The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Home > Other > The Omnibus Homo Sacer > Page 29
The Omnibus Homo Sacer Page 29

by Giorgio Agamben


  not subject to the law [ ipsa necessitas dispensationem habet annexam, quia necessitas

  non subditur legi].

  Here, the theory of necessity is none other than a theory of the exception

  ( dispensatio) by virtue of which a particular case is released from the obligation to observe the law. Necessity is not a source of law, nor does it properly suspend

  the law; it merely releases a particular case from the literal application of the

  norm: “He who acts beyond the letter of the law in a case of necessity does not

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  187

  judge by the law itself but judges by the particular case, in which he sees that the

  letter of the law is not to be observed [ non iudicat de ipsa lege, sed iudicat de casu singulari, in quo videt verba legis observanda non esse].” The ultimate ground of

  the exception here is not necessity but the principle according to which “every

  law is ordained for the common well-being of men, and only for this does it

  have the force and reason of law [ vim et rationem legis]; if it fails in this regard, it has no capacity to bind [ virtutem obligandi non habet].” In the case of necessity, the vis obligandi of the law fails, because in this case the goal of salus hominum is lacking. What is at issue here is clearly not a status or situation of the juridical order as such (the state of exception or necessity); rather, in each instance

  it is a question of a particular case in which the vis and ratio of the law find no application.

  א We find an example of the law’s ceasing to apply ex dispensatione misercordiae

  [out of a dispensation of mercy] in a peculiar passage from Gratian where the canonist

  states that the Church can elect not to punish a transgression in a situation where the

  transgressive deed has already occurred ( pro eventu rei [for the consequence of the thing]: for example in a case where a person who could not accede to the episcopate

  has in fact already been ordained as bishop). Paradoxically, the law is not applied here

  precisely because the transgressive act has effectively already been committed and pun-

  ishing it would anyway entail negative consequences for the Church. In analyzing this

  text, Anton Schütz has rightly observed that “in conditioning validity by facticity, in

  seeking contact with an extrajuridical reality, [Gratian] prevents the law from referring

  only to the law, and thus prevents the closure of the juridical system” (Schütz 1995,

  120). In this sense, the medieval exception represents an opening of the juridical system

  to an external fact, a sort of fictio legis by which, in this case, one acts as if the bishop had been legitimately elected. The modern state of exception is instead an attempt to

  include the exception itself within the juridical order by creating a zone of indistinction in which fact and law coincide.

  א We find an implicit critique of the state of exception in Dante’s De monarchia.

  Seeking to prove that Rome gained dominion over the world not through violence but

  iure, Dante states that it is impossible to obtain the end of law (that is, the common good) without law, and that therefore “whoever intends to achieve the end of law, must proceed

  with law [ quicunque finem iuris intendit cum iure graditur]” (2.5.22). The idea that a suspension of law may be necessary for the common good is foreign to the medieval world.

  1.10. It is only with the moderns that the state of necessity tends to be in-

  cluded within the juridical order and to appear as a true and proper “state” of

  the law. The principle according to which necessity defines a unique situation in

  which the law loses its vis obligandi (this is the sense of the adage necessitas legem

  188

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  non habet) is reversed, becoming the principle according to which necessity con-

  stitutes, so to speak, the ultimate ground and very source of the law. This is true

  not only for those writers who sought in this way to justify the national interests

  of one state against another (as in the formula Not kennt kein Gebot [necessity

  knows no law], used by the Prussian Chancellor Bethmann-Hollweg and taken

  up again in Josef Kohler’s book of that title [1915]), but also for those jurists,

  from Jellinek to Duguit, who see necessity as the foundation of the validity of

  decrees having force of law issued by the executive in the state of exception.

  It is interesting to analyze from this perspective the extreme position of

  Santi Romano, a jurist who had a considerable influence on European legal

  thought between the wars. For Romano, not only is necessity not unrelated to

  the juridical order, but it is the first and originary source of law. He begins by

  distinguishing between, on the one hand, those who see necessity as a jurid-

  ical fact or even a subjective right of the state, which is ultimately grounded

  as such in the legislation in force and in the general principles of law, and, on

  the other hand, those who think necessity is a mere fact and that therefore the

  emergency [ eccezionali] powers founded upon it have no basis in the legislative

  system. According to Romano, both positions, which agree in their identifi-

  cation of the juridical order [ il diritto] with the law [ la legge],* are incorrect, insofar as they disavow the existence of a true and proper source of law beyond

  legislation.

