Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 65
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 65

by Bart Schultz


  tian conception of human beings as the children of God – souls endowed

  with free will and somewhere in between the beasts and the angels, striving

  or being drawn to ever fuller awareness of the Divine spark within, the very

  ground of one’s being. Persons are special; the experience of freedom that

  each has is revelatory of how much more there is than the natural world.

  Sidgwick would always admit the force of the key analogy: “If the aggre-

  gate of thoughts and feelings into which the world as empirically known

  to me is analysable has every element of it connected by reference to a self-

  conscious subject, we may argue from analogy that there must be such a

  subject similarly related to the Universe” (LPK ). Consciousness, as so

  many philosophers of mind continue to urge, just does manifest a special

  unity and integration. With Green, there is a further Hegelian admixture

  in this, since the striving for perfection involves a world-historical form

  of spiritual progress, but his is decidedly a Hegel moderated by Kant and

  by a warmer feeling for the achievements of English civilization.

  The Hegelian twist in Green’s remarks, to the effect that a deeper

  logic can account for the necessary appearance of circularity in ordinary

  reasoning – which was just bound to be incoherent when it bumped up

  against its limits – would appear time and again in Idealist criticisms

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  of Sidgwick. In fact, the first Idealist salvo against Sidgwick’s Methods,

  in print at least, came not from Green but from Bradley, whose Ethical

  Studies appeared in . This work, often regarded as the breakthrough

  statement of British Idealism, makes some reference to Sidgwick, who in

  turn reviewed it in Mind – rather unfavorably:

  At any rate, whatever the author may have intended, I venture to think that

  uncritical dogmatism constitutes the largest and most interesting element of

  Mr. Bradley’s work. It is true that his polemical writing, especially his attack on

  ethical and psychological hedonism . . . is always vigorous, and frequently acute and suggestive: but often again, just at the nodes of his argument, he lapses provokingly into mere debating-club rhetoric; and his apprehension of the views which

  he assails is always rather superficial and sometimes even unintelligent. This last

  defect seems partly due to his limited acquaintance with the whole process of

  English ethical thought, partly to the contemptuous asperity with which he treats

  opposing doctrines: for really penetrating criticism, especially in ethics, requires

  a patient effort of intellectual sympathy which Mr. Bradley has never learned

  to make, and a tranquillity of temper which he seems incapable of maintaining.

  Nor again, does he appear to have effectively criticised his own fundamental po-

  sitions, before putting them before the public. His main ethical principle is that

  Self-Realisation is the ultimate end of practice: but in Essay II . . . the reader is startled by the communication that Mr. Bradley “does not properly speaking know

  what he means when he says ‘self ’ and ‘real’ and ‘realise’.” The frankness of this

  confession disarms satire. . . .

  Manifestly, Sidgwick was out to teach his obnoxious, irritable junior

  from Oxford a few Apostolic lessons about how to pursue truth. This

  review was followed up, in Mind, by an unrepentant reply from Bradley

  and a further rejoinder from Sidgwick – if anything even more damning,

  though also quite revealing:

  Mr. Bradley seems to be under a strange impression that, while professing to

  write a critical notice of his views on ethics, I have been or ought to have been –

  defending my own. I entertain quite a different notion of a reviewer’s ‘station and

  duties.’ In criticising his book (or any other) I put out of sight my own doctrines,

  in so far as I am conscious of them as peculiar to myself: and pass my judgments

  from a point of view which I expect my readers generally to share with me. Hence

  the references in his reply to my opinions would be quite irrelevant, even if he

  understood those opinions somewhat better than he does. I passed lightly over

  his attack on Hedonism in Essay III for the simple reason – which I gave – that I

  thought it less interesting and important than other parts of his work. Much of it,

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  as he must be perfectly aware, either has no bearing on Hedonism as I conceive it,

  or emphasises defects which I have myself pointed out: the rest consists chiefly of

  familiar anti-hedonistic commonplaces: the freshest argument I could find was one

  with which I had made acquaintance some years ago in Mr. Green’s Introduction

  to Hume. This, as stated by Mr. Green, I have taken occasion to answer in the

  course of an article in the present number of this journal. The attack on my

  book appended to Essay III, though not uninstructive to myself, is far too full of

  misunderstandings to be profitable for discussion. It is criticism of the kind that

  invites explanation rather than defense: such explanation I proposed to give in its

  proper place – which was certainly not my notice of Mr. Bradley.

