The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Home > Other > The Omnibus Homo Sacer > Page 139
The Omnibus Homo Sacer Page 139

by Giorgio Agamben


  fection of a common life in all and for all ( unianimes in domo cum iocunditate

  habitare, “live harmoniously in a house pleasantly,” as an ancient rule has it):

  Par ceste liberté entrèrent en louable émulation de faire tous ce que à un seul

  voyoient plaire. Si quelqu’un ou quelcune disoit : “beuvons,” tous beuvoient;

  si disoit: “jouons,” tous jouoient; si disoit: “Allons à l’esbat ès champs,” tous y

  alloient [By this freedom they were all moved by laudable emulation to do what

  they saw a single one liked. If some man or woman said: “Let’s drink,” they all

  drank; if one said: “Let’s go play in the fields,” they all went]. (Rabelais, pp. 61/126)

  The abbreviated formulation of the rule is not, however, an invention of Rabe-

  lais, but goes back to the author of one of the first monastic rules, and still fur-

  896

  HOMO SACER IV, 1

  ther, to Augustine, who, in his commentary on the First Epistle of John (7.4.8),

  had summarized the precept of the Christian life in the genuinely Gargantuan

  stipulation: dilige et quod vis fac, “love and do what you wish.” Moreover, it

  corresponds precisely with the way of life of those monks who were, accord-

  ing to a tradition inaugurated by Cassian, pejoratively named “Sarabaites” and

  whose sole rule was caprice and desire ( pro lege eis est desideriorum voluntas). The Rabelaisian parody, though comical in appearance, is thus so serious that one

  can compare the episode of Thélème to the Franciscan foundation of a new type

  of order (Gilson, pp. 265–66): the common life, by identifying itself with the

  rule without remainder, abolishes and cancels it.

  1.3. In 1785, in his cell in the prison of the Bastille, Donatien Alphonse de

  Sade, filling a roll of paper twelve meters long with a minute calligraphy in

  only twenty days, wrote what many consider his masterpiece: Les 120 journées de

  Sodome ( The 120 Days of Sodom). The narrative frame is well known: on November 1 of an unspecified year at the end of the reign of Louis XIV, four powerful

  and rich libertines—the duke of Blangis, his brother the bishop, the president of

  Curval, and the financier Durcet—lock themselves away with forty-two victims

  in the castle of Silling in order to celebrate an orgy that would be without limits

  and yet perfectly and obsessively regulated. Here as well, the model is unequiv-

  ocally the monastic rule. Yet while in Rabelais, the paradigm is evoked directly

  (Thélème is an abbey) in order to be precisely negated and reversed (no clocks,

  no divisions of time, no compulsory behavior), at Silling, which is a castle and

  not an abbey, the time is articulated according to a meticulous ritualism that

  recalls the unfailing ordo of the monastic Office. Immediately after having been

  locked up (indeed walled up) in the castle, the four friends write and promulgate

  the règlements (“statutes”) that must govern their new common life. Not only

  is every moment of the “cenoby” fixed beforehand as in the monastery—the

  sanctioned rhythms of waking and sleeping, the rigidly programmed collective

  meals and “celebrations”—but even the boys’ and girls’ defecation is subject to

  meticulous regulation. On se lèvera tous les jours à dix heures du matin, demands

  the rule, parodying the scansion of the canonical hours, à onze heures les amis se

  rendront dans l’appartement des jeune filles . . . de deux à trois heures on servira les deux premières tables . . . en sortant du souper, on passera dans le salon d’assemblée (this is the synaxis or collecta or conventus fratrum of monastic terminology) pour la célébration (the same term that in the rules designates the Divine Offices) de ce qu’on appelle les orgies . . . (“the company shall rise every day at ten o’clock in the morning . . . at eleven o’clock, the friends shall repair to the quarters appointed

  THE HIGHEST POVERTY

  897

  for the little girls . . . from two to three the first two tables shall be served . . . the evening meal concluded, Messieurs shall pass into the salon for the celebration

  of what are to be called orgies”; pp. 41–43/241–46).

