Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 33
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 33

by Bart Schultz


  who, just because they had these dispositions, were so strongly disposed to reject

  Utilitarianism and insist on the intrinsic value of these actions and of ends other

  than universal good.

  It follows that there is a deeply uneasy gap or dislocation in this type of theory

  between the spirit that is supposedly justified and the spirit of the theory that

  supposedly justifies it. The gap is not very clearly perceived, if at all, by Sidgwick, nor, in my view, is its significance fully or at all adequately understood by later

  theorists who have adopted very much Sidgwick’s position.

  As Williams recognizes, Sidgwick does have certain strategies for deal-

  ing with this dislocation not available to later utilitarians, albeit these are of

  a fairly elitist variety, such that the utilitarian theorists might be conceived

  as an elite class guiding, in Government House fashion, a less enlightened

  populace. But there are other responses to his critique as well, as later

  sections will explain, and it is mentioned here precisely because it applies

  more broadly than this passage suggests.

  In fact, something akin to Williams’s line of objection runs through

  a wide swath of criticism directed at the Methods, figuring in the argu-

  ments of perfectionists, virtue ethicists, anti-theorists, pragmatists, and

  others concerned to claim that Sidgwick just misses the point of the

  nonhedonistic alternatives. Indeed, it is a venerable line of argument,

  and something very like it was given in Rashdall’s review of the third

  edition of the Methods:

  We must believe in a future life, Prof. Sidgwick tells us, because we must believe

  that the constitution of things is rational. And yet, according to Prof. Sidgwick,

  the universe is so constituted that the man who most completely succeeds in

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  concealing from himself the true end of his being – or haply in never finding it

  out – will ultimately realise that end most thoroughly. A priori no one can deny that the universe may be so constituted; but where is the rationality of such a

  state of things? If we are to make assumptions, let them be such as will satisfy the

  logical demand on which they are founded. If we are to assume a rational order in

  the universe, surely the end prescribed to a man by his Reason must be his highest

  end. Man is so far a rational being that he is capable of preferring the rational

  to the pleasant. Surely, then, the reasonableness of such a preference cannot be

  dependent on its ultimately turning out that he has after all preferred the very things which his love of the reasonable led him to reject.

  Such objections have of course been seized on by many different critics

  of utilitarianism, anxious to demonstrate that this view cannot capture

  the recognition we accord to nonhedonistic values, or lives rather than

  acts, or other aspects of commonsense morality. Obviously, elegant and

  subtle as Sidgwick’s approach to happiness may be, it has not converted

  the legions of perfectionists or those defenders of “virtue ethics” who

  hold that the good life is one characterized by the exercise of certain

  excellences – courage, generosity, justice, and so forth – that are valuable

  for their own sake and constitute the happy life as parts of a whole, without

  requiring any reference to pleasure or desirable consciousness for their

  vindication.

  Now, again, Sidgwick was not unappreciative of the force of such views,

  or of the efforts of the ancients – “through a large part of the present work

  the influence of Plato and Aristotle on my treatment of this subject has

  been greater than that of any modern writer” (ME ) – but he could not

  persuade himself that they offered a genuinely constructive solution to the

  problems of ethics: “it seems worthy of remark that throughout the ethical

  speculation of Greece, such universal affirmations as are presented to us

  concerning Virtue or Good conduct seems always to be propositions which

  can only be defended from the charge of tautology, if they are understood

  as definitions of the problem to be solved, and not attempts at its solution”

  (ME –).

  Indeed, the Greek worldview was limited not only by its failure to artic-

  ulate the notion of disinterested duty. The “whole ethical controversy of

  ancient Greece,” on Sidgwick’s reading, was based on the assumption that

  “a rational individual would make the pursuit of his own good his supreme

  aim,” and in claiming that the good was best conceived not in terms of

  pleasure but in terms of virtue – a nonhedonist eudaimonism – figures

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  such as Aristotle simply lapsed into vagueness and tautology, defining

  virtue in terms of good and good in terms of virtue in a vicious circle (ME

  –). Clarity in this department required that it be possible to compare

  and contrast, to quantify at least in a rough way, the happiness generated

  by one activity rather than another, or by one life rather than another.

  Falling back on some diffuse notion of “judgment” was no determinate

  solution at all.

