Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 38

by Giorgio Agamben


  that makes law), when it is not reduced to merely the power to negotiate with

  the law. The only truly political action, however, is that which severs the nexus

  between violence and law. And only beginning from the space thus opened will

  it be possible to pose the question of a possible use of law after the deactivation

  of the device that, in the state of exception, tied it to life. We will then have be-

  fore us a “pure” law, in the sense in which Benjamin speaks of a “pure” language

  and a “pure” violence. To a word that does not bind, that neither commands

  nor prohibits anything, but says only itself, would correspond an action as pure

  means, which shows only itself, without any relation to an end. And, between

  the two, not a lost original state, but only the use and human praxis that the

  powers of law and myth had sought to capture in the state of exception.

  Bibliography

  Arangio-Ruiz, Gaetano. 1913. Istituzioni di diritto costituzionale italiano. Reprint, Milan: Bocca, 1972.

  Arendt, Hannah. 1961. Between Past and Future. New York: Viking.

  Balladore-Pallieri, Giorgio. 1970. Diritto costituzionale. Milan: Giuffrè.

  Bengel, Johann Albrecht. 1734. Vorrede zur Handausgabe des griechischen N. T.

  Benjamin, Walter. 1921. Zur Kritik der Gewalt. In Tiedemann and Schweppenhäuser, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 2, pt. 1. Translated by Edmund Jephcott as Critique of violence. In Selected Writings, vol. 1, 1913–1926, ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press, 1996.

  ———. 1928. Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels. In Tiedemann and Schweppenhäuser, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 1, pt. 1. Translated by John Osborne as The Origin of German Tragic Drama. London: Verso, 1998.

  ———. 1931. Karl Kraus. In Tiedemann and Schweppenhäuser, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 2, pt. 1.

  Translated by Edmund Jephcott as Karl Kraus. In Selected Writings, vol. 2, 1927–1934, ed. Michael W. Jennings, Howard Eiland, and Gary Smith. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,

  Belknap Press, 1999.

  ———. 1934. Franz Kafka. In Tiedemann and Schweppenhäuser, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 2, pt. 2. Translated by Harry Zohn as Franz Kafka. In Selected Writings, vol. 2, ed. Michael W.

  Jennings, Howard Eiland, and Gary Smith. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Belknap

  Press, 1999.

  ———. 1942. Über den Begriff der Geschichte. In Tiedemann and Schweppenhäuser, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 1, pt. 2. Translated by Harry Zohn as On the concept of history. In Selected Writings, vol. 4, 1938–1940, ed. Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press, 2003.

  ———. 1966. Breife. 2 vols. Ed. Gershom Scholem and Theodor W. Adorno. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Translated by Manfred R. Jacobson and Evelyn M. Jacobson as The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin, ed. Gershom Scholem and Theodor W. Adorno. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.

  ———. 1972–89. Gesammelte Schriften. 7 vols. Ed. Rolf Tiedemann and Hermann Schweppenhäuser. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

  ———. 1992. Notizen zu einer Arbeit über die Kategorie der Gerechtigkeit. Frankfurter Adorno Blätter 4.

  Benveniste, Émile. 1969. Le Vocabulaire des institutions indo-européennes. 2 vols. Paris: Minuit.

  Translated by Elizabeth Palmer as Indo-European Language and Society. Coral Gables, FL: University of Miami Press, 1973.

  Biscardi, Arnaldo. 1987. Autoritas patrum: Problemi di storia del diritto pubblico romano. Naples: Jovene.

  243

  244

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  Bredekamp, Horst. 1998. Von W. Benjamin zu C. Schmitt. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 46.

  Delatte, Armand. 1922. Essai sur la politique pythagoricienne. Paris: Champion.

  Delatte, Louis. 1942. Les traités de la royauté d’Ecphante, Diotogène et Sthénidas. Paris: Droz.

  De Martino, Francesco. 1973. Storia della costituzione romana. Naples: Jovene.

  Derrida, Jacques. 1994. Force de loi. Paris: Galilée. Translated by Mary Quaintance as Force of law: The “mystical foundation of authority.” Cardozo Law Review 11, nos. 5–6 (1990).

  Drobische, Klaus, and Günther Wieland. 1993. System der NS-Konzentrationslager 1933–1939. Berlin: Akademie.