  Corresponding to the lectio of Holy Scripture (or of the text of the rule itself, as in the Regula magistri) that accompanied the meals and the daily occupations of the monks in monasteries, one finds here the ritual narration that the four historiennes, la Duclos, la Champville, la Martaine, and la Desgranges, make of their depraved

  life. Corresponding to the unlimited obedience-unto-death of the monks toward

  the abbot and their superiors ( oboedientia praeceptum est regulae usque ad mortem; Fructuosus, Regula monastica communis, chap. 5, p. 1115B), there is the absolute

  malleability of the victims to their masters, including extreme torture ( le moindre

  rire, ou le moindre manque d’attention ou respect ou de soumission dans les parties de débauche sera une des foutes les plus graves et les plus cruellement punies, “the least display of mirth, or the least evidence given of disrespect or lack of submission during

  the debauched activities shall be deemed one of the gravest of faults and shall be

  one of the most cruelly punished”; Sade pp. 44/248—in the same sense, monas-

  tic rules punish laughter during gatherings: Si vero aliquis depraehensus fuerit in

  risu . . . iubemus . . . omni flagello humilitatis coherceri, “if someone is caught laugh-ing or using scurrilous language . . . we order that he be chastised in the name of

  the Lord by every scourge of humility”; Vogüé 1, 1, pp. 202–4/31).

  Here also then, as at Thélème, the cenobitic ideal is parodically maintained

  (indeed, exaggerated). But while life in the abbey, making pleasure their rule,

  ended by abolishing it, at Silling the laws, in being identified at every point with

  life, can only destroy it. And while the monastic cenoby is conceived as lasting

  forever, here, after only five months, the four libertines, who have sacrificed the

  life of their objects of pleasure, hastily abandon the by now half-empty castle to

  return to Paris.

  1.4. It can appear surprising that the monastic ideal, born as an individual

  and solitary flight from the world, should have given origin to a model of total

  communitarian life. Nevertheless, as soon as Pachomius resolutely put aside

  the anchorite model, the term monasterium was equivalent in use to cenoby

  and the etymology that refers to the solitary life was dismissed to such a point

  that, in the Rule of the Master, monasteriale can be put forward as a translation of cenobite, and is glossed as militans sub regula vel abbate (“serving under a

  rule and an abbot”; Vogüé 2, 1, pp. 328/105). The rule of Basil was already on

  guard against the perils and egotism of the solitary life, which “the doctrine of

  charity does not permit” ( machomenon tōi tēs agapēs nomōi; Basil, Regulae fusius

  898

  HOMO SACER IV, 1

  tractatae, chap. 7). “It is impossible, indeed,” adds Basil, “to rejoice with him

  who receives an honor or to sympathize with him who suffers when, by reason

  of their being separated from one another, each person cannot, in all likelihood,

  be kept informed about the affairs of his neighbor” (ibid.). In the community of

  life ( en tēi tēs zōēs koinoniai), by contrast, the gift of each becomes common to

  those who live together with him ( sympoliteuomenōn) and the activity ( energeia) of the Holy Spirit in each is communicated to all the others (ibid.).
On the

  contrary, “he who lives alone . . . and has, perhaps, one gift renders it ineffectual

  through inoperativity ( dia tēs argias), since it lies buried within him ( katoryxas en eautōi)” (ibid.). If to advise against solitude, “the desolation of the desert and the terror of various monsters” are invoked at the beginning of the Rule of the

  Four Fathers, immediately afterward cenoby is founded, through scriptural ref-

  erences, in the joy and unanimity of the common life: volumus ergo fratres unianimes in domo cum iocunditate habitare (“therefore we desire that the brothers live harmoniously in a house pleasantly”; Vogüé 1, 1, pp. 182/17). The temporary

  suspension of common life ( excommunicatio; ibid., pp. 202/31) is the punish-

  ment par excellence, while leaving the monastery ( ex communione discedere) is

  equivalent, in the Regula Macharii, to choosing the infernal darkness ( in exteriores ibunt tenebras; Vogüé 1, 1, p. 386). Even in Theodore the Studite, cenoby is compared to paradise ( paradeisos tēs koinobiakēs zōēs), and leaving it is equivalent to the sin of Adam. “My son,” he admonishes a monk who wants to retire to

  the solitary life, “how has Satan the Evil One driven you out of the paradise of

  the common life, precisely like Adam who was seduced by the counsel of the

  serpent?” ( Epistle 1, p. 938).

