Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes

Home > Other > Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes > Page 28
Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes Page 28

by Democracy in Dangerous Places (pdf)


  candle. In its place came the principle of national sovereignty: what-

  ever wrongs a government perpetrated on its own population, they

  did not have sufficient consequence upon the well-being of other

  countries to warrant intervention. At the time the concept was de-

  veloped in the seventeenth century, there were reasonable grounds

  for such a proposition: economies and societies were not highly inte-

  grated. Whether or not it was true at the time, it certainly is not true

  any longer. Nowadays a civil war generates externalities for neigh-

  bors that are too large and too adverse to be dismissed.

  I have tried to measure them through studies with Anke, Lisa

  Chauvet, and Alberto Behar. The approach we used was standard,

  although care has to be taken to distinguish those neighborhood ef-

  fects that have nothing to do with war from war itself. For example,

  a neighborhood might be affected in common by a drought, as in

  Southern Africa during the mid-1990s. We find, unsurprisingly,

  that the costs of a civil war to any particular neighboring country

  are considerably less than the costs to the country itself. Typically,

  a country might lose around 0.9 percentage points off its growth

  rate if one of its neighbors is at war. However, the typical civil war

  country has three or more neighbors, and, further, the economies

  of the neighboring countries are usually larger than that of the civil

  war country itself. This is because, as we have seen, being small and

  being poor are both risk factors.

  In our analysis we include only costs to immediate neighbors.

  This omits demonstrated adverse spillover effects across a wider

  area. Even with the restriction to immediate neighbors, the num-

  bers imply that the costs to the neighbors as a group are likely to

  be even larger than the costs to the country at war. So, reflecting

  the standard economic solution to the problem of how externalities

  should be internalized into the decision process, decisions that sub-

  Better Dead Than Fed?

  223

  stantially affect the risk of a civil war should be internalized among

  the neighborhood. In the Democratic Republic of the Congo sev-

  eral of the neighbors got involved: indeed, three of them, Rwanda,

  Uganda, and Angola, sent their troops into the country. The neigh-

  borhood dimension of security could scarcely be more graphically

  illustrated.

  Recall that by far the most dangerous situations are post-con-

  flict. Post-conflict relapses are likely and inflict high costs upon

  neighbors. Should the neighbors of a post-conflict state have some

  rights to a say in post-conflict policies? That was where my thinking

  had reached a year ago: post-conflict countries should go through

  a phase of sharing sovereignty with their neighbors until they had

  progressed out of danger. And then I woke up to two insuperable

  problems.

  Problem number one: Not only do neighbors have a legitimate

  interest in the governance of the post-conflict country, they are also

  likely to have some interests that are rather less legitimate. Around

  the world, neighbors often have problematic relationships: after all,

  they are overwhelmingly the main source of external threat. Paki-

  stan, which as I write is imploding following the death of Benazir

  Bhutto, is not going to share its sovereignty with India; Eritrea is

  not going to share its sovereignty with Ethiopia. So neighborhood-

  shared sovereignty is not going to work. The African Union rec-

  ognized this when it proposed that the African peacekeeping force

  for Somalia should be composed of forces from any willing coun-

  try other than a neighbor. However, Somalia also demonstrated the

  limits of that approach: the only country with a sufficiently strong

  interest to send a major force was neighboring Ethiopia.

  Problem number two: The neighbors of a country that becomes

  post-conflict are not a natural political grouping. As a result they

  have no experience of cooperating as a group. Worse, their coop-

  eration would clearly be time-limited: it may last for only a decade.

  Worse still, there may be rather a lot of neighbors. Take the Dem-

  224

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  ocratic Republic of the Congo, which is currently a post-conflict

  country, and look at a map. What grouping of neighbors do we get:

  Congo-Brazzaville, the Central African Republic, Sudan, Uganda,

  Rwanda, Tanzania, Zambia, and Angola. Experimental games find

  that cooperation gets harder as the number of players is increased,

  and eight participants is a lot. They also find that the players grad-

  ually learn how to cooperate, so that starting up as a group from

  cold would impose a phase of mistakes just when the post-conflict

  country is most vulnerable. Finally, one of the most basic results of

  experimental games is that players evolve a tit-for-tat strategy that

  enforces cooperation: players avoid unreasonable decisions because

  they would eventually get their comeuppance. So temporary coop-

  eration is much harder than permanent cooperation.

