The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Home > Other > The Omnibus Homo Sacer > Page 184
The Omnibus Homo Sacer Page 184

by Giorgio Agamben

called ‘harmony’; and the union of the two is called ‘a performance by a chorus’”

  ( Laws, 665a). In this sense, the term is also used, particularly by lyric poets, to define the proper form and character of each individual: “know what rhythm

  governs human beings” ( gignoske d’ oios rhythmos anthropous echei; Archilocus),

  “do not praise a man before knowing his sentiment, his rhythm, and his charac-

  ter” ( orgen kai rithmon kai tropon; Theognides).

  Mode expresses this “rhythmic” and not “schematic” nature of being: being

  is a flux, and substance “modulates” itself and beats out its rhythm—it does not

  fix and schematize itself—in the modes. Not the individuating of itself but the

  beating out of the rhythm of substance defines the ontology that we are here

  seeking to define.

  Hence the peculiar temporality of mode, on which it is appropriate to reflect.

  The adverb modo means in Latin “a short time ago, just now, recently.” This in-

  dicates, in the “now,” a small temporal gap, which is not a chronological past so

  much as a non-coincidence of the moment with itself, which obligates it to stop

  and take itself up again. We could say, then, that the temporal form of mode is

  neither the past nor the present nor even less the future: it is the mode rn, on condition of restoring to this discredited word its etymological meaning from modo and

  modus (present to some extent even in the related Italian term moda, “fashion”).

  Since its first appearance in a letter of Gelasius I, which distinguishes the

  admonitiones modernae from antiquae regulae, the term modernus always implies a tension with regard to the past, as if the present could grasp and define itself

  1184

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  only in a gap with respect to itself. That is to say, the modern is intimately histor-

  ical and archaic, because it has need of the ancient to refer and, at the same time,

  to oppose to itself. Analogously, the temporality of mode is not actuality: it is,

  in present existence or in the actual, the gap that impedes their coinciding with

  themselves—the operative time in which the flux of being pulsates and stops,

  takes itself up and repeats itself and, in this way, modulates itself in a rhythm.

  Insofar as it demands to preserve itself in its being, substance disseminates itself

  in the modes and can thus take form in time. The “being that it was” and its

  resumption in thought, existence and essence, substance and modes, past and

  present are only the moments or the figures of this rhythm, of this music of

  being: ductus sub aliqua figura servatus.

  The person who is properly modern, in this sense, is not the one who op-

  poses the ancient so much as the one who understands that only when some-

  thing “has done its time” does it become truly urgent and actual. Only at this

  point can the rhythm of being be known and grasped as such. Today we are

  in this extreme epochal situation, and yet it seems that human beings do not

  manage to become aware of it and continue to be cut and divided between the

  old and the new, the past and the present. Art, philosophy, religion, politics have

  done their time, but only now do they appear to us in their fullness, only now

  can we draw from them a new life.

  א Developing the Neoplatonic idea of emanation, Avicenna conceives of being as a

  flux ( fayd ). The first principle acts neither by will nor by choice but simply exists and, from its existence, accomplishes and “flows into” the world. The fact that in the image

  of flux what is in question is a tendential neutralization of the concept of cause, in the sense of the reciprocal immanence between causing and caused, is implicit in the way in

  which Albert the Great takes up this idea: “Only that can flow in which flowing and that

  from which it flows are of the same form, as the river has the same form as the source

  from which it flows. . . .” (Lizzini, pp. 10–11). If one maintains the image of flux, then the most adequate form for thinking mode is that of conceiving it as a vortex in the flux

  of being. It has no substance other than that of the one being, but, with respect to the

  latter, it has a figure, a manner, and a movement that belong to it on its own. The modes

  are eddies in the boundless field of the substance that, by sinking and whirling into itself, disseminates and expresses itself in singularities.

  3.27. In order to correctly think the concept of mode, it is necessary to con-

  ceive it as a threshold of indifference between ontology and ethics. Just as in

  ethics character ( ethos) expresses the irreducible being-thus of an individual, so also in ontology, what is in question in mode is the “as” of being, the mode in

  which substance is its modifications. Being demands its modifications; they are

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1185

  its ethos: its being irreparably consigned to its own modes of being, to its “thus.”

  The mode in which something is, the being-thus of an entity is a category that

  belongs irreducibly to ontology and to ethics (which can also be expressed by

  saying that in mode they coincide). In this sense, the claim of a modal ontology

  should be terminologically integrated in the sense that, understood correctly, a

  modal ontology is no longer an ontology but an ethics (on the condition that we

  add that the ethics of modes is no longer an ethics but an ontology).