  The necessity with which we are concerned here must be conceived of as a state

  of affairs that, at least as a rule and in a complete and practically effective way,

  cannot be regulated by previously established norms. But if it has no law, it makes

  law, as another common expression has it; which means that it itself constitutes a

  true and proper source of law. . . . It can be said that necessity is the first and orig-

  inary source of all law, such that by comparison the others are to be considered

  somehow derivative. . . . And it is to necessity that the origin and legitimation of

  the legal institution par excellence, namely, the state, and its constitutional order

  in general, must be traced back, when it is established as a de facto process, for

  example, on the way to revolution. And what occurs in the initial moment of a

  particular regime can also repeat itself, though in an exceptional way and with

  more attenuated characteristics, even after the regime has formed and regulated

  its fundamental institutions. (Romano 1909, 362)

  * The two terms here are diritto and legge, both of which are usually translated in English as “law.”

  While these terms have close correspondences in French ( droit, loi), Spanish ( derecho, ley), and German ( Recht, Gesetz), some of their sense is inevitably lost in the passage to English. Among their meanings, diritto carries the sense of law in the abstract, or the entire sphere of law, while legge refers to the specific body of rules that a community or state considers binding. Here and in a few other cases where this distinction is critical, I have, following the author’s suggestion, rendered diritto as “the juridical order” and legge as “the law.”—Trans.

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  189

  As a figure of necessity, the state of exception therefore appears (alongside

  revolution and the de facto establishment of a constitutional system) as an

  “ illegal” but perfectly “juridical and constitutional” measure that is realized in

  the production of new norms (or of a new juridical order):

  The formula . . . according to which, in Italian law, the state of siege is a mea-

  sure that is contr
ary to the law (let us even say illegal) but is at the same time in

  conformity with the unwritten positive law, and is for this reason juridical and

  constitutional, seems to be the most accurate and fitting formula. From both

  the logical and the historical points of view, necessity’s ability to overrule the

  law derives from its very nature and its originary character. Certainly, the law

  has by now become the highest and most general manifestation of the juridical

  norm, but it is an exaggeration to want to extend its dominion beyond its own

  field. There are norms that cannot or should not be written; there are others that

  cannot be determined except when the circumstances arise for which they must

  serve. (Romano 1909, 364)

  The gesture of Antigone, which opposed the written law to the agrapta nomima

  [unwritten laws] is here reversed and asserted in defense of the constituted order.

  But in 1944, by which timea civil war was under way in his country, the elderly ju-

  rist (who had already studied the de facto establishment of constitutional orders)

  returned to consider the question of necessity, this time in relation to revolution.

  Although revolution is certainly a state of fact that “cannot be regulated in its

  course by those state powers that it tends to subvert and destroy” and in this sense

  is by definition “antijuridical, even when it is just” (Romano 1983, 222), it can,

  however, appear this way only

  with respect to the positive law of the state against which it is directed, but that

  does not mean that, from the very different point of view from which it defines

  itself, it is not a movement ordered and regulated by its own law. This also means

  that it is an order that must be classified in the category of originary juridical

  orders, in the now well-known sense given to this expression. In this sense, and

  within the limits of the sphere we have indicated, we can thus speak of a law of

  revolution. An examination of how the most important revolutions, including

  the most recent ones, have unfolded would be of great interest for demonstrating

  the thesis that we have advanced, which could at first sight seem paradoxical:

  revolution is violence, but it is juridically organized violence. (Romano 1983, 224)

  Thus, in the forms of both the state of exception and revolution, the status

  necessitatis appears as an ambiguous and uncertain zone in which de facto pro-

  ceedings, which are in themselves extra- or antijuridical, pass over into law, and

  juridical norms blur with mere fact—that is, a threshold where fact and law

  190

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  seem to become undecidable. If it has been effectively said that in the state of

  exception fact is converted into law (“Emergency is a state of fact; however, as

  the brocard fittingly says, e facto oritur ius [law arises from fact]” [Arangio-Ruiz 1913, 528]), the opposite is also true, that is, that an inverse movement also acts

  in the state of exception, by which law is suspended and obliterated in fact. The

  essential point, in any case, is that a threshold of undecidability is produced at

  which factum and ius fade into each other.

  Hence the aporias that every attempt to define necessity is unable to resolve.

  If a measure taken out of necessity is already a juridical norm and not simply

  fact, why must it be ratified and approved by a law, as Santi Romano (along with

  the majority of writers) believes it must? If it is already law, why does it not last if

  it is not approved by the legislative bodies? And if instead it is not law, but sim-

  ply fact, why do the legal effects of its ratification begin not from the moment

  it is converted into law, but ex tunc [from then]? (Duguit rightly notes that this retroactivity is a fiction and that ratification can produce its effects only from the

  moment at which it occurs [Duguit 1930, 754].)