  Duguit, Léon. 1930. Traité de droit constitutionnel. Vol. 3. Paris: de Boccard.

  Durkheim, Émile. 1897. Le Suicide. Étude de sociologie. Paris: Alcan. Translated by John A. Spauld-ing and George Simpson as Suicide: A Study in Sociology. New York: Free Press, 1951.

  Ehrenberg, Victor. 1924. Monumentum Antiochenum. Klio 19.

  Fontana, Alessandro. 1999. Du droit de résistance au devoir d’insurrection. In Le droit de résistance,

  ed. Jean-Claude Zancarini. Paris: ENS.

  Fraschetti, Augusto. 1990. Roma e il principe. Rome-Bari: Laterza.

  Fresa, Carlo. 1981. Provvisorietà con forza di legge e gestione degli stati di crisi. Padua: CEDAM.

  Friedrich, Carl J. [1941] 1950. Constitutional Government and Democracy. 2nd. ed. Boston: Ginn.

  Fueyo, Jesus. 1968. Die Idee des “Auctoritas”: Genesis und Entwicklung. In Epirrrhosis. Festgabe für Carl Schmitt, ed. Hans Barion. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

  Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1960. Wahrheit und Methode. Tübingen: Mohr. Translated by Joel Wein-sheimer and Donald Marshall as Truth and Method. 2d rev. ed. New York: Crossroads, 1989.

  Hatschek, Julius. 1923. Deutsches und Preussisches Staatsrecht. Vol. 2. Berlin: Stilke.

  Heinze, Richard. 1925. Auctoritas. Hermes 60.

  Kohler, Josef. 1915. Not kennt kein Gebot. Berlin-Leipzig: Rothschild.

  Magdelain, André. 1947. Auctoritas principis. Paris: Belles Letters.

  ———. 1990. Ius Imperium Auctoritas. Études de droit romain. Rome: École française de Rome.

  Mathiot, André. 1956. La théorie des circonstances exceptionelles. In Mélanges Mestre. Paris: n.p.

  Meuli, Karl. 1975. Gesammelte Schriften. 2 vols. Basel-Stuttgart: Schwabe.

  Middell, Emil. 1887. De iustitio deque aliis quibusdam iuris publici romani notionibus. Minden, Germany: Bruns.

  Mommsen, Theodor. 1969. Römisches Staatsrecht. 3 vols. Reprint, Graz: Akademische Druck. Orig.

  pub. 1871.

  Nissen, Adolph. 1877. Das Iustitium. Eine Studie aus der römischen Rechtsgeschichte. Leipzig: Gebhardt.

  Noailles, Pierre. 1948. Fas et Ius. Études de droit romain. Paris: Belles Lettres.

  Plaumann, Gerhard. 1913. Das sogennante Senatus consultum ultimum, die Quasidiktatur der

  späteren römischen Republik. Klio 13.

  Quadri, Giovanni. 1979. La forza di legge. Milan: Giuffrè.

  Reinach, Theodor. 1885. De l’etat de siège. Étude historique et juridique. Paris: Pichon.

  Romano, Santi. 1909. Sui decreti-legge e lo stato di assedio in occasione dei terremoti di Messina e Reggio Calabria. In Scritti minori. Vol. 1. Reprint, Milan: Giuffrè, 1990.

  ———. 1983. Frammenti di un dizionario giuridico. Milan: Giuffrè.

  Roosevelt, Franklin D. 1938. The Public Papers and Addresses. Vol. 2. New York: Random House.

  Rossiter, Clinton L. 1948. Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies. New York: Harcourt Brace.

  Saint-Bonnet, François. 2001. L’état d’exception. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

  Schmitt, Carl. 1921. Die Diktatur. Munich-Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

  ———. 1922. Politische Theologie. Munich-Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot; Translated by George Schwab as Political Theology. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985.

  ———. 1928. Verfassungslehre. Munich-Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  245

  ———. 1931. Der Hüter der Verfassung. Tübingen: Mohr.

  ———. 1995. Staat, Großraum, Nomos. B
erlin: Duncker & Humblot.

  Schnur, Roman. 1983. Revolution und Weltbürgerkrieg. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

  Schütz, Anton. 1995. L’immaculée conception de l’interprète et l’émergence du système juridique: À propos de fiction et construction en droit. Droits 21.

