The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

Home > Other > The Structure of Evolutionary Theory > Page 115
The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Page 115

by Stephen Jay Gould


  A reconciliation of allopatric speciation with long-term trends can be formulated ... We envision multiple . . . invasions, on a stochastic basis, of new environments by peripheral isolates. There is nothing inherently directional about these invasions. However, a subset of these new environments might... lead to new and improved efficiency ... The overall effect would then be one of net, apparently directional change: but, as with the case of selection upon mutations, the initial variations [species] would be stochastic with respect to the change [trend].

  Several paleontologists groped towards a generalization during the next few years, but Stanley (1975, 1979) made the greatest headway in appreciat­ing the full generality of such an analogistic procedure for macroevolutionary theory: “In this higher-level process species become analogous to individuals, and speciation replaces reproduction. The random aspects of speciation take the place of mutation. Whereas, natural selection operates upon individu­als within populations, a process that can be termed species selection oper­ates upon species within higher taxa, determining statistical trends” (Stanley, 1975, p. 648).

  Stanley preceded this statement with a claim that I regard as fully justified and prescient, but that became a lightning rod for unfair criticism: “Macroevolution is decoupled from microevolution, and we must envision the pro­cess governing its course as being analogous to natural selection but operat­ing at a higher level of organization” (1975, p. 648). Largely on the basis of this claim about “decoupling,” Stanley, Eldredge and I, and others, were of­ten accused of trying to scuttle Darwinism, and to invent an entirely new (and fatuously speculative) causal apparatus for evolutionary change (meaning, and explicitly so stated in this reductionistic critique, a new genetics).

  We made no such claim, and the words quoted above speak for themselves. We were trying to explore the different workings of selection on individuals at levels of the evolutionary hierarchy higher than the conventional Darwin­ian focus upon organisms. Not only do I continue to regard this procedure as [Page 716] fruitful and fully justified, but I would also defend such an effort as the basis for an independent macroevolutionary theory that can harmoniously expand our conventional and exclusive focus on organisms to yield a more satisfac­tory general account of life's workings and history.

  I also continue to regard the individuality of species as the central proposi­tion of such an expanded theory. If organisms are the traditional units of se­lection in classical Darwinian microevolution within populations, then spe­cies operate in the same manner as basic units of macroevolutionary change. This perspective establishes an irreducible hierarchical structure in nature, precluding the smooth upward extrapolation of microevolutionary change within populations to explain evolution at all scales, particularly phenotypic trends and patterns of diversity displayed in geological time — the proposition that true devotees of microevolutionary exclusivism rightly feared. If species, as stable units and genuine evolutionary individuals, interpose themselves be­tween populational anagenesis and trends within clades, then the lower-level process cannot smoothly encompass the higher-level phenomenon. For this fundamental (and excellent) reason — and not because any “new” genetics or anti-Darwinian forces reign in a threatening world of macroevolution — Stan­ley introduced his key notion of “decoupling.”

  The levels become decoupled because macroevolution must employ species as “atoms,” or stable and basic units of change. Decoupling then becomes in­tensified because higher levels exhibit allometric properties that distinguish their phenomenology from the workings of lower levels. Thus, macroevolu­tion with species as individuals must differ, in deep and interesting ways, from microevolution with organisms as individuals. These differences, and not any fatuous claims about “new genetics,” express the uniqueness of macroevolution, and the validity of our argument for decoupling.

  An extensive analogy — “the grand analogy,” if you will (see Gould and Eldredge, 1977, p. 142) — between organismal microevolution and speciational macroevolution provides a good tool for assessing the differences im­posed by scaling among the levels. Stanley (1975, p. 649) and Gould and Eldredge (1977, pp. 142-145) proposed some partial and preliminary schemes, and several others have added components along the way (Stanley, 1979; Vrba, 1980; Grantham, 1995, for example). I present this grand anal­ogy below, largely in the form of a chart contrasting the key features of or­ganic structure and evolution in their organismal and speciational manifesta­tions. For each major category, I list the most important differences between the levels. A fuller explication of all items on the chart follows.