  Somewhat analogous objections are directed at the religious ethicist

  James Martineau, about whom, as Schneewind observes, Sidgwick wrote

  more than about any other contemporary excepting Herbert Spencer. For

  Martineau, the objects of ethical judgment are not things or acts per se

  but persons, and what is judged is always the “inner spring of action,”

  assessed according to a scale of motives. But this is scarcely a system at all,

  according to Sidgwick; it is either as vague as unrefined common sense

  or must collapse into a utilitarian calculation of the consequences flowing

  from the different motives in action.

  As negative as Sidgwick is on these matters, he obviously took the lower,

  “Goethean” ideal very seriously, even if he awkwardly tried to fold it into

  Whewellian intuitionism or at least to divide it into that and nonhedonistic

  egoism. His later engagements with the work of Green, Rashdall, and

  Moore would again suggest that he was in fact quite willing to treat this

  as, in effect, a separate method on its own terms, as he had in his earlier

  discussions with the Grote Club. Indeed, he was very appreciative of the

  classical influence on writers such as Green, and how this informed the

  rejection of any dualism of practical reason because, in T. H. Irwin’s words,

  “[t]he full realization of one person’s capacities requires him to will the

  good of other people for their own sake. We can show that the dualism of

  practical reason is avoidable if we can set out a true conception of a rational

&nbs
p; agent’s good.” This was, obviously, not a result to which Sidgwick was

  emotionally averse. However, as Irwin stresses,

  Sidgwick acknowledges Butler as the source of his own formulation of the dualism

  of practical reason; and he believes that Aristotelian non-hedonist eudaimonism

  allows us to think we have escaped the dualism simply because we mistake vague

  and useless formulations of substantive principles with practical consequences.

  Once we try to say more precisely what a person’s good consists in, we will see

  that we are either assuming some highly controversial claim about the relation of

  morality to self-love or opening the very gap that Sidgwick calls to our attention.

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  Sidgwick, therefore, cannot take seriously any attempt to derive practical con-

  clusions from a general conception of happiness such as the one Aristotle accepts;

  and he cannot endorse Aristotle’s attempt . . . to show that self-love, correctly understood, requires acceptance of morality.

  For Irwin, and for many others drawn to perfectionism or virtue ethics,

  Sidgwick’s main reason for rejecting nonhedonistic eudaimonism “rests

  on a demand for clarity that plays a highly controversial role at cru-

  cial points in The Methods of Ethics,” and that begs the question of

  whether this kind of clarity “is necessary or appropriate in this case.”

  Both Aristotle and Green could be given more generous readings, on

  this basis, though Irwin, like Schneewind, does agree with much of

  what Sidgwick says about the difference between ancient and modern

  ethics.

  Yet as Thomas Hurka has argued, Irwin is actually forced to concede

  on one truly fundamental issue, given the paradox of altruism:

  On no plausible perfectionist view can a person’s good consist entirely in promot-

  ing the good of others, and the other states that are good are ones for which conflict, especially over scarce resources, is possible. But Irwin does not state Sidgwick’s

  argument in its strongest form. As (accurately) characterized by Irwin, Green’s

  account of the good involves a vacuous circularity: each person’s good consists en-

  tirely in promoting the good of others, which consists entirely in their promoting the good of others, which consists entirely in their promoting, etc. Unless there is something else that is good, there is nothing for all this promoting to aim at. This

  is Sidgwick’s argument against the view that virtue, understood as pursuit of the

  good, can be the only intrinsic good. . . . And his response to Green therefore takes the form of a dilemma: for the good to be entirely non-competitive it must consist

  entirely in virtue, but then the theory of the good is vacuous; for the theory of the good not to be vacuous it must contain goods other than virtue, for which conflict

  is possible.

  Hurka goes on to observe, rightly, that Sidgwick’s hedonistic account

  does not simply follow from such criticism, since even “if virtue cannot

  be the only intrinsic good it can be one intrinsic good among others,

  and its being so can make the good less competitive than on views like

  Sidgwick’s.” Such options have been explored by Moore, Rashdall, Ross,

  and, more recently, by Hurka himself, who endorses part of Rashdall’s

  claim, against Sidgwick, that what the partisans of virtue value is “the

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  settled bent of the will towards that which is truly or essentially good, and

  not a mere capacity or potentiality of pleasure-producation such as might

  be supposed to reside in a bottle of old port.”