  The theme of the common life had its paradigm in the Book of Acts, where

  the life of the apostles and of those who “devoted themselves to the apostles’ teach-

  ing” (Acts 2:42) is described in terms of “unanimity” and communism: “All who

  believed were together and had all things in common. . . . Day by day, as they

  persevered unanimously [ homothymadon] in the temple, they broke bread at home

  and ate their food with glad and sincere hearts” (Acts 2:44–46); “the whole group

  of those who believed were of one heart and one soul, and no one claimed private

  ownership of any possessions, but everything they owned was held in common”

  (Acts 4:32). It is in reference to this ideal that Augustine’s rule defines as the first

  goal of the monastic life “that you dwell in unity in the house, and that you have

  but one soul and one heart in God” ( primum propter quod in unum estis congregati,

  ut unanimes habitetis in domo et sit vobis anima una et cor unum in Deo; Augustine, Regula ad servos Dei, pp. 1377/17). And Jerome, who in 404 translated the rule of

  Pachomius from a Greek version, in an epistle refers explicitly to the Coptic term

  THE HIGHEST POVERTY

  899

  that, in the original, defined those who lived in community: coenobitae, quod illi

  “sauses” gentili lingua vocant, nos “in commune viventes” possumus appellare (“There are the cenobites, whom they call in their foreign tongue sauses; we may describe

  them as those who live in a community”; Epistle 22.34).

  At least up to the monastic renewal of the eleventh century, which with Ro-

  muald and Peter Damian saw the rekindling of the “tension between cenoby and

  hermitage” (Calati, p. 530), the primacy of the communitarian life over that of

  the hermit is a constant tendency. This culminates in the decision of the Council

  of Toledo (646), according to which, with a complete inversion of the historical

  process that had led from the anchorites to the monastery, no one can be admitted

  to the life of the hermit without having first passed through the cenobitic life. The

  cenobitic project is literally defined by the koinos bios, by the common life from which it draws its name, and without which it cannot be understood at all.

  א The idea of a “common life” seems to have an obvious political meaning. In the

  Politics, Aristotle defines the city as a “perfect community” ( koinonia teleios; 1252b29) and makes use of the term syzēn, “to live together,” to define the political nature of humans (“they desire to live together”; 1278b22). Yet he never speaks of a koinos bios.

  The polis is certainly born with view toward living ( tou zēn eneka; 1252b30), but its reason for existing is “living well” ( to eu zēn; ibid.). In the introduction to the Cenobitic Institutions, Cassian mentions as a goal of his book, alongside the “improvement of our behavior,” the exposition of the “perfect life” (Cassian 1, pp. 30/13). The monastery, like the polis, is a community that intends to realize the “perfection of the cenobial life”

  ( perfectionem . . . coenobialis vitae; ibid., pp. 182/82). In the Conlationes (or Conferences), Cassian therefore distinguishes the monastery from cenoby, because a monastery “is the

  name of the residence and does not imply more than the place where the monks live.

  ‘House of cenobites’ points to the character and the way of life of the profession. The residence of a simple monk can be called a monastery. But a place cannot be termed a house

  of cenobites unless one means a community of many people living together [ plurimorum

  cohabitantium . . . unita communio]” (Cassian 2, pp. 22/191). Cenoby does not name only a place, but first of all a form of life.

