The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

Home > Other > The Structure of Evolutionary Theory > Page 26
The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Page 26

by Stephen Jay Gould


  I raise this point here because abuse of selective quotation has been particularly notable in discussions of Darwin's views on gradualism. Of course Dar­win acknowledged great variation in rates of change, and even episodes of rapidity that might be labelled catastrophic (at least on a local scale); for how could such an excellent naturalist deny nature's multifariousness on such a key issue as the character of change itself? But these occasional statements do not make Darwin the godfather of punctuated equilibrium, or a cryptic sup­porter of saltation (as de Vries actually claimed, thus earning a unique and of­ficial rebuke from the organizers of the Darwinian centenary celebration at Cambridge — see p. 416).

  Gradualism may represent the most central conviction residing both within and behind all Darwin's thought. Gradualism far antedates natural selection among his guiding concerns, and casts a far wider net over his choice of subjects for study. Gradualism sets the explanatory framework for his first substantive book on coral reefs (1842) and for his last on the formation of to­pography and topsoil by earthworms (1881) — two works largely devoid of [Page 149] reference to natural selection. Gradualism had been equated with rationality itself by Darwin's chief guru, Charles Lyell (see Chapter 6). All scholars have noted the centrality of gradualism, both in the ontogeny (Gruber and Barrett, 1974) and logic (Mayr, 1991) of Darwin's thought.

  I will not play “duelling quotations” with “citation grazers,” though a full tabulation of relative frequencies could easily bury their claims under a mountain of statements. For the present assessment of branch two (“creativ­ity of natural selection”) on the coral of essential Darwinian logic, the neces­sity of gradualism will suffice. Selection becomes creative only if it can impart direction to evolution by superintending the slow and steady accumulation of favored subsets from an isotropic pool of variation. If gradualism does not accompany this process of change, selection must relinquish this creative role and Darwinism then fails as a creative source of evolutionary novelty. If im­portant new features, or entire new taxa, arise as large and discontinuous variations, then creativity lies in production of the variation itself. Natural se­lection no longer causes evolution, and can only act as a headsman for the unfit, thus promoting changes that originated in other ways. Gradualism therefore becomes a logical consequence of the operation of natural selection in Darwin's creative mode. Gradualism also pervades the methodological pole of Darwin's greatness because the uniformitarian argument of extrapola­tion will not work unless change at the grandest scale arises by the summa­tion through time of small, immediate, and palpable variations.

  Gradualism, for Darwin, represents a complex doctrine with several layers of meaning, all interconnected, while remaining independent in some impor­tant senses. I shall consider three increasing levels of specificity, arguing, on the Goldilocks model, that one meaning is too nebulous, another overly wrought, but the third (in the middle) “just right” as the crucial validator of natural selection (whereas the other two meanings play equally crucial roles for other aspects of Darwin's view of life).

  Historical continuity of stuff and information. At the broadest level, gradualism merely asserts unbroken historical connectedness between putative ancestor and descendant, without characterizing the mode or rate of transition. If new species originate as creations ex nihilo by a divine power, then connectivity fails. The assertion of gradualism in this broadest meaning encapsulates the chief defense for the factuality of evolution. Such a contention could not be more vital to Darwin's revolution of course, but this sense of gradualism only asserts that evolution occurred, while telling us nothing about how evolution happens; the logical tie of gradualism to natural selection cannot reside here.* Thus, this first, or “too big,” sense of gradualism [Page 150] validates evolution itself (vs. creationism), but not Darwin's, or anyone else's, proposed mechanism of evolutionary change.

  Insensibility of intermediacy. We now come to the heart of what natural selection requires. This second, “just right,” statement does not ad­vance a claim about how much time a transition must take, or how variable a rate of change might be. The second meaning simply asserts that, in going from A to a substantially different B, evolution must pass through a long and insensible sequence of intermediary steps — in other words, that ancestor and descendant must be linked by a series of changes, each within the range of what natural selection might construct from ordinary variability. Without gradualism in this form, large variations of discontinuous morphological im­port — rather than natural selection — might provide the creative force of evo­lutionary change. But if the tiny increment of each step remains inconsequen­tial in itself, then creativity must reside in the summation of these steps into something substantial — and natural selection, in Darwin's theory, acts as the agent of accumulation.

