Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 125
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 125

by Bart Schultz

:

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  and patient care the Morality of Common Sense. I referred to the moral

  judgements – and especially the spontaneous unreflected judgments on

  particular cases, which are sometimes called moral intuitions – of those

  persons, to be found in all walks and stations of life, whose earnest and

  predominant aim is to do their duty.” These are the persons of whom the

  verse rang that “though they slip and fall, / They do not blind their souls

  with clay,” and they are such that “after each lapse and failure recover and

  renew their rectitude of purpose and their sense of the supreme value of

  goodness.” Sidgwick has in mind here not the denizens of “hermitages

  and retreats,” but persons

  in the thick and heat of the struggle of active life, in all stations and ranks, in the churches and outside the churches. It is to them we have appealed for aid and

  sympathy in the great task that we have undertaken; and it is to their judgments

  on the duties of their station, in whatever station they may be found, that the

  moral philosopher should, as I have said, give reverent attention, in order that he

  may be aided and controlled by them in his theoretical construction of the Science

  of Right. (PE –)

  But again, the study of common sense, the normal man of the

  Benthamites now become a medical classification, was in Sidgwick’s hands

  a very worried affair, the piercing of the veil to get at the true self that was

  rapidly becoming the study of abnormal psychology. Knowing what made

  people tick ethically remained for him an inquiry of the utmost urgency,

  and consequently theism was, as always, very much on the agenda during

  this gathering up of the “fragments that remain.”

  II. Reasonable Persons

  For Sidgwick’s part, as his letters to Ward and Balfour demonstrate, he was

  still under no illusions about the difference between hoping that theism

  was true and actually showing that it was. As he unmistakably put it in

  Philosophy, Its Scope and Relations – by his own account one of the most

  finished of his unpublished works and one that he thought might suitably

  be published – although many thoughtful persons have been persuaded

  of the truth of theism,

  I myself regard Theism as a belief which, though borne in upon the living mind

  through life, and essential to normal life, is not self-evident or capable of being

  cogently demonstrated. It belongs, therefore, to a class of beliefs which I do not

  P: IJD/GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Last Words?

  

  dispute the general reasonableness of accepting, but which I think have to be

  considered carefully and apart in estimating the grounds of their acceptance –

  assumptions for which we cannot but demand further proof, though we may see

  no means of obtaining it. (PSR )

  All his old views about the spirit of the age being theistic, but with Chris-

  tianity still playing a valuable social role, emerge again in this context. He

  has some sympathetic feeling for those who turn to external authority in

  search of faith, but he cannot follow them. What he still feels so acutely is

  the emotional unsatisfactoriness of his views:

  [I]n opposing your argument [Ward’s on the role of saints], I intended to limit

  myself to the sociological point of view: from which morality does not seem to me

  to lead us to Theism. But I did not mean to say that I could be satisfied to regard morality exclusively from this point of view: quite the reverse: I hold strongly that sociological inquiry cannot answer the deepest questions which the individual,

  reflecting on his moral judgments and impulses, is inevitably led to ask. And

  where Sociology fails, the need of Theism – or at least some doctrine establishing

  the moral order of the world – seems to me clear.

  As to the definition of Theism – I should think a provisional definition would

  not be difficult to agree on, if any one wants it. But I should have thought we might wait till any serious divergence in our conceptions disclosed itself. (CWC)

  Of course, various deep differences did appear. One crisis came when

  early on Myers wanted to give a paper “to discuss what he conceives

  to be the limitations of Christianity from the point of view of a wider

  religious outlook,” which Sidgwick did not think a bad subject, though

  “it had better come later.” When it came, the “wider religious outlook”

  clearly had a lot of Whitmanian Cosmic Enthusiasm in it, and caused

  Father Tyrrell no little pain. Myers had apparently been “quite unaware

  of ‘thunder in the air’ ” and claimed to have expressed himself “in simple

  confidence in the general good humour that he thought prevailed.” And

  Sidgwick urged that “I feel very strongly that anything like ‘crowing’ over

  ‘adhesion’ as Tyrrell calls it is a great mistake: it must tend to repress

  the perfect frankness on which both the pleasure and the profit of such

  debates depends.” (CWC)

  “Adhesiveness” was of course Whitman’s term of art for spiritualized

  but sensual male comradeship, and Myers may well have sounded a good

  deal like Symonds, though it may also be that Father Tyrrell was thinking

  of adhesion in the narrower sense of religious conformity.