  According to Hurka, the more plausible versions of perfectionism –

  untouched by Sidgwick’s criticisms – make it clear that there “are initial

  goods such as the pleasure and knowledge of everyone, and then higher-

  level moral goods that consist in caring about those goods appropriately.

  That is a perfectionist view that values virtue but is not egoistic and

  not at all circular,” and in this it differs from ancient perfectionism and

  “the virtue ethics that is its contemporary descendant,” at least as these

  are understood by Irwin and many others. But Hurka also allows that

  many of the virtue ethicists who have objected to indirect or self-effacing

  forms of consequentialism have been guilty of an even severer form of

  moral schizophrenia. For consequentialists, including utilitarians, “the

  source of self-effacingness is a contingent psychological fact,” whereas

  “virtue-ethical theory must be non-contingently self-effacing,” since to

  “avoid encouraging self-indulgence, it must say that being motivated by

  its claims about the source of one’s reasons is in itself and necessarily

  objectionable.”

  As Sidgwick so often insisted, and as Hurka appears to admit, the

  Greeks can be plausibly understood as being in the main egoists, for whom

  cultivating one’s perfection or virtue was, after all, cultivating one’s own

  perfection or virtue. They were the forerunners of Arnoldian sweetness

  and light. One need only read, say, Aristotle on magnanimity to grasp how

  self-indulgent this orientation could become. Thus, it must be allowed

  that Sidgwick’s critical arguments carried and carry a good deal of force

  against some tremendously important ethical positions and thinkers, even

  if they cannot be credited with answering all the questions raised by his

  students Rashdall and Moore – who, after all, were developing Sidgwick’s

  project on many fronts.

  One might therefore conclude that however dismissive the treatment

  of Sidgwick’s hedonism has been, his arguments and those of his contem-

  poraries are nonetheless enjoying that curious vitality, characteristic of

  utilitarianism and egoism in general, that seems to come with having been

  pronounced dead so often. Just how vital this discussion is will become

  clearer in the sections to follow. This preliminary survey of the issues is

  meant simply to highlight various controversial elements of Sidgwick’s

  approach that need to be kept in mind in order to understand just how

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  carefully qualified his claims for utilitarianism actually were, and how

  fertile in philosophical insight they have proved to be.

  Of course, Sidgwick’s hedonistic interpretation of ultimate good, it

  should be stressed again, also falls afoul of the conception of utility at work

  in most orthodox neoclassical economics, where the notion of minimally
/>   consistent preference satisfaction, disallowing any interpersonal compar-

  isons of utility, serves as the last word on practical rationality (or at least has

  done so until recent decades). Yet, as Book II of the Methods handsomely

  demonstrates, Sidgwick was as painfully aware of the difficulties involved

  in adding up and comparing utilities as any twentieth-century economist –

  asking, for example, “who can tell that the philosopher’s constitution is not

  such as to render the enjoyments of the senses, in his case, comparatively

  feeble?” (ME ) He was, however, also cognizant of the unavoidability

  of making “comparisons between pleasures and pains with practical re-

  liance on their results,” for purposes both of ethics and of everyday life

  (ME ). The by now vast literature on the inadequacies of Pareto op-

  timality as a substitute for justice, although often working in the service

  of Kantian alternatives to utilitarianism, at least points up the intelligence

  of Sidgwick’s fundamental conviction – informed by a great deal of eco-

  nomic sophistication – that interpersonal (and intrapersonal) comparisons

  of some sort can hardly be avoided when discussing any marginally real-

  istic social scheme. The stronger point to make in this connection con-

  cerns the curious denouement for Benthamism that came with Sidgwick’s

  candid, frustrated confession that “in the development of human nature,

  the incalculable element increases at a more rapid ratio than the calcu-

  lable.” How overly ambitious could he have been, when he claimed that

  “I think that with great trouble one may come to calculate the sources of

  such happiness as may then be found to be nearly valueless to us”?

  III. The Methods of Ethics: Common Sense, Intuition,

  and Certainty

  The orthodox moralists such as Whewell (then in vogue) said that there was a

  whole intelligible system of intuitions: but how were they to be learnt? I could

  not accept Butler’s view as to the sufficiency of a plain man’s conscience: for it

  appeared to me that plain men agreed rather verbally than really.

  In this state of mind I had to read Aristotle again; and a light seemed to dawn

  upon me as to the meaning and drift of his procedure – especially in Books ii.,

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN

 

‹ Prev