  THE PARTICULARS OF MACROEVOLUTIONARY EXPLANATION

  The structural basis

  The first category of structural differences seems straightforward enough. In order to construct the analogy, we ratchet the focal level of individuality up from the organism to the species, thus redefining both lower components and higher contexts in the structural triad of part-individual-collectivity (see page

  [Page 717]

  Table 8-1. The Grand Analogy

  Feature

  Organismal Level

  Species Level

  I The Triad of Structure

  1. Individual

  Organism

  Species

  2. Part

  Gene, cell

  Organism, deme

  3. Collectivity

  Deme, species

  Clade

  2a. Usual result of

  proliferation of one pan to

  crowd out others

  Cancer

  Immediately adaptive

  anagenesis

  II The Criteria of Individuality

  1. Production of

  new individuals

  Birth

  Speciation

  2. Elimination of individuals

  Death

  Extinction

  3. Sources of cohesion

  i) Stability of individual

  Physiological homeostasis

  in ontogeny

  Sources of stasis in punc-

  tuated equilibrium

  ii) Boundaries against

  invasion

  Skin to delineate; immune

  system to police

  Reproductive isolating

  mechanisms

  iii) “Glue” of subparts

  Functional integration &

  division of labor

  Social structure & behav-

  ioral interaction among

  parts (organisms); re-

  combination in sexual

  reproduction to mix

  parts in their replica-

  tion

  4. Inheritance

  Asexual by budding from

  one individual, or sex-

  from one individual

  ual by mixture of two

  individuals

  “Asexual” by budding

  from one individual

  5. Source of new variation in

  newborn individuals

  Mutation

  Geographic (or some

  other form of) isolation

  (a precondition); drift

  & selection (mecha-

  nisms), causing differ-

  ences that break repro-

  ductive integrity

  4a. Spread of new variation to

  other individuals in the

  collectivity

  Recombination in sexual

  reproduction

  Generally absent except

  for hybridization be-

  tween species in some

  clades

  5a. Frequency of new variation

  in replicated individuals

  Very rare for any single

  trait

  Inherent in birth process

  and always present

  III Modes of Change in the Collectivity

  A. Drives, or Directional Variation Within or Between Individuals

  1. Heritable ontogenetic

&n
bsp; change within the

  individual=ontogenetic

  drive

  Lamarckism—powerful if

  it occurred, but pre-

  cluded by nature of he-

  redity

  Anagenesis (gradualism

  within species); rare by

  punctuated equilibrium

  [Page 718]

  Table 8-1 (continued)

  Feature

  Organismal Level

  Species Level

  2. Biased production of new

  individuals=reproductive

  drive

  Mutation pressure

  Directional speciation

  2a. Frequency of biased

  production

  Very low (if harmful to

  organism) because

  organismal selection

  effectively suppresses

  lower levels

  Potentially common for

  two reasons: 1) species

  processes don't strongly

  suppress lower-level se-

  lection; 2) new individ-

  uals must originate

  with change from par-

  ent

  B. Selection, or Differential Proliferation Due to Traits of Interactors

  1. Name of process

  Natural (organismal)

  selection

  Species selection

  2. Basis in birth

  Differential birth

  Differential speciation

  3. Basis in death

  Differential death

  Differential extinction

  2a. Reason for non-

  directionality of variation

  as precondition of

  selection's power

  Inherent in nature of

  mutation as unrelated

  to needs of organism

  No necessary reason;

  benefits of organism &

  species frequently coin-

  cide. No relation if im-

  mediate adaptive con-

  texts of new species

  uncorrelated with direc-

  tion of trend. Testable

  as Wright's Rule

  2b. Distinctive feature of birth

  bias

  Usually internal to organ-

  ism; need not lead to

  adaptation to environ-

  ment

  Usually irreducible as

  based on traits of pop-

  ulations, not organisms

  3a. Distinctive feature of death

  bias

  Usually yields adaptation

  to local environment

  Often reducible as simple

  summation of organism

  deaths

  C. Drift, or Random Differential Proliferation

  1. Within the collectivity

  Genetic drift

  Species drift

  2. In founding of new

  collectivities

  Founder effect

  Founder drift

  1a. Frequency

  Rare except in special cir-

  cumstances of small

  populations, or neutral-

  ity of many genie sites

  Common because most

  clades have low N;

  intensified by reduction

  of N in mass extinction

  2a. Frequency

  Common; depends on N

  of founding population

  Very common for two

  reasons: 1) necessary

  (and often large) differ-

  ence from ancestor at

  each founding; 2)

  greatly different poten-

  tials in allopatric re-

  gions

  [Page 719]

  Table 8-1 (continued)