  Only at this point does a confrontation with Heideggerian ontology become

  possible. If the difference between essence and existence becomes a crucial prob-

  lem in Being and Time, in the sense that “the essence of Dasein lies in its exis-

  tence” (Heidegger 1, p. 42/67), the characteristics of this entity are not, however,

  to be conceived according to the model of traditional ontology as “properties”

  or accidents of an essence but “always and only as possible modes [ Weisen] of

  being.” Therefore, “when we designate this entity with the term ‘Dasein,’ we are

  expressing not its ‘what’ (as if it were a table, house, or tree) but its being” (ibid.).

  Heidegger emphatically emphasizes that the concept of existence that is in

  question here is not that of traditional ontology, which is founded on the clear

  distinction of essence and existence. The reference to the “modes of being” and

  the specification “every being-thus [ Sosein] of this entity is primarily being” (ibid.) should have made us understand that the ontology of Dasein, even if Heidegger

  does not pronounce it explicitly, is a radical form of modal ontology, even if not a

  clearly thematized one. The lectures of the summer semester of 1928 at Marburg,

  which contain such precious comments on passages from Being and Time, suggest

  this unreservedly: Dasein “designates the being for which its own proper mode

  of being [ seine eigene Weise zu sein] in a definite sense is not indifferent” (Heidegger 8, p. 171/136). Dasein is not an essence that, as in Scotus and the scholastics, is

  indifferent to its modifications: it is always and only its mode of being, which is

  to say, it is always radically mode (paraphrasing the Scholastic motto according to

  which “horseness is only horseness,” Dasein is mode and nothing more). Dasein

  is the mode of a being that coincides completely with mode.

  It is not possible here to specify the reasons that drove Heidegger not to

  make the modal character of his ontol
ogy explicit. It is probable that it was pre-

  cisely his prolonged adherence to the Aristotelian apparatus that did not allow

  him to understand that the ontological difference must be completely resolved

  into the being-modes relation. In any case, it is a matter of the same difficulty

  that constrained him to avoid up to the end a confrontation with the philosophy

  of Spinoza.

  Intermezzo II

  1.In the latter half of the thirties, while he was writing and compiling

  the remarks that come together in the notebook Beiträge zur Philosophy

  ( Contributions to Philosophy, inappropriately designated by the editors of the

  Gesamtausgabe as one of his Hauptwerke), Heidegger insistently returns to his concept of Dasein (which he now always writes as Da-sein), and in revisiting

  the existential analytic that he had sketched in Being and Time, he newly de-

  fines the relationship between the human being and what that term was to

  designate. In Being and Time, he suggests, the concept was still thought in too

  anthropological a way, which could allow for equivocations. The term does

  not mean the human being or a characteristic or structural property of the

  human being (precisely this is what still seems to him to lend itself to “easy

  misunderstandings” in Being and Time): it is, rather, something that one must

  assume and “take up” ( übernehmen; Heidegger 9, p. 297/235) and in which one

  must “be steadfast” (ibid., p. 319/252–253). As such, it indicates “a possibility of

  the human being to come,” the “ground of a determinate future being of the

  human being, not the ground of ‘the’ human being as such” (p. 300/237), that

  is, of the human being who “endures being the Da, the ‘there’” and conceives

  himself as the “steward of the truth of being” (p. 297/235). Dasein does not

  mean “presence in some place or another” or simply “turning up” ( Vorkommen)

  but rather “steadfast enduring [ inständige Ertragsamkeit] as grounding the

  ‘there’” (p. 298/235), “persistence [ Beständnis; bestehen means “to tenaciously overcome a test”] in the truth of Being [ Seyns]” (p. 311/246). In the 1929–30

  course Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, Dasein is defined still more figu-

  ratively as a “burden” that the human being must take upon himself.

  Let us reflect on the terminology with which Heidegger seeks to define Da-sein:

  “taking up” ( übernehmen), “possibility,” “steadfast endurance,” “persistence.” That is to say, we are dealing not with something that is always already present in the

  human being and which the human can have at its disposal but instead with a task

  1186

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1187

  or a test that the human being must take up and endure—and it is an arduous

  task, if it is true that, as the title for §5 reads, it remains reserved for the “few and

  rare” ( Für die Wenigen—Für die Seltenen).

  Da-sein here seems to be not a substance but something like an activity or

  a mode of existing that the human being must assume in order to approach the

  truth (his own and that of being)—something that he therefore can also possibly

  miss. But how can that in which the very truth of being is in question remain

  entrusted solely to the uncertainty and contingency of a “test” or a “task”?

  2. Here Heidegger is coming up against a difficulty that was already pres-

  ent in Being and Time. There the circular ontological constitution of Dasein,

  that is, of the entity for which being itself is at issue in its being, entails a “pri-

  ority” ( Vorrang; Heidegger 1, p. 13/34) and a “distinctiveness” ( Auszeichnung; p. 11/32) of Dasein, which in its very structure—insofar as it “has a relation of

  being with its being”—is “in itself ontological” (p. 13/34). In this sense, Da-

  sein is the “ontico-ontological condition for the possibility of any ontology”

  (p. 13/34). At the beginning of §4, the relation between Dasein and the human

  being had, however, been defined by Heidegger, at least in a hurried way, in

  these words: “As ways in which the human being behaves, sciences have the

  manner of being [ Seinsart] this entity—the human being itself—possesses.