  Seston, William. 1962. Les chevaliers romains et le iustitium de Germanicus. In Scripta varia. Reprint, Rome: École française de Rome, 1980.

  Smend, Rudolph. 1956. Integrationslehre. In Handwörterbuch der Sozialwissenschaften. Vol. 5.

  Stuttgart: Fischer; Tübingen: Mohr; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

  Taubes, Jacob. 1987. Ad Carl Schmitt. Gegenstrebige Fügung. Berlin: Merve.

  Tingsten, Herbert. 1934. Les pleins pouvoirs. L’expansion des pouvoirs gouvernementaux pendant et après la grande guerre. Paris: Stock.

  Versnel, H. S. 1980. Destruction, devotio, and despair in a situation of anomy: The mourning for Germanicus in triple perspective. In Perennitas. Studi in onore di Angelo Brelich. Rome: Edizioni dell’Ateneo.

  Viesel, Hansjörg. 1988. Jawohl, der Schmitt. Zehn Briefe aus Plettenberg. Berlin: Support.

  Wagenvoort, H. 1947. Roman Dynamism. Oxford: Blackwell.

  Watkins, Frederick M. 1940. The Problem of Constitutional Dictatorship. Public Policy 1.

  Weber, Samuel. 1992. Taking exception to decision: W. Benjamin and C. Schmitt. In Walter Benjamin, ed. Uwe Steiner. Bern: Lang.

  Wenger, Leopold. 1939. Römisches Recht in Amerika. In Studi di storia e diritto in onore di Enrico Besta. Vol. 1. Milan: Giuffrè.

  HOMO SACER II, 2

  STASIS

  Civil War as a

  Political Paradigm

  TRANSLATED BY NICHOLAS HERON

  Contents

  Foreword

  251

  1. Stasis

  253

  2. Leviathan and Behemoth

  265

  Bibliography

  291

  This page intentionally left blank

  Foreword

  The two texts published here reproduce, with slight variations and additions,

  two seminars on civil war given at Princeton University in October 2001. It is up

  to readers to determine to what extent the theses advanced here—which iden-

  tify the fundamental threshold of politicisation in the West in civil war and the

  constitutive element of the modern State in ‘ademia’ (that is, in the absence of a

  people)—still apply, or whether, to the contrary, the passage into the dimension

  of global civil war has altered their meaning in an essential manner.

  251

  This page intentionally left blank

  1

  Stasis

  1.It is generally acknowledged that a theory of civil war is completely lacking

  today, yet this absence does not seem to concern jurists and political sci-

  entists too much. Roman Schnur, who formulated this diagnosis as early as the

  1980s, nonetheless added that the dis regard of civil war went hand in hand with

  the advance of global civil war (Schnur 1983, 121, 156). At thirty years’ distance,

  this observation has lost none of its topicality: while the very possibility of distin-

  guishing a war between States and an internecine war appears today to have dis-

  appeared, specialists continue to carefully avoid any hint at a theory of civil war.

  It is true that in recent years, owing to the upsurge of wars impossible to define

  as international, publications concerning so-called ‘internal wars’ have multiplied

  (above all, in the United States); even in these instances, however, the analysis

  was geared not toward an interpretation of the phenomenon, but—in accordance

  with a practice ever more widespread—toward the conditions under which an

  international intervention becomes possible. The paradigm of consensus, which

  today dominates both political action and theory, seems incompatible with the se-

  rious investigation of a phenomenon that is at least as old as Western democracy.

  א There exists, today, both a ‘polemology’, a theory of war, and an ‘irenology’, a

  theory of peace, but there is no ‘stasiology’, no theory of civil war. We have already mentioned how, according to Schnur, this absence could be related to the advance of global

  civil war. The concept of ‘global civil war’ was introduced contemporaneously in 1963

  in Hannah Arendt’s book On Revolution (in which the Second World War was defined

  as ‘a kind of civil war raging all over the earth’ [Arendt 1963, 8]) and in Carl Schmitt’s Theorie des Partisanen (Schmitt 2007), a book dedicated to the figure that marks the end of the conception of war of the Jus publicum Europaeum, which was grounded on the

  possibility of clearly distinguishing between war and peace, soldiers and civilians, enemies and criminals. Whatever date one wishes to trace this end back to, it is certain that today the state of war in the traditional sense has virtually disappeared. Even the Gulf War, the last conflict that still had the appearance of a war between States, was fought without the warring States declaring the state of war (which for some States, such as Italy, would have been unconstitutional). The generalisation of a model of war which cannot be defined as