  Feature

  Organismal Level

  Species Level

  IV External and Internal Environments

  A. Competition and the External Environment

  1. In direct contact

  Most often biotic

  More likely to produce

  an effect by differential

  elimination

  2. Not in direct contact; often

  allopatric

  More often abiotic

  More likely to produce

  an effect by differential

  birth

  1a. Main feature

  Major source of occa-

  sional biomechanical or

  general progress

  Often reducible to

  organismal level

  2a. Main feature

  Adaptation to local cir-

  cumstances; no general

  vector

  Usually irreducible

  B. Constraint and the Internal Environment

  1. Limits on runaway change

  by directional evolution of

  parts

  Lamarckian inheritance

  doesn't occur

  Punctuated equilibrium

  suppresses anagenesis

  by stasis

  2. Structural brakes upon

  change

  Design limits of Bauplan

  Positive correlation of

  frequency of speciation

  and extinction appar-

  ently unbreakable

  3. Variational brakes

  Rarity of new mutation

  allayed by recombina-

  tion in sexuals; serious

  in asexuals (allayed by

  short generations in

  many unicells)

  Sufficient change per new

  individual, but low N

  of species in clades

  4. Developmental brakes

  Von Baer's laws of com-

  plex ontogenesis

  Hold of homology

  5. Positive channeling by

  structure

  Heterochrony and pre-

  ferred ontogenetic ex-

  tensions

  Differential ease &

  permissibility of

  Bauplan modifications

  6. Positive channeling by

  variation

  Not important, given rar-

  ity of directional varia-

  tion

  Frequent correlation of

  directional speciation

  with differential prolif-

  eration

  7. Size of exaptive pool

  High in such crucial cir-

  cumstances as genetic

  redundancy usable in

  evolution of complexity

  Generally high because

  lower levels not sup-

  pressed and frequently

  correlative

  [Page 720]

  673). But this basic ratcheting already reveals some pivotal differences be­tween the evolution of organism-individuals and species-individuals. In Table 8-1, line I2a, for example, notes the profoundly different outcome that usu­ally ensues when particular parts of the individual proliferate differentially and crowd out other parts. Such a process usually spells disaster for a com­plex multicellular organism — and we call the result cancer — because parts lack independent viability (and therefore harm both themselves and their col­lectivity, the organism, by unchecked proliferation), and because organisms build coherence (an important criterion of individuality) by functional inte­gration and division of labor among parts. But species achieve equal coher­ence by other routes. The parts of a species — that is, its component organ­isms — do have independent viability; moreover, their interests in proliferation often coincide with the health of the enclosing species. Thus, in a species-indi­vidual, differential proliferation of some parts at the expense of other parts does not lead to death of the full entity, but usually to adaptation by anagenesis.

  Criteria for individuality

  Moving to the second category of criteria for individuality (see pp. 602–613 of this chapter), we may regard the species-level analogs of o
rganismal birth and death (lines III—2) — speciation and extinction — as both evident and well recognized. But the different causes of cohesion (line 113) are both fascinating and portentous throughout the chart. I only remind readers that the mecha­nisms used by species, while not clamping down so hard on lower levels, and therefore providing substantial “play” for interaction between organismal and species selection, provide species with as much coherence and stability as the “standard” devices of morphological boundaries, internal policing and functional integration among parts, do for organisms.

  Important differences arise in the mode of production for novel variation in newborn individuals. Mutation supplies this attribute at the organismal level. (Following conventional usage, I consider recombination in sexual or­ganisms as a device for spreading variation among individuals, although I recognize, of course, that novel combinations also arise thereby. In asexual organisms, a better analog for species in any case, mutation alone supplies new variation.) Speciation itself is not the proper analog of mutation at the species level (an error previously made both by me, in Gould and Eldredge, 1977, and by Stanley, 1975). Speciation, the production of a new species-individual by budding, is the analog of organismal birth, particularly the birth of asexual organisms. We made this error by inadequately interpreting one of the most interesting differences between organisms and species as evo­lutionary individuals. The birth of a new organism, particularly in asexuals, may or may not engender any substantial difference from parental form or genetics. But the birth of a new species necessarily includes the generation of enough difference from ancestors to preclude reproductive amalgation be­tween the parts (organisms) of the two species. We therefore mistook a forced correlate of birth at the species level (change at speciation) with the process of [Page 721] birth itself (speciation) — and equated the correlate at one level with the phenomenon at the other. The proper analog of mutation, a source of variation for new individuals, is the change that insures reproductive isolation between species (with geographic isolation as a usual precondition, and drift and se­lection as mechanisms) — see line 115.

 

‹ Prev