The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Home > Other > The Omnibus Homo Sacer > Page 190
The Omnibus Homo Sacer Page 190

by Giorgio Agamben


  living, but life itself, in all its forms (including animals and plants), is immedi-

  ately contemplation ( theoria).

  Indeed, Plotinus begins with a gesture of whose novelty he is perfectly aware,

  attributing contemplation to all living beings, including plants (which for Aris-

  totle were the “alogical” beings par excellence) and suddenly announces, appar-

  ently in the form of a joke, the thesis of a physis that generates and produces by means of contemplation:

  Suppose we said, playing at first before we set out to be serious, that all things

  aspire to contemplation, and direct their gaze to this end—not only rational but

  irrational living things, and the power of growth in plants, and the earth which

  brings them forth—and that all attain to it as far as possible for them in their

  natural state. . . . Now let us talk about the earth itself, and trees, and plants in

  general, and ask what their contemplation is, and how we can relate what the

  earth makes and produces to its activity of contemplation, and how nature, which

  people say has no power of forming images or reasoning, has contemplation in

  itself and makes what it makes by contemplation. (3, 8, 1)

  The first consequence of this “theoretical” or contemplative character of physis is a transformation of the very idea of natural life ( zoè), which ceases to be a sum

  of heterogeneous functions (psychic life, sensible life, vegetative life) and is de-

  fined from the very start with a strong accent on the unitary character of every

  vital phenomenon, as “neither vegetative nor sensitive nor psychic” but rather as

  “living contemplation.” The Stoics had elaborated the concept of “logical life”

  ( logikè zoè) and “logical animal” ( zoon logikon) to characterize properly human with respect to that of other living things. The novelty of this notion, with regard to the classical definition of the human being as an “animal that has logos”

  ( zoon logon echon) is that logos here is not simply added to the vital functions common to the other animals while leaving them unchanged but pervades the

  entire human physis, transforming it from top to bottom so that its impulses,

  its desires, its sensations, and its passions appear as intimately logical. Plotinus

  pushes this Stoic idea to the extreme and extends it to some extent to all living

  things and all forms of life without distinction. Now what is logical and theoret-

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1223

  ical is life itself, which is articulated, disseminated, and diversified according to

  the more or less manifest character ( ergastes, “luminous”) of contemplation that

  is proper to it. The intuition of this profound unity of life in its intimate logi-

  cal tension toward expression and thought is the most original legacy that the

  late-ancient world leaves as an inheritance to Christian theology and, by means

  of the latter, to modernity.

  Contemplation is a movement of nature toward the soul, and of the soul to

  thought, and contemplations become always more intimate and unified to the

  contemplators. . . . So this must be something where the two become truly one.

  But this is living contemplation [ theoria zosa], not an object of contemplation

  [ theorema] like that in something else. For that which is in something else is alive because of that other, not in its own right. If, then, an object of contemplation

  [ theorema] and thought [ noema] is to have life, it must be a life that is not vegetative [ phytikè] nor sensible [ aisthetikè], nor psychical. For the other lives are thoughts [ noesis], but one is a growth-thought, one a sense-thought, and one a

  soul-thought. How, then, are they thoughts? Because they are logoi, languages.

  And every life is a certain thought [ pasa zoè noesis tis], but one is dimmer than the other, just as life has degrees of clarity and strength. But this life is more luminous

  [ enargestera]; this is first life and first intellect in one. So the first life is thought, and the second life thought in the second degree, and the last life thought in

  the last degree. All life, then, belongs to this kind and is thought. But perhaps

  people may speak of different kinds of thought but say that some are thoughts,

  but others not thoughts at all, because they do not investigate at all what kind

  of thing life is. But we must bring out this point, at any rate, that again our

  discussion shows that all beings are contemplations. And if the truest life is the

  life of thought, then the truest thought lives and contemplation and the object

  of contemplation are a living and a life and the two together are one. (3, 8, 8)

  3.3. The counterpart of this dual unity of life and thought in all their mani-

  festations is a new ontological status of the living thing, which the treatise “On

  Happiness” thematizes obliquely, making use of categories that seem to come

  from the traditional vocabulary of political reflection. The central concept of

  this new ontology is that of form of life ( eidos zoes or tes zoes), whose peculiarity as a technical term in Plotinus’s lexicon has escaped the attention of scholars.

