimony, and I find it hard to believe that I shall

  not discover some unknown laws, psychological or other” (M ). T. H.

  Green may have “sniffed” at the project, but Sidgwick was unmoved.

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  Interestingly, though not surprisingly, Sidgwick’s ghostological inves-

  tigations tended to mirror the Apostolic mode of inquiry. This is not

  merely because a number of the associates he had taken on were in fact

  also Apostles – for instance, Oscar Browning and J. J. Cowell, the latter of

  whom collaborated with Sidgwick in experiments in automatic or “spirit”

  writing. More important was the overall mission and method; in Janet

  Oppenheim’s view, the Apostolic “idea of a group of men meeting regu-

  larly to discuss, with utter frankness and without restrictions, questions

  of religious, philosophical, and ethical import” would inspire a number of

  those who went on to form the the Society for Psychical Research, in ,

 

‹ Prev