  This meaning of gradualism underlies Darwin's frequent invocation of the old Leibnizian and Linnaean aphorism, Natura non facit saltum (nature does not proceed by leaps). Darwin's commitment to this postulate can only strike us as fierce and, by modern standards, overly drawn. Thus, Darwin writes (p. 189): “If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modi­fications, my theory would absolutely break down.” And lest we doubt that “my theory” refers specifically to the mechanism of natural selection (and not simply to the assertion of evolution), Darwin often draws an explicit link be­tween selection as a creative force and gradualism as an implied necessity: “Undoubtedly nothing can be effected through Natural Selection except by the addition of infinitesimally small changes; and if it could be shown that... transitional states were impossible, the theory would be overthrown” (in Natural Selection — see Stauffer, 1975, p. 250). And in the concluding chapter of the Origin: “As natural selection acts solely by accumulating slight, succes­sive, favorable variations, it can produce no great or sudden modification; it can act only by very short and slow steps. Hence the canon of 'Natura non facit saltum'... is on this theory simply intelligible” (p. 471).

  But would the theory of natural selection “absolutely break down” if even a single organ — not to mention an entire organism — could arise by large and discontinuous changes? Does Darwinism truly require the following extreme [Page 151] formulation: “Natural selection can only act by the preservation and accu­mulation of infinitesimally small inherited modifications” (p. 95). At some level of discontinuity, of course, Darwin's strong statement must prevail. If the altered morphology of new species often arose in single steps by fortu­itous macromutation, then selection would lose its creative role and could act only as a secondary and auxiliary force to spread the sudden blessing through a population. But can we justify Darwin's application of the same claim to single organs? Suppose (as must often happen) that developmental heterochrony produces a major shift in form and function by two or three steps without intermediary stages. The size of these steps may lie outside the “normal” variation of most populations at most moments, but not beyond the potential of an inherited developmental program. (Incidentally, these types of changes represent the concept that Goldschmidt embodied in the le­gitimate meaning of “hopeful monster,” before he made his unfortunate deci­sion to tie this interesting concept to his fallacious genetics of “systemic mu­tation” — see Chapter 5 and Gould, 1982a.)

  Would natural selection perish if change in this mode were common? I don't think so. Darwinian theory would require some adjustments and com­promises — particularly a toning down of assertions about the isotropy of variation, and a more vigorous study of internal constraint in genetics and de­velopment (see Chapter 10 for advocacy of this theoretical shift) — but natu­ral selection would still enjoy a status far higher than that of a mere execu­tioner. A new organ does not make a new species; and a new morphology must be brought into functional integration — a process that requires second­ary adaptation and fine tuning, presumably by natural selection, whatever the extent of the initial step.
<
br />   I believe, therefore, that Darwin's strong, even pugnacious, defense of strict gradualism reflects a much more pervasive commitment, extending far be­yond the simple recognition of a logical entailment implied by natural selec­tion — and that this stronger conviction must record such general influences as Darwin's attraction to Lyell's conflation of gradualism with rationality itself, and the cultural appeal of gradualism during Britain's greatest age of indus­trial expansion and imperial conquest (Gould, 1984a). Huxley's savvy assess­ment of the Origin still rings true, for while he offered, in his famous letter to Darwin, written just as the Origin rolled off the presses, to “go to the stake” for Darwin's view, he also stated his major criticism: “You have loaded your­self with an unnecessary difficulty in adopting Natura non facit saltum so un­reservedly” (in L. Huxley, 1901, p. 189).