  But the extreme aporia against which the entire theory of the state of neces-

  sity ultimately runs aground concerns the very nature of necessity, which writers

  continue more or less unconsciously to think of as an objective situation. This

  naive conception—which presupposes a pure factuality that the conception it-

  self has called into question—is easily critiqued by those jurists who show that,

  far from occurring as an objective given, necessity clearly entails a subjective

  judgment, and that obviously the only circumstances that are necessary and

  objective are those that are declared to be so.

  The concept of necessity is an entirely subjective one, relative to the aim that one

  wants to achieve. It may be said that necessity dictates the issuance of a given

  norm, because otherwise the existing juridical order is threatened with ruin; but

  there must be agreement on the point that the existing order must be preserved.

  A revolutionary uprising may proclaim the necessity of a new norm that annuls

  the existing institutions that are contrary to the new exigencies; but there must

  be agreement in the belief that the existing order must be disrupted in observance

  of new exigencies. In both cases . . . the recourse to necessity entails a moral or

  political (or, in any case, extrajuridical) evaluation, by which the juridical order

  is judged and is held to be worthy of preservation or strengthening even at the

  price of its possible violation. For this reason, the principle of necessity is, in every

  case, always a revolutionary principle. (Balladore-Pallieri 1970, 168)

  The attempt to resolve the state of exception into the state of necessity thus

  runs up against as many and even more serious aporias of the phenomenon that

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  191

  it should have explained. Not only does necessity ultimately come down to a

  decision, but that on which it decides is, in truth, something undecidable in

  fact and law.

  א Schmitt (who refers several times to Santi Romano in his writings) probably knew

  of Romano’s attempt to ground the state of exception in necessity as the originary source

  of law. His theory of sovereignty as the decision on the exception grants the Notstand a properly fundamental rank, one that is certainly comparable to the rank given it by

  Romano, who made it the originary figure of the juridical order. Furthermore, he shares

  with Romano the idea that the juridical order [ il diritto] is not exhausted in the law [ la legge] (it is not by chance that he cites Romano precisely in the context of his critique of the liberal Rechtsstaat); but while the Italian jurist wholly equates the state with law, and therefore denies all juridical relevance of the concept of constituent power, Schmitt

  sees the state of exception as precisely the moment in which state and law reveal their

  irreducible difference (in the state of exception “the state continues to exist, while law recedes” [Schmitt 1922, 13/12]), and thus he can ground the extreme figure of the state of exception—sovereign dictatorship—in the pouvoir constituant.

  1.11. According to some writers, in the state of necessity “the judge elabo-

  rates a positive law of crisis, just as, in normal times, he fills in juridical lacu-

  nae” (Mathiot 1956, 424). In this way the problem of the state of exception is

  put into relation with a particularly interesting problem in legal theory, that

  of lacunae in the juridical order [ il diritto]. At least as early as Article 4 of the Napoleonic Code
(“The judge who refuses to judge, on the pretence of silence,

  obscurity or insufficiency of the law, can be prosecuted on the charge of denial

  of justice”), in the majority of modern legal systems the judge is obligated to

  pronounce judgment even in the presence of a lacuna in the law [ la legge]. In

  analogy with the principle according to which the law [ la legge] may have lacu-

  nae, but the juridical order [ il diritto] admits none, the state of necessity is thus interpreted as a lacuna in public law, which the executive power is obligated to

  remedy. In this way, a principle that concerns the judiciary power is extended

  to the executive power.

  But in what does the lacuna in question actually consist? Is there truly

  something like a lacuna in the strict sense? Here, the lacuna does not concern a

  deficiency in the text of the legislation that must be completed by the judge; it

  concerns, rather, a suspension of the order that is in force in order to guarantee its existence. Far from being a response to a normative lacuna, the state of exception appears as the opening of a fictitious lacuna in the order for the purpose

  of safeguarding the existence of the norm and its applicability to the normal

  situation. The lacuna is not within the law [ la legge], but concerns its relation

  192

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  to reality, the very possibility of its application. It is as if the juridical order [ il diritto] contained an essential fracture between the position of the norm and its

  application, which, in extreme situations, can be filled only by means of the state

  of exception, that is, by creating a zone in which application is suspended, but

  the law [ la legge], as such, remains in force.

  2

  Force-of-Law

  2.1. The most rigorous attempt to construct a theory of the state of ex-

  ception was made by Carl Schmitt, essentially in the books Dicta-

  torship and, one year later, Political Theology. Because these two books from the beginning of the 1920s describe—with a, so to speak, interested prophesy—a

  paradigm (a “form of government” [Schmitt 1921, 151]) that has not only re-

  mained current but has today reached its full development, it is necessary at

  this point to present the fundamental theses of Schmitt’s theory of the state of

 

‹ Prev