  1.5. It is starting from this tension between private and common, between

  hermitage and cenoby, that the curious threefold or fourfold articulation of genera

  monachorum (“types of monks”) seems to have been elaborated. These are found in

  Jerome ( Epistle 22); in Cassian ( Conferences, 18.4–8); in the long digression at the beginning of the Rule of the Master; in Benedict; and, in varied forms, in Isidore, John Climacus, Peter Damian, and Abelard, up through the texts of the canonists. The sense of this articulation—which, after having distinguished the cen-

  obites, in commune viventes (“living in common”), from the anchorites, qui soli

  900

  HOMO SACER IV, 1

  habitant per desertum (“who live alone in the wilderness”), opposes to these, as

  a “detestable and filthy” type, the Sarabaites (and, in a fourfold variant, which

  becomes canonical starting from the Rule of the Master and the Benedictine rule,

  the itinerants)—becomes clear, however, only if one understands that what is in

  question is not the opposition between solitude and common life, so much as

  the (so to speak) “political” opposition between order and disorder, governance

  and anarchy, stability and nomadism. Already in Jerome and Cassian the “third

  type” (qualified by teterrimum, deterrimum ac infidele) is defined by the fact that they live “together by twos or threes, not many more, and live according to their

  own will and independently [ suo arbitratu ac ditione]” (Jerome, Epistle 22.34) and

  “do not put up with being governed by the care and power of the abbot” ( abbatis

  cura atque imperio gubernari; Cassian 2, pp. 18/186). As the Rule of the Master confirms, “they have as their law the willfulness of their own desires” ( pro lege eis

  est desideriorum voluntas; Vogüé 2, 1, pp. 330/105), and they live without “having been tested . . . by any rule” ( nulla regula adprobati; cf. Pricoco, p. 134).

  In this “commonplace of monastic homiletics” (Penco, p. 506) that the four-

  fold division of the genera monachorum represents, what is at stake is thus the

  need to oppose at every point a well-governed community to anomia, a positive

  political paradigm to a negative one. In this sense, the classification is not, as has

  been suggested (Capelle, p. 309), entirely devoid of logic. Rather, as is evident

  in Isidore’s variant in which the types become six, every group has its double or

  its negative shadow, in such a way that they are organized precisely according to

  a binary opposition ( tria optima, reliqua vero tet
errima; Isidore, De ecclesiasticis officiis 2.16). In an illustration from the Rule of St. Benedict preserved in the public library of Mantua, the miniaturist opposes the two paradigms representationally: corresponding to the cenobites (exemplified by four monks who are

  praying together devoutly) and the anchorites (represented by an austere solitary

  monk) are the inferior images of the Sarabaites, who walk in opposite directions

  turning their backs to each other, and the itinerants, who gulp down food and

  drink without restraint. Once the anchoritic exception is left to one side, the

  problem of monasticism will always be more that of constructing and affirming

  itself as an ordered and well-governed community.

  1.6. Communal habitation is the necessary foundation of monasticism.

  Never theless, in the earliest rules, the term habitatio seems to indicate not so

  much a simple fact as, rather, a virtue and a spiritual condition. “The virtue that

  distinguishes the brothers is habitation and obedience,” proclaims a passage of

  the Rule of the Four Fathers (Pricoco, p. 10). In the same sense, the term habitare

  THE HIGHEST POVERTY

  901

  (frequentative of habeo) seems to designate not only a factual situation but a way of life. The Rule of the Master can thus establish that the clergy may also stay for a long time as guests ( hospites suscipiantur) in the monastery, but cannot “inhabit it” ( in monasterio habitare), that is, assume the monastic condition (Vogüé 2, 2,

  pp. 342–46).

  In the context of the monastic life, the term habitus—which originally signi-

  fied “a way of being or acting” and, among the Stoics, became synonymous with

  virtue ( habitum appellamus animi aut corporis constantem et absolutam aliqua in

  re perfectionem, “By habit we mean a stable and absolute constitution of mind or body”; Cicero, De inventione 1.25.36)—seems more and more to designate the

  way of dressing. It is significant that, when this concrete meaning of the word

  begins to be affirmed in the post-Augustan age, it is not always easy to distinguish

  it from the more general sense, all the more so in that habitus was closely associated with dress, which was in some way a necessary part of the “way to conduct

  oneself.” When we read in Cicero virginali habitu atque vestitu (“in the shape and attire of maidens”; Verrine Orations, 2.4.5), the distinction and, at the same time, the proximity between the two concepts are perfectly clear. Yet it is not as certain

 

‹ Prev