  P: IJD/GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  To be sure, Sidgwick had not given up exploring the various possibilities

  for harmonizing duty and interest. “On the Nature of the Evidence for

  Theism” in fact reads like a continuation of the conclusion of the Methods,

  especially after the third edition. The entire problematic is set out in just

  the same fashion:

  Theism is a philosophical doctrine: it is the primary aim of philosophy to unify

  completely, bring into clear coherence, all departments of rational thought; and

  this aim cannot be realised by any philosophy that leaves out of its view the

  important body of judgments and reasoning which form the subject matter of

  Ethics. And it seems especially impossible, in attempting the construction of a

  Theistic Philosophy, to leave Ethics on one side. No view of Theism – as X

  [presumably Ward] says – “is of much importance to mankind which does not

  include the conception of a Sovereign Will that orders all things”; and if – as

  he goes on to say – “the only form of dogmatic religion worth arguing about is

  Christianity,” I think we may agree to add one word to the statement previously

  quoted, and say “A Sovereign Will that orders all things rightly.” For this reason I cannot agree to discard from our discussions – even provisionally – “arguments

  drawn from the indications of ethical experience.”

  But here again I should like to go as far as I can to meet X’s views. I quite admit


  that when we contemplate human morality from the point of view from which the

  historian or sociologist naturally contemplates it – regarding it as a body of rules

  of conduct supported by social sentiments of approval and disapproval, which

  a normal member of society shares, and through sympathy with others applies

  reflectively to his own conduct as well as to the conduct of others – it certainly

  does not seem “easy to prove that the Theistic hypothesis is necessary to account

  for its existence.” Especially when we direct our attention to the variations in

  prevalent moral opinion and sentiment, which are observable as we pass in our

  contemplative survey from age to age, and from one contemporary society to

  another; the fluid and changing results that impartial observation thus seems to

  yield hardly even suggest the hypothesis of “super human institution”; they are

  more naturally viewed as a part of the complex adaptation of social man to the

  varying conditions of gregarious existence, civilised and uncivilised. Nor would

  the fact that saints generally have found themselves irresistibly led to regard

  moral rules as the dictates of a Divine Ruler weigh with me much on the other

  side; unless I were assured that the saints in question had made a systematic

  attempt to contemplate the variations in positive morality from a sociological

  point of view – which is not, so far as I know the case. But all such sociological

  observation of morality ignores the question which, from the point of view of

  the reflective individual, is the fundamental question of ethics, ‘Why should I,

  always and in all circumstances, do what is most conducive to the well-being of

  P: IJD/GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Last Words?

  

  my society, or of humanity at large?’ To answer this question satisfactorily, we have to find a solution of the primâ facie conflict between an individual’s interest and his social duty, which the actual conditions of human life from time to time present.

  Optimistic moralists of the last century attempted to obtain the required solution

  by establishing a perfect coincidence of interest and duty on a strictly empirical

  basis; but such attempts are now, I think, abandoned by serious thinkers; and yet

  some solution must be found, if the normal judgments of our practical reason are

  to be reduced to a coherent system. It is this consideration which led Kant to

  affirm with so much emphasis the indispensability of Theism in the construction

  of an ethical system: “Without a God and without a world, not visible to us now

  but hoped for, the glorious ideas of morality are indeed objects of applause and

  admiration, but not springs of purpose and action, because they fail to fulfil all the aims which are natural to every rational being.” This language is too sweeping to

  express my own convictions: still, the importance of the conception of the moral

  government of the world, in giving the required systematic coherence to Ethics,

  seems to me so great that I cannot consent to discard this consideration – even

  provisonally – in seeking a ‘working philosophy’ of Theism. (M –)

  This is a nice appropriation of Jamesian language and, as usual, a shrewd

  assessment of Kant’s deeper concerns, but as Sidgwick realizes, the

  natural objection is that this establishes only the convenience of believing

  in theism, not the evidence of its truth. Again, he sounds much the same

  note as that struck in the Methods: “To this I should reply by asking whether any philosophical theory can ever be established, if we are not to accept as

  evidence of its truth the fact that it introduces unity, harmony, systematic

  coherence into our thought, and removes the conflict and contradiction

  which would otherwise exist in the whole or some department of it?”