  In short, Sidgwick has “nothing to retract or qualify on any of the

  points raised by Mr. Bradley – except a pair of inverted commas which

  were accidentally attached to a phrase of my own.” Apparently, he held

  to this (plausible) judgment that whatever was interesting in Bradley was

  due to Green and that he was better off addressing the latter; at least, he

  would continue to write and lecture about Green’s philosophy, while flatly

  ignoring Bradley’s further productions, including the long pamphlet on

  “Mr. Sidgwick’s Hedonism” that appeared in .

  As Schneewind has suggested, Sidgwick was largely right to be unim-

  pressed by Bradley’s early statement of the Idealist case. The best one can

  say of Bradley’s charges – for example, that the very notion of a sum of

  pleasures is incoherent, like all the rest of phenomenal appearances – is

  that they “depend on certain doctrines, concerning either the internal-

  ity of relations, which makes certain types of abstraction illegitimate, or

  the concrete universal as the necessary structure of the moral end, which

  makes it impossible that the end should be a ‘mere aggregate’,” and these

  doctrines are scarcely developed in either Bradley or Green when they

  criticize Sidgwick. Indeed, Bradley’s larger view in Ethical Studies rests

  “on the unstated Hegelian idea that the world spirit, operating through

  us, moves ever onward to new stages in its development. The task of the

  philosophical owl that flies at twilight is to articulate the developments

>   the world spirit has already undergone. Philosophy can no more antici-

  pate its evolution in morality than it can in science.” Thus, as Schneewind

  notes, this position is fundamentally at odds “with Sidgwick’s belief that

  the same principle which provides an adequate explication of the ‘morality

  current in the world’ must also provide the basis for a method of rectifying

  that morality.” Bradley’s plain man, who has identified with the moral

  spirit of his community and acts out of decent unreflective habit, has no

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  need of the philosopher, who, if it is Bradley, will insist that the philoso-

  pher is indeed perfectly useless and has absolutely nothing to contribute

  to ordinary practice, to making the world a better place.

  Given the general fate of Idealist metaphysics and logic, it would be

  easy to conclude that what was lurking behind the Idealists’ criticisms

  of Sidgwick was not such as to seriously threaten the viability of his

  views, however powerful the academic standing of Idealism was during

  its heyday. And in fact, when Sidgwick does address Green, it is for

  the most part in a remarkably effective manner. For Green rather obvi-

  ously misunderstood utilitarianism from beginning to end, more or less

  constantly confusing it with hedonistic psychological egoism and render-

  ing it as a mishmash of the least compelling parts of Bentham and Mill.

  Sidgwick, in addressing the bits from the Prolegomena quoted earlier, has a

  fairly easy time of it, given the gulf of implausibility lying between his min-

  imal metaethical account of reason and the full-blooded Idealist account,

  with all its perfectionist elements:

  If such objects, then, as Truth, Freedom, and Beauty, or strictly speaking, the

  objective relations of conscious minds which we call cognition of Truth, con-

  templation of Beauty and Independence of Action, are good, independently of

  the pleasures that we derive from them, it must be reasonable to aim at these for

  mankind generally, and not at happiness only: and this view seems, though not

  the prevailing one, to be widely accepted among cultivated persons.

  When I compare the cognition of Truth, contemplation of Beauty, volition to

  realise Freedom or Virtue, with Pleasure, in respect of their relation to Ultimate

  Good, I would justify my own view that it is Pleasure alone, desirable Feeling, that

  is ultimately and intrinsically good, by the only kind of argument of which the case

  seems to me to admit. I would point out that we may be led to regard as mistaken our

  preferences for the conditions, concomitants or consequences of consciousness, as

  distinguished from the consciousness itself, and in order to show this, I would ask

  the reader to use the same twofold procedure that I have regarded as applicable

  in considering the absolute and independent validity of common moral precepts.

  I would appeal, firstly, to his intuitive judgment after due consideration of the

  question fairly placed before it: and, secondly, to a comprehensive comparison

  of the ordinary judgments of mankind. As regards the first argument, to me at

  least it seems clear that these objective relations of the conscious subject, when

  distinguished in reflective analysis from the consciousness accompanying and

  resulting from them, are not ultimately and intrinsically desirable, any more than

  material or other objects are, when considered out of relation to conscious existence altogether.

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  Now, how does Green answer this argument? So far as I can see, he ignores it.