  Plotinus begins by asking whether, once “living well” ( eu zen, the same term that

  in Aristotle’s Politics defines the end of the polis) has been identified with being happy ( eudaimonein), one must then also render the other living beings aside

  from humans participants in it, for example, birds and plants (in his writings

  Plotinus betrays a striking predilection for plants, which by contrast generally

  function in Aristotle as negative paradigms with respect to the human). Those

  1224

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  who deny to irrational beings the capacity of living well end up, without realizing

  it, placing living well in something other than life (for example, in reason). For

  his part, Plotinus instead declares unreservedly that he situates happiness in life

  and therefore seeks to think a concept of life and of being in line with this radical

  thesis. Let us read the passage in question, which constitutes one of the supreme

  achievements of Plotinus’s genius, the ontological implications of which have

  perhaps not yet been fully grasped:

  Suppose we assume that happiness is to be found in life; then if we make life a

  term which applies to all living things in exactly the same sense, we allow that all

  of them are capable of happiness, and that those of them actually live well who

  possess one and the same thing, something which all living beings are naturally

  capable of acquiring; we do not on this assumption grant this potential solely

  to living beings endowed with reason, denying it to the irrational. Life is com-

  mon [ koinon] to both, which have in potential the same attitude with respect

  to happiness, if happiness is to be found in a kind of life. So I think that those

  who say that happiness is to be found in rational life [ en logikei zoei] and not

  in common life [ en koinei zoei] are unaware that they are really assuming that

  being happy is not a life at all. They would have to say that the rational potential

  on which happiness depends is a quality. But their starting point is rational life,

  and happiness depends on this, namely on another form of life [ perì allo eidos

  zoes]. I do not mean “another form” in the sense of a logical distinction, but

  in the sense in which we Platonists speak of one thing as prior and another as

  posterio
r. The term “life” is used in many ways, distinguished according to the

  rank of the things to which it is applied, first, second, and so on; and thus life

  and living is a homonymous term that is said in one sense of plants, in another

  of rational animals, and both differ according to their level of clarity or obscurity;

  so obviously the same applies to living well. (1, 4, 3)

  3.4. Plotinus’s new bio-ontology is articulated by means of a critical reinter-

  pretation of the Stoic concept of logical life. Plotinus thinks life, however, not

  as an undifferentiated substrate ( hypokeimenon) to which determinate qualities

  would come to be added (for example, rational or linguistic being) but as an

  indivisible whole, which he defines as eidos zoes, “form of life.” That this expression here has a terminological character emerges beyond any doubt from the

  specification that, in it, eidos does not indicate the specific difference of a common genus (for this reason it would be erroneous to translated it with “species”).

  The specification according to which the term eidos is not to be understood as

  species of a genus but according to the prior and posterior, refers, according to

  the definition that Aristotle gives in Metaphysics 1018b 9ff., only to the greater or lesser proximity to an archè (for this reason Plotinus had spoken of “primary”

  THE USE OF BODIES

  1225

  and “secondary life”). “Life” is not a synonym (in which there is an identity for

  the term and of the definition, which have a common referent) but a homonym,

  which in each form of life takes on a sense that is differentiated according to

  its being more or less manifest, more or less luminous. Pressed by the need for

  a new definition of life, Plotinus profoundly transforms Aristotelian ontology:

  yes, there is a unique substance, yet this is not a subject that remains behind or

  beneath its qualities but is always already homonymically shared in a plurality

  of forms of life, in which life is never separable from its form and, quite to the

  contrary, is always its mode of being, without for that reason ceasing to be one.

  3.5. “If then a human being can have the perfect life, then he will be able to

  be happy. If not, one would have to attribute happiness to the gods, if among

  them alone this kind of life is to be found. But since we maintain that this

  happiness is to be found among human beings we must consider how it is so.

  What I mean is this: it is obvious from what has been said elsewhere that the

  human being has perfect life by having not only sensibility, but reasoning and

  true thought. But there is no human being who does not possess it, in potential

  or in act, and when he has it in act, we will call him happy. But shall we say

  that he has this form of life [ eidos tes zoes], which is perfect, in him as a part of himself? The human being who has it in potential have it as a part, but the happy

  person is the one who already is happy in act and has passed over into being this

  (form of life) [ metabebeke pros to autò einai touto]” (1, 4, 4, 1–15).

  The happy life here appears as a life that does not possess its form as a part

  or a quality but is this form, has completely passed into it (this is the sense of metabaino). In this new and extreme dimension, the ancient opposition of bios

  and zoè definitively loses its sense. Plotinus can thus write at this point, with an intentionally paradoxical expression that takes up and twists one of the key concepts from Aristotle’s Politics: autarkes oun ho bios toi outos zoen echonti, “bios is autarchic insofar as it in some way has zoè” (ibid., 23). We have seen that Victor Goldschmidt demonstrated that autarkia in Aristotle’s Politics is not a juridical or economic or political concept in the strict sense but first of all biological. That

  polis is autarchic, which has reached the just numerical consistency of its population. Only if it has reached this limit can it pass from simple living to living well.