  (M )

  The main difference is that Sidgwick goes on to explore this possibility

  at greater length, addressing in more detail the matter of “the analogy

  between hypotheses that are verifiable and those that are not verifiable

  by human experience.” He readily admits that “those sciences which can

  point to exact particular predictions, made before the event and realised

  by the event, acquire thereby a claim to our confidence, which must be

  wanting to any philosophy of Theism, based on the data which we at

  present possess.” Theism ought to predict “the complete realisation of

  Divine Justice in the ordering of the world of humanity and the individual

  lives of men: and it admittedly cannot show the realisation of this predic-

  tion in past experience.” Still, Sidgwick confesses that he is not willing to

  P: IJD/GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  admit “that verification by particular experiences and cogent demonstra-

  tion from incontrovertible premises are the only modes of attaining the

  kind and degree of certitude which we require for a ‘working philosophy.’ ”

  And here Sidgwick adds some very interesting (and personal) insights and

  examples, arguing against a too-narrow construction of “verification by

  experience.”

  The criterion that we find really decisive, in case after case, is not any particular new sense-perception, or group of new sense-perceptions, but consistency with

  an elaborate and complex system of beliefs, in which the results of an indefinite

  number of perceptions and inferences are combined. Let me take a case of some

  current interest. Many of the vulgar and a few educated persons still believe

  that there are such things as ‘ghosts’ moving about in space. The vulgar naively

  consider that this general statement is ‘verified’ by the numerous experiences

  of ‘seeing ghosts,’ which undoubtedly do occur to some persons from time to

  time. But no educated person thinks that the mere fact of A’s ‘seeing’ a ghost

  is any evidence at all for the above generalisation: he unhesitatingly concludes

  that the apparent vision of an external object is in this case merely apparent, an

  ‘hallucination.’ And why? Surely because the existence of something so material as

  to produce through the organ of vision the apparent perception of a human figure,

  and yet so immaterial as to pass through the wall of a room, is incompatible with

  his general conception of the physical world. Suppose this general conception

  different, and the “verification” might be accepted by a mind far from credulous.

  Indeed, the history of thought shows this. Epicurus was not in his age regarded

  as prone to superstition, but rather as the great deliverer from the terrors of

  superstition; yet Epicurus held it to be an important argument for the existence

  of Gods that phantasms of them appear to men in dreams and visions.

  It seems to me, then, that if we are led to accept Theism as being, more than

  any other view of the Universe, consistent with, and calculated to impart
a clear

  consistency to, the whole body of what we commonly agree to take for knowledge –

  including knowledge of right and wrong – we accept it on grounds analogous to

  those on which important scientific conclusions have been accepted; and that,

  even though we are unable to add the increase of certitude derivable from verified

  predictions, we may still attain a sufficient strength of reasoned conviction to

  justify us in calling our conclusions a “working philosophy.” (M –)

  But this is a very big “if.” Although this may appear to be a rather

  more holistic, coherentist sentiment than that expressed in the Methods,

  the notion of a “working philosophy” may not be all that different from

  the “provisional” postulate that had kept Sidgwick going until his crisis

  in the eighties. He was, after the fashion of Mill on theism, in that region of

  P: IJD/GCV

  c.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Last Words?

  

  legitimate hope that had not been foreclosed by the evidence. It was still, as

  he argued in Philosophy, Its Scope and Relations, not possible to give theism a completely “cogent” demonstration, however reasonable it might seem.

  Interestingly, when Ward reviewed Henry Sidgwick, A Memoir, Eleanor

  Sidgwick would write in response: “I am glad you dwell on the optimism.

  Some have said that the life gives them a sad impression. Of course there

  was an element of disappointment that he had not been able to find the

  truth he sought, but his life was certainly a happy and a hopeful one in

  spite of occasional depression.” This should be read as an affirmation

  that Sidgwick remained less than fully convinced by and content with the

  coherentist argument. As Maitland observed, if Sidgwick had not been

  Sidgwick, “he might, as others often do, have forgotten the exact point

  where proof ended and only hope remained.” But he never did.

  Plausibly, Sidgwick’s final position did lend some support to the nascent

  pragmatist movement. Had he been able to embrace mere reasonableness

  as what the human world offers and to shake off the feeling that he was

  provisionally settling for a second-best, functional view, he might deserve

 

‹ Prev