  This entity we grasp terminologically [ fassen wir terminologisch] as ‘Dasein’”

  (p. 11/32).

  What is thematically confronted in the Beiträge zur Philosophie is precisely

  the problem of this “terminological grasp.” Is it the human being who, in as-

  suming its Da, is the “projector of Being” ( Entwerfer des Seins; p. 299/236), who opens its clearing and safeguards its truth, or is it, rather, Being that “uses”

  (p. 318/251) the human being to this end? That is to say, is Being, the open, a

  performance of the human being as Dasein, or is Dasein (and the human being

  it entails) a performance of Being?

  3. In the Beiträge, these questions never stop resonating, and it can be said

  that Ereignis (understood etymologically as “appropriation”) is the apparatus

  through which Heidegger seeks to resolve the aporia that is expressed in them.

  This is clearly confirmed in the explanation of the title that opens the book:

  what is in question here is “to let oneself be appropriated in appropriation

  [ Er-eignis], which is equivalent to a transformation of the human being: from

  ‘rational animal’ ( animal rationale) to Da-sein. The fitting rubric is therefore

  Of [ von] Ereignis” (Heidegger 9, p. 3/5).

  1188

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  The paragraphs of section V, which bear the title “The Grounding,” return

  constantly to the problem of the relation between Dasein and the human:

  Who is the human being? The one used [ gebraucht] by Being for the sake of

  withstanding the essence [ Wesung] of the truth of Being.

  As so used, however, humans “are” humans only inasmuch as they are

  grounded in Da-sein, i.e., inasmuch as they themselves, by creating, become the

  ones who ground Da- sein.

  Yet Being is also grasped here as appropriation [ Er-eignis]. Both belong to-

  gether: the grounding back [ Rückgrundung] into Da-sein and the truth of Being

  as appropriation-event [ Ereignis].

  We grasp nothing of the direction of the questioning that is opened up

  here if we casually base ourselves on arbitrary ideas of the human being and of

  “beings as such” instead of putting into question at one stroke both the “human

  being” and Being (not simply the being of the human being) and keeping them

  in question. (Ibid., p. 318/252)

  Ereignis is what allows one to think the co-belonging and reciprocal foundation

  of human being and Dasein and of Dasein and Being. If the relation of co-

  belonging between Being and Dasein (the Da, the “there” as opening of Being)

  is already in Being and Time and even more in the Beiträge in some way analyzed and defined, that of the human being and Dasein and the transformation of the

  living human being, of the animal rationale into Da-sein that is in question in

  it remain, by contrast, problematic to the end. Being is “grounded back” into

  Dasein, but whether Dasein in turn needs a foundation or a place (a Da) in the

  human being is left vague. In what way does Dasein entail the human being in

  itself, so that Being, in appropriating Dasein to it
self, can also appropriate to

  itself the human being? And what happens, in the event of appropriation, to the

  living human being as such?

  4. Benjamin once defined Heidegger’s style as “angular,” in the sense that

  it betrayed the philosopher’s fear of running up against a corner, that is, prob-

  lems that he had not been able to get to the bottom of. That Heidegger does

  not manage to get to the bottom of the co-belonging of the human being and

  Da-sein, that the problem of the living human being remains in some way un-

  resolved, is obvious in the obscurity and vagueness that characterize the style of

  the Beiträge every time Heidegger comes up against this theme. Paragraph 175

  is among those in which the question is precisely invoked. The question here is

  that of exceeding “the first reference to Da-sein as the grounding of the truth of

  Being” that in Being and Time had been achieved by means of asking about the

  human being, conceived as “the projector of Being [ der Entwerfer des Seins] and

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1189

  thus as detached from all ‘anthropology’” (p. 299/236). And yet what is equivocal

  here is that it seems that Dasein can be understood only with reference to the

  human being. Instead, when thought starting from the truth of Being, “Da-sein

  moves . . . away from the relation to the human being and reveals itself as the

  ‘between’ which is developed by Being itself so as to become the open domain

  for the beings that protrude into it, a domain in which beings are at the same

  time set back on themselves. The ‘there’ is appropriated and made to happen

  [ ereignet] by Being itself. The human being, as steward of the truth of Being,

  is subsequently appropriated and thus belongs to Being in a preeminent and

  unique way [ in einer ausgezeichneten einzigen Weise]” (ibid.). How this “preem-

  inent and unique” appropriation of the human being on the part of Being can

  happen is not in any way explained, unless it is with the word “subsequently,”

  which remains all the more problematic insofar as Dasein has just been moved

  away from any reference to the human being.

  At this point it is not surprising that the paragraph concludes with a sen-

  tence in which the angular stylistics are neutralized and leave the problem en-

 

‹ Prev