  Darwin persevered nonetheless. We often fail to recognize how much of the Origin presents an exposition of gradualism, rather than a defense of natural selection. As a striking example, the famous (and virtually only) statement about human evolution asserts the pedagogical value of gradualism — not nat­ural selection — in our Socratic quest to know ourselves: “Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation. Light will be thrown on the origin of man and his history” (p. 488). [Page 152]

  Chapter 9 on geological evidence, where the uninitiated might expect to find a strong defense for evolution from the most direct source of evidence in the fossil record, reads instead as a long (and legitimate) apologia for a threatening discordance between data and logical entailment — a fossil record dominated by gaps and discontinuities when read literally vs. the insensible transitions required by natural selection as a creative agent. Darwin, with his characteristic honesty, states the dilemma baldly in succinct deference to his methodological need for equating temporal steps of change with differences noted among varieties of contemporary species: “By the theory of natural se­lection all living species have been connected with the parent-species of each genus, by differences not greater than we see between the varieties of the same species at the present day” (p. 281).

  Darwin, as we all know, resolved this discordance by branding the fossil record as so imperfect — like a book with few pages present and only a few let­ters preserved on each page — that truly insensible continuity becomes de­graded to a series of abrupt leaps in surviving evidence:

  Why then is not every geological formation and every stratum full of such intermediate links? Geology assuredly does not reveal any such finely graduated organic chain; and this, perhaps, is the most obvious and gravest objection which can be urged against my theory. This expla­nation lies, as I believe, in the extreme imperfection of the geological rec­ord (p. 280).

  He, who rejects these views on the nature of the geological record, will rightly reject my whole theory (p. 342).

  Slowness and smoothness (but not constancy) of rate. Darwin also championed the most stringent version of gradualism — not mere continuity of information, and not just insensibility of innumerable transi­tional steps; but also the additional claim that change must be insensibly gradual even at the broadest temporal scale of geological durations, and that continuous flux (at variable rates to be sure) represents the usual state of nature.

  This broadest version of gradualism does not hold strong logical ties to natural selection as an evolutionary mechanism. Change might be episodic and abrupt in geological perspective, but still proceed by insensible intermediacy at a generational perspective — given the crucial scaling principle that thousands of generations make a geological moment. For this reason, Eldredge and I have never viewed punctuated equilibrium, which does refute Darwinian gradualism in this third sense, as an attack on the creativity of nat­ural selection itself (Eldredge and Gould, 1972; Gould and Eldredge, 1977, 1993). The challenge of punctuated equilibrium to natural selection rests upon two entirely different issues of support provided by punctuational ge­ometry for the explanation of cladal trends by differential species success and not by extrapolated anagenesis, and for the high relative frequency of species selection, as opposed to the exclusivity of Darwinian selection on organisms (see Chapters 8 and 9). [Page 153]

  Some fidei defensores of the Darwinian citadel have sensed the weakness of this third version of gradualism, and have either pointed out that the creativ­ity of natural selection cannot be compromised thereby (quite correct, but then no one ever raised such a challenge, at least within the legitimate de­bate on punctuated equilibrium); or have argued either that Darwin meant no such thing, or that, if he really did, the claim has no importance (see Dawkins, 1986). This last effort in apologetics provides a striking illustration of the retrospective fallacy in historiography. Whatever the current status of this third formulation within modern Darwinism, this broadest style of grad­ualism was vitally important to Darwin; for belief in slow change in geologi­cal perspective lies at the heart of his more inclusive view about nature and science, an issue even larger than the mechanics of natural selection.

  Darwin often states his convictions about extreme slowness and contin­uous flux in geological time — as something quite apart from gradualism's second meaning of insensible intermediacy in microevolutionary perspec­tive. Evolutionary change, Darwin asserts, usually occurs so slowly that even the immense length of an average geological formation may not reach the mean time of transformation between species. Thus, apparent stasis may ac­tually represent change at average rates, but to an imperceptible degree even through such an extensive stretch of geological time! “Although each forma­tion may mark a very long lapse of years, each perhaps is short compared with the period requisite to change one species into another” (p. 293).