  It is this biological-political concept that Plotinus completely transforms, ren-

  dering it indiscernible from bios and form of life. The two terms bios and zoè, on the opposition of which Aristotelian politics were founded, now contract into

  one another in a peremptory gesture that, while irrevocably taking leave of clas-

  sical politics, points toward an unheard-of politicization of life as such (“bios is

  1226

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  autarchic insofar as it in some way has zoè”). The wager here is that there can be a bios, a mode of life, that is defined solely by means of its special and inseparable union with zoè and has no other content than the latter (and, reciprocally, that

  there is a zoè that is nothing other than its form, its bios). Precisely and solely to the bios and zoè thus transfigured do there belong the attributes of political life: happiness and autarchy, which in the classical tradition were instead founded on

  the separation of bios and zoè. One has a political bios who never has his zoè as a part, as something separable (that is, as bare life), but is his zoè, is completely form-of-life.

  4

  Life Is a Form Generated by Living

  4.1. One of the places through which the Plotinian concepts of life and

  form of life ( eidos zoes) were transmitted to Christian authors is the

  Adversus Arium of Marius Victorinus, a Roman rhetor and convert to Christian-

  ity who exercised a determinant influence on Augustine with his translation of

  the Enneads. Victorinus seeks to think the trinitarian paradigm, which is taking

  form in those years, through Neoplatonic categories, not only by developing

  from this perspective the doctrine of the three hypostases (being, life, thought)

  but also and above all by deepening the unity between being and life that we

  have seen to define Plotinian bio-ontology. Already Aristotle, in a passage of the

  De anima that was to have a long lineage, had affirmed, albeit cursorily, that

  “being for the living is to live.” Now it is a question, by completely translating

  the ontological vocabulary into a “bio-logical” vocabulary, of thinking the unity

  and consubstantiality—and at the same time, the distinction—between Father

  and Son as unity and articulation of “living” and “life” in God. Mobilizing to the

  point of excess the artifice and subtlety of his rhetorical art, Victorinus dedicates

  the entire fourth book of his treatise to this difficult theological problem:

  “He lives” and life [ vivit ac vita], are they one thing, or the same thing, or are they different things? One? But why the two terms? The same thing? But how

  so, since it is one thing to be actually, the other thing to be actuality. Are they

  therefore different? But how would they be different, since in that which lives

  there is life, and in that which is life, it is necessarily the case that it lives? In-

  deed, that which lives does not lack life, since then there would be life that does

  not live. Therefore they are different in one another, and consequently, in one

  another, whatever they are, they are two; and if, in some way, they are two, they

  are not however, two purely and simply, since indeed they are one in the other

  and that is the case with both of them. Are they therefore the same thing? But

  the same thing in two is other than itself. This identity is therefore at the same

  time alterity in each of the two. But if there is an identity, and each of the two

  is identical to itself, both are identical and one. Indeed, each one being wh
at the

  other is, neither of the two is double [ geminum]. Therefore, if each of the two, by 1227

  1228

  HOMO SACER IV, 2

  the very same thing that he is, is also the other, each one of the two will be one

  in himself. But since each one of the two is one in himself, it is the same one in

  the other. . . . Living and life are such that what living consists in is life and what

  life consists in is living: not that one is duplicated into the other, or that one is

  with the other—for that would be a union [ copulatio: for from this, even if the

  connection were inseparable, there is only a union, not a unity ( unitum est, non

  unum)]—no in fact they are such that in the very act that is living is to be life

  and in the same way, to be life is to live. . . . “He lives” and life are therefore one

  substance. (Victorinus, pp. 502–504/253–255)

  4.2. Nothing shows the new and decisive centrality that the concept of life

  acquires both in the speculations of dying paganism and in nascent Christian

  theology as much as the fact that the problem of the consubstantiality between

  Father and Son is thought in terms of a relation between pure living and the

  life that is co-originarily generated in it. In a passage that, as has been noted, is

  perhaps the densest of his entire work, the paradox of this bi-unity is resolved by

  Victorinus, with an unquestionable revival of the Plotinian concept of eidos zoes, in the idea of a “form of life” ( vitae forma, forma viventis) generated by the very act of living ( vivendo):

  Indeed, life is a habit of living [ vivendi habitus], and it is a kind of form or state generated by living [ quasi quaedam forma vel status vivendo progenitus], containing in itself living itself and that being which is life [ id esse quod vita est], so that both are one substance. For they are not truly one in the other, but they are one redoubled

  in its own simplicity [ unum suo simplici geminum], one, in itself because it is from itself [ ex se] and one which is from itself because the first simplicity has a certain work within itself. . . . For living is being; but being life is a certain mode, that is, the form of living produced by the very one for which it is form [ forma viventis confecta

  ipso illo cui forma est]. But the producer, living, never having a beginning—for that which lives from itself has no beginning since it lives always—it follows that life also

 

‹ Prev