  These problems persuaded me that sharing sovereignty with

  the neighbors is out. What then is the alternative? The solution, I

  think, is to place the legitimate interests of neighbors in trust with a more permanent grouping that does not itself have strong interests. While this might be a regional body such as the African Union,

  the more obvious locus is the United Nations, and more specifically

  the Peace-Building Commission, which was established in 2005

  and is jointly under the Security Council and the General Assem-

  bly. So, in the case of the Democratic Republic of the Congo, the

  United Nations would hold a share of sovereignty on behalf of the

  neighbors, tasked with minimizing the shared costs inflicted on the

  neighbors. To be clear about this, the United Nations would not,

  in its own right, hold a share of sovereignty. This is far short of the old model of United Nations trusteeship that some scholars have

  suggested should be revived. The post-conflict government would

  share sovereignty rather than be stripped of it, and the objectives

  of the regional or international body with which sovereignty was

  shared would be predefined to be the protection of the legitimate

  interests of neighbors.

  What would guide the decisions of the trustees? To an extent,

  Better Dead Than Fed?

  225

  each decision has to be based on the totality of the circumstances that

  make each decision unique. But it would help to have an explicit set

  of guidelines. Guidelines are useful where different players have to

  be coordinated. I think that there are three distinct players. Some

  governments should provide or finance peacekeepers; some govern-

  ments should provide aid; and the post-conflict government should

  reform economic policy, cut its military spending, and, if it chooses

  to hold elections, let them be free and fair. The embargoes on im-

  ports of armaments that are appropriate in post-conflict situations

  have routinely been broken by rogue companies in countries that


  have to date been below the radar screen of international scrutiny,

  but we now have the means to identify such breaches.

  Each of these depends upon the others. Peacekeepers are less

  likely to get killed where arms embargoes are effective. The realis-

  tic exit strategy for peacekeepers is economic development. In turn,

  economic development is enhanced by aid and policy reform. Elec-

  tions as commonly practiced to date, which is to say far from free

  and fair, have increased the risk of violence, not reduced it. Not only

  are these decisions interdependent, but they need to be sustained for

  around a decade, whereas to date all three players usually focus only

  on the short term. Guidelines that set out the mutual responsibilities

  of all players over the course of the decade could not be legally bind-

  ing, but they could create a common expectation of behavior. They

  are also very much in the spirit of modern international coopera-

  tion: from the Monterrey Consensus to the United Nations Global

  Compact with large corporations, the approach has been to spell

  out mutual responsibilities. As the inclusion of the responsibility to

  comply with arms embargoes demonstrates, the responsibilities ex-

  tend broadly and are not polarized between the governments of the

  rich world and those of the bottom billion.

  In setting out guidelines for the behavior of each party, a post-

  conflict compact would also, implicitly or explicitly, reveal the red

  lines that should not be crossed. The clearer the red lines, the less

  226

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  likely they would be breached, and so international involvement in

  post-conflict situations would become less of a nightmare. If some

  red lines had been in place, I think that the post-conflict nightmares

  might have been avoided.

  I h av e p u t f o r wa r d t h r e e proposals for international action.

  Between them they address the abuse of democracy in the acquisi-

  tion of power, the misuse of power once acquired, and the structural

  insecurity that has beset the societies of the bottom billion. Might

  they be adopted?

  At present, discussion of international action ranges across

  the extremes. Think of the different stances on Zimbabwe. At

  one extreme there have been calls both from within Zimbabwe,

  by the Archbishop of Bulawayo, and from a range of international

  commentators, for international military intervention to depose

  President Mugabe. Tony Blair vetoed Mugabe’s attendance at the

  Commonwealth Conference, and Gordon Brown refused to at-

  tend the Africa-Europe Summit because Mugabe was included.

  At the other extreme has been the indignant solidarity of African

  presidents, manifested in the election of Zimbabwe as chair of the

  United Nations Human Rights Committee. The three proposals

  in this book are a very long way from using military intervention

  for regime change. I think that externally imposed regime change

  tramples on the unhealed wound of colonialism and so is unreal-

  istic. They are also far from noninterference. In an interconnected

  world, untrammeled national sovereignty leads unswervingly to

  hell. The proposals are a compromise between positions that are

  currently deadlocked.

  If they were adopted, would they make a difference?

  The disaster unfolding before my eyes as I finish this book is

  Kenya. As the book has built up I have tried to show how the rule to

  bolster the conduct of elections would quite probably have changed

  Better Dead Than Fed?