  253

  254

  HOMO SACER II, 2

  an international conflict, yet which lacks the traditional features of civil war, has led some scholars to speak of ‘uncivil wars’, which, unlike civil wars, appear to be directed not toward the control and transformation of the political system, but toward the maximisation

  of disorder (Snow 1996). The attention which scholars dedicated to these wars in the 1990s ultimately could not lead to a theory of civil war, but only to a doctrine of management,

  that is, of the administration, manipulation and internationalisation of internal conflicts.

  2. One possible reason for the lack of interest in civil war was the increasing

  popularity of the concept of revolution (at least, up until the end of the 1960s),

  which was often substituted for civil war, yet without ever coinciding with it. It was

  Hannah Arendt who, in her book On Revolution, unreservedly formulated the the-

  sis of the heterogeneity between the two phenomena. ‘[R]evolutions’, she writes,

  are the only political events which confront us directly and inevitably with the

  problem of beginning [ . . . ] Modern revolutions have little in common with

  the mutatio rerum of Roman history or the stasis, the civil strife which disturbed the Greek polis. We cannot equate them with Plato’s metabolai, the quasi- natural

  transformation of one form of government into another, or with Polybius’s po-

  liteiōn anakyklōsis, the appointed recurring cycle into which human affairs are

  bound by reason of their always being driven to extremes. Antiquity was well

  acquainted with political change and the violence that went with change, but

  neither of them appeared to it to bring about something new. (Arendt 1963, 13–14)

  Although it is likely that the difference between the two concepts is in fact purely

  nominal, it is certain that the concentration of attention on the concept of revo-

  lution (which for some reason seemed more respectable than that of stasis, even

  to a scholar as unprejudiced as Arendt), has contributed to the marginal isation

  of studies on civil war.

  3. A theory of civil war is not among the possible objectives of this text. In-

  stead, I will restrict myself to examining the topic as it appears within Western

  political thought at two moments in its history: in the testimonies of the philos-

  ophers and historians of Ancient Greece and in the thought of Thomas Hobbes. />
  The two examples have not been selected by chance: I would like to suggest that

  they represent the two faces, so to speak, of a single political paradigm, which

  manifests itself, on the one hand, through the assertion of the necessity of civil war,

  and on the other, through the assertion of the necessity of its exclusion. That the

  paradigm is, in truth, single, means that the two opposed necessities maintain a se-

  cret solidarity between them. And it is this secret solidarity that I will seek to grasp.

  An analysis of the problem of civil war (or stasis) in classical Greece can only

  begin with the studies of Nicole Loraux, who dedicated a series of articles and es-

  STASIS 255

  says to this theme, which were collected in 1997 in the volume La Cité divisée—

  the volume to which she used to refer as mon livre par excellence. As in the life of artists, so too in the life of scholars there are mysteries. Thus I was never able to

  successfully explain to myself why Loraux never included in the volume an essay

  written in 1986 for a lecture in Rome entitled ‘La guerre dans la famille’, which

  is perhaps the most important of all the studies she dedicated to the problem

  of stasis. The circumstance is all the more inexplicable given that she decided to publish the essay in an issue of the journal Clio dedicated to guerres civiles in the same year as the book, almost as if she were aware—but this would be a truly singular motivation—that the thesis defended in the essay went decidedly further

  in terms of originality and radicality than the already acute thesis advanced in

  the book. I will attempt, in any case, to summarise the essay’s findings in order

  then to attempt to locate what Feuerbach called the Entwicklungsfähigkeit, the

  ‘capacity for development’ that they contain.

  4. Other French scholars—allow me to mention at least two classics, Gustave

  Glotz and Fustel de Coulanges, and in their wake, Jean-Pierre Vernant—had

  underscored the importance of stasis in the Greek polis prior to Nicole Loraux.

  The novelty of Loraux’s approach is that she immediately situates the problem

 

‹ Prev