  Change not only occurs with geological slowness on this largest scale; but most transformations also proceed in sufficient continuity and limited varia­tion in rate that elapsed time may be roughly measured by degree of accumu­lated difference: “The amount of organic change in the fossils of consecutive formations probably serves as a fair measure of the lapse of actual time” (p. 488).

  Darwin presents his credo in crisp epitome: “Nature acts uniformly and slowly during vast periods of time on the whole organization, in any way which may be for each creature's own good” (p. 269). Note how Darwin concentrates so many of his central beliefs into so few words: gradualism, adaptationism, locus of selection on organisms.

  But the most striking testimony to Darwin's conviction about gradualism in this third sense of slow and continuous flux lies in several errors promi­nently highlighted in the Origin — all based on convictions about steady rate (gradualism in the third sense), not on the insensible intermediacy genuinely demanded by natural selection (gradualism in the second sense), or on the simple continuity of historical information required to validate the factuality of evolution itself (gradualism in the first sense). For example, Darwin makes a famous calculation (dropped from later editions) on the “denudation of the Weald” — the erosion of the anticlinal valley located between the North and South Chalk Downs of southern England (pp. 285-287). He tries to deter­mine an average value for yearly erosion of seacliffs today, and then extrapo­lates his figure as a constant rate into the past. His date of some 300 million years for the denudation of the Weald overestimated the true duration by five [Page 154] times or more. (The deposition of the Chalk, an Upper Cretaceous formation, persisted nearly to the period's end 65 million years ago.)

  Moving to a biological example that underscores Darwin's hostility to episodes of “explosive” evolutionary diversification (he used his usual argument about the imperfection of the fossil record to deny their literal appearance and to spread them out in time), Darwin predicted that the Cambrian explo­sion would be exposed as an artifact, and that complex multicellular crea­tures must have thrived for vast Precambrian durations, gradually reaching the complexity of basal Cambrian forms. (When Darwin published in 1859, the Cambrian had
not yet been recognized, and his text therefore speaks of the base of the Silurian, meaning lower Cambrian in modern terminology): “If my theory be true, it is indisputable that before the lowest Silurian stra­tum was deposited, long periods elapsed, as long as, or probably far longer than, the whole interval from the Silurian age to the present day; and that during these vast, yet quite unknown periods of time, the world swarmed with living creatures” (p. 307).

  Paleontologists have now established a good record of Precambrian life. The world did swarm indeed, but only with single-celled forms and multi-cellular algae, until the latest Precambrian fauna of the Ediacara beds (begin­ning about 600 million years ago). The explosion of multicellular life now seems as abrupt as ever — even more so since the argument now rests on copi­ous documentation of Precambrian life, rather than a paucity of evidence that could be attributed to imperfections of the geological record (see Chapter 10, pp. 1155–1161). Darwin on the other hand, predicted that complex, multi­cellular creatures must extend far into the Precambrian. He wrote: “I cannot doubt that all the Silurian [= Cambrian] trilobites have descended from some one crustacean, which must have lived long before the Silurian [= Cambrian] age” (p. 306). Darwin also conjectured, again incorrectly, that the ancestral verterbrate, an animal with an adult phenotype resembling the common embryological Bauplan of all modern vertebrates, must have lived long before the dawn of Cambrian times: “It would be vain to look for [adult] animals having the common embryological character of the Vertebrata, until beds far beneath the lowest Silurian strata are discovered” (p. 338).

  Darwin struggled for clarity and consistency. He did not always succeed. (How can an honest person so prevail in our complex and confusing world? I shall, for example, examine Darwin's ambivalences on progress in Chapter 6.) Darwin did not always keep the different senses of gradualism distinct. He frequently conflated meanings, arguing (for example) that the validity of nat­ural selection (sense 2) required an acceptance of slow and continuous flux (sense 3). Consider once again the following familiar passage: “It may be said that natural selection is daily and hourly scrutinizing, throughout the world, every variation, even the slightest... We see nothing of these slow changes in progress, until the hand of time has marked the long lapse of ages” (p. 84).

 

‹ Prev