  227

  the course of Kenyan history. But the disaster that has overshadowed

  Africa for the past decade has been Zimbabwe. Manifestly, Presi-

  dent Mugabe has systematically dismantled both the democratic

  polity and the economy of his country. So what might have averted

  this disaster? The only power that might realistically have changed

  the course of Zimbabwean history is its own military. The African

  Union now has a rule refusing to accept coups as legitimate. While it

  is entirely understandable that incumbent presidents would happily

  agree to such a rule, it is misplaced. Zimbabwe needed a coup, but

  not one that led, as in Cote d’Ivoire and Ethiopia, to further ruin.

  Coups need to be harnessed, not eliminated: the core proposal of

  this book.

  C h a p t e r 1 0

  O N C H A N G I N G R E A L I T Y

  We have come full course. The societies of

  the bottom billion are structurally insecure and

  structurally unaccountable. Despite recent years be-

  ing the most successful period of economic global growth on record,

  the appalling consequences are apparent to all. Structural insecurity

  hit the headlines in 2007 first due to Somalia and then to Sudan.

  Structural lack of accountability in the conduct of elections hit the

  headlines in 2007, first in Nigeria, then in Pakistan, shortly followed

  by Kenya. The year 2008 started with a rebellion in Chad and a coup

  attempt in East Timor, the president of which is currently recuper-

  ating in Australia. I fear that there will be many more such events.

  So what, in a nutshell, is the structural problem faced by the

  countries of the bottom billion? It is that they are too large to be na-

  tions yet too small to be states. Too large, because they lack the cohesion needed for collective action. Too small, because they lack the

  scale needed to produce public goods efficiently. Societies can func-

  tion well enough without some public goods because they can also

  be supplied privately. Some of the health and education services that

  are supplied as public goods in Europe are supplied as private goods

  in America. But some other public goods cannot be substituted by

  private activity. Security and accountability are such goods.

  230

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  No society can rely successfully upon private security, although

  periodically it has been tried. The private forces hired for defense

  become predatory on the very people they are supposed to protect.

  Britons tried it after the Romans departed, hiring a gang of Jute

  thugs to defend them against the Picts. It took the thugs fifteen

  years to work out the obvious: they then slaughtered the British po-

  litical elite and took over. As for the private provision of account-

  ability, most instances that appear to be private provision, such as

  the way that the American health system is disciplined by the fear

  of being sued, depend upon being backstopped by the rule of law.

  In the absence of the rule of law the need to maintain a good repu-

  tation within a small network of associates can enforce a degree of

  accountability. Economists regularly parade the example of how

  thirteenth-century Jewish traders conducted long-distance trade

  despite the lack of law. But Avinash Dixit has recently shown that if

  such networks are scaled up the whole system crashes. Security and

  accountability are either provided by government or they are not

  provided. Their absence produces socioeconomic conditions such as

  the botto
m billion have lived through for forty years. During that

  time they have become the poorest people on earth.

  With sufficiently visionary political leadership, the states of

  the bottom billion could build a shared identity within the society,

  thereby transforming state into nation, and cooperate with the other

  nations of their region. Combined, these approaches would enhance

  the supply of the public goods, providing the security and the checks

  and balances that their citizens need. From time to time people ca-

  pable of such leadership gain political power, but not very often. It

  is not by chance that the visionary leaders Julius Nyerere, Sukarno,

  and Nelson Mandela were all founding presidents. Once political

  power can readily be won by the self-serving, the self-serving will

  step forward to try their luck and the honorable will step back. Bad

  currency drives out good. In this book I have spared you the fancy

  terminology of economics, but since you have reached the end you

  On Changing Reality

  231

  can take delight in one technical term: in economic language the

  quality of political leadership is endogenous. As a result, in these

  societies visionary leadership is now rare.

  There is thus a powerful case for security and accountability to

  be regarded as basic social needs that, as a default option, should be

  provided internationally. After the intervention in Iraq, many peo-

  ple might reasonably feel that the unintended consequences of secu-

  rity interventions are such that intervention in any form is too risky.

  Yet international military intervention has had many successes. The

  lesson is not that it is intrinsically risky, but that the circumstances

  that warrant it should be limited and clearly delineated.

  Since any such proposal will be met by a chorus of outrage from

  the beneficiaries of presidential sovereignty, the five billion who live

  in territories that have been more fortunate can readily justify their

  natural proclivity to stand back and watch. It will also be the con-

  clusion of those in thrall to a sense of victimhood: the rest of the

  world has already done enough damage. My own attitude used to

  be “just give it time.” After all, in the countries that are now devel-

  oped, the transition from the effective but unaccountable state of the

 

‹ Prev