  He answers . . . an argument, involving Psychological Hedonism, which I do not use; and which he admits that I do not use. (GSM –)

  Here again, as described in Chapter , Sidgwick, the man so heavily laden

  with a finely tuned cognitive apparatus, thinks his way to a celebration of

  Feeling, the “other” of his psyche, as the source of intrinsic value. He

  does not, in his sensitive discrimination of the various pleasures, altogether

  relinquish the appeal to their feeling tone. Indeed, as for the charge of

  “tautology,” Sidgwick deems it “quite unwarrantable.” Even considering

  only the presentation of the argument in the Methods, Book III, Chapter ,

  Green’s case fails:

  For the object of a great part of this argument is carefully to distinguish pleasure

  or happiness – desirable Feeling – from other elements of conscious life, which I do not, in a reflective attitude, regard as ultimately desirable. To say that the

  ‘only thing that reason declares to be ultimately desirable is some kind of feeling,’

  whatever it is, is not a tautology, nor the same thing as saying that it is some kind of conscious life. But again, Green’s statement of my view leaves out the further

  determination of the kind of feeling which is given in the definition of Pleasure,

  and which I fondly supposed that the reader would carry with him from Book II.

  I there define Pleasure as ‘the kind of feeling which, when we experience it, we

  apprehend as desirable or preferable’ – as ‘feeling that is preferable or desirable,

  considered merely as feeling, and therefore from a point of view from which the

  judgment of the sentient individual is final.’ The statement that Ultimate Good

  is feeling of a certain quality, the quality being estimated by the judgement of

  value implicitly passed on it by the sentient being at the time of feeling it, – this proposition is certainly not a tautology.

  A similar want of understanding of my distinction between ‘desired’ and ‘desir-

  able’ appears in Green’s subsequent arguments. . . . I do not argue that the reason why ‘no one denies pleasure to be a good’ is merely ‘because he is conscious

  of desiring it,’ for I maintain that we all have experiences of desires directed to

  wrong objects, and also to objects clearly not ultimately desirable – e.g. in resent-

  ful impulse I desire another’s pain, but on reflection I do not judge this pain to

  be desirable because I desire it, but because it is necessary for the determent or

  reformation of the offender.

  Again, I cannot conceive why ‘desirable’ should exclude the ‘actually desired,’

  as is argued by Green. . . . Of course we should not apply the idea of ‘desirable’ as distinct from ‘desired,’ unless we had empirical evidence that we desire pleasures

  to some extent out of proportion to their value as pleasures; but it does not follow

  that feeling actually desired is not normally, in the main, feeling judged desirable

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

   />
  when fruition comes: as overwhelming experience shows to be in fact the case.

  (GSM –)

  Thus, although Sidgwick was wary of identifying, in Benthamite fash-

  ion, one particular mental quality of pleasure or pain, he did invoke the

  family of feelings that counted as desirable consciousness. And this was

  important, pointing to how he in effect used an “experience requirement”

  (as noted in Chapter ) to show that his account of Good did not bump

  up against the limits of thought as the Idealists claimed.

  In fact, the upshot of this engagement with Green is to turn the tables,

  to seek to recruit Green for the Sidgwickian camp:

  With part of Green’s controversy against Mill – that which is directed against

  Psychological Hedonism – I am almost entirely in accord – that is to say, I agree

  with his conclusion that the object of conscious desire and voluntary aim is not

  pleasure only. And I agree in the main with the explanation he gives of the preva-

  lence of the opposite error – that is, that pleasure normally accompanies the

  attainment of the desired object, and that hence it is easy to conceive this pleasure as the real object aimed at. But the same analysis which shows me that I do not

  always aim at my own pleasure, shows me equally that I do not always aim at my

  own satisfaction. I reject, in the one case as in the other, the conscious egoism

  of the form in which human choice is conceived – except in the insignificant

  sense that I am conscious that what I desire and aim at is desired and aimed

  at by me – a tautological proposition. In fact, I find a considerable difficulty in

  distinguishing what Green calls self-satisfaction from pleasure. And so far as I

  can distinguish them, – so far as I can conceive the consciousness of attainment

  of a desired object separated from pleasure, – it is something I do not desire.

  (GSM )

  As in the case of Bradley, Sidgwick cannot make out what Green really

  means by “Self-satisfaction,” or whether he has any coherent notion of

  it. And this is crucial, since Green seems to be offering up his Idealism

  as a philosophical form of the reconciliation project, achieving through

  the notions of “good” and “perfection” what Sidgwick had called in the

  theistic postulate to deal with. But Sidgwick wonders whether, despite

 

‹ Prev