The Book of Memory

Home > Other > The Book of Memory > Page 15
The Book of Memory Page 15

by Mary Carruthers


  machine nor the machine itself. It is ‘ embodied,’ as the form which

  ‘ causes matter to be.’ 62

  The implications of this belief were well realized by Thomas Aquinas’s

  great pupil, Dante, when, at the end of his Paradiso, memory and speech

  both fail him. Angels, says Dante, have no need of memory for they have

  continuous understanding,63 but human beings must know by remember-

  ing physically formed phantasms. Of direct knowledge of God, such as that

  indicated at the end of the Paradiso, the memory ‘ can form no adequate

  image,’ in Gardner’s phrase (we recall the scholastic aphorism, veritas est

  adaequatio rei et verbi), and so it fails the intellect, bringing back nothing but

  an inadequate shadow or impression of the vanished vision. 64 The bodily

  matrix of memory is also clear in Thomas Aquinas’s belief that sensory

  memory does not survive death, for it has ‘‘no activity apart from the

  corporal organ.’ 65 The memory that is immortal is what he calls ‘‘intellectual

  memory,’ since the intellect does survive death. But this is not true memory.

  Intellectual memory is ‘‘the notion of memory’’ (a conception of having had

  a memory when one was still alive in one’s body); after death, the soul can

  still regard past events which are preserved in its intellect, and it can recall

  these (for recollection is an intellectual activity). But it can form no new

  memories when it no longer has a body.66 Because memory requires a body,

  the souls in Dante’s Inferno are forever stuck in their recollected pasts,

  unable to form new memories in hell, yet cut off also from the continuous

  vision that nourishes the blessed souls and angels.

  Dream-images and memory-images

  Other kinds of images were thought to arise from the imagination. It will

  be useful to consider these briefly, as a way of distinguishing them from

  memory-images. Imagination produces a dream-image in a different man-

  ner, though from the same materials. Aristotle says that the mental images

  which come in dreams arise spontaneously, not in response to a controlled

  process like recollection; in fact this is their chief difference from the

  memory-images that are the subject of my study here. Dream-images are

  74

  The Book of Memory

  created by the vis imaginativa, as are all phantasms.67 They are in the same

  class as after images, hallucinations, and other irrational images, the

  product of aroused, imbalanced emotions (as perception is distorted by

  anger or lust) or of raw sense-data unformed by judgment (as when we see

  the land moving as we ride through it). Such images are themselves just

  sense-data, aisth¯emata, rather than being the imprint of a sense impression

  after some time has elapsed, Aristotle’s basic definition of a memory-

  phantasm. To put the matter in modern psychological terms, Aristotle

  does not consider that a memory is a memory until it has been securely

  stored in a retrievable manner in the ‘‘long-term memory.’’ In sleep, the

  controlling sensus communis, the seat of awareness, is not functioning. So

  the external senses, if stimulated, produce unprocessed raw data; there are

  also residual movements, effects, left over from material received during

  the day.68 All of this uncontrolled material can stimulate the imagination,

  but with the sensus communis and all other judgmental activity in the inner

  sense suspended, the resulting mental images pose a special interpretive

  problem, for they must be judged after the fact, as it were, as to their truth

  or falsity, whether they are of divine origin and predictive of the future, or

  whether they are simply the body’s way of adjusting the balance of humors,

  or the product of random, raw aisth¯emata.

  While Aristotle acknowledges that some dreams can be true, such things

  do not seem to interest him very much, and he says little about them. But

  Averroe¨s and Avicenna are both greatly interested in prophetic dreams,

  which they regard as the province of those with especially well-formed

  imaginations. Avicenna discusses the prophetic imagination, ‘ that is, what

  is genuinely prophetic in the image-making power.’ 69 Dreams of the future

  result from a direct action of angelic intelligences upon the mind in sleep,

  acting upon the imagination. He also recognizes inspirations ‘ which sud-

  denly fall into the soul [quae subito in animam cadunt],’ unrelated to

  previous knowledge or experience. Such inspiration is of various kinds,

  ‘ sometimes it is from the intellect, sometimes by means of divination, and

  sometimes it is from poetry, and this happens according to aptitude and

  habit and custom.’ 70 These inspirations, Avicenna says, arise from causes

  which assist the soul for the most part unknown and for the most part [they] are

  like sudden apparitions, which do not remain in a manner so that they can be

  sought out in recollection, unless the mind hastens to aid them with an already-

  held memory. 71

  Avicenna underlines here the relationship among the images formed in

  heightened states such as trances and epilepsy, in dreams, and those

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  75

  required in memory. The images produced during dreams and trances will

  disappear unless they are associated with images that are already in memory

  storage, already familiar and accessible to recollection. Thus even direct

  inspiration requires the immediate assistance of human memory, though

  in a way more mysterious than that of ordinary dreaming or consciously

  controlled recollection.

  Meticulous mental imaging – mental painting, really – is a feature of

  trained recollection, even when one may be ‘‘recollecting’’ an experience

  recorded in someone else’s words. In his Epitome of Aristotle’s Parva

  naturalia, written about 1170, Averroe¨s writes of individuals with peculiarly

  gifted powers of concentration, who can form accurate images of things

  just from their description by others: ‘‘In this manner, it is possible for a

  person to form the image of an elephant without his ever having actually

  seen one.’’ Such a feat can only be achieved by all three faculties (imagi-

  nation, cogitation, and memory) acting together, and is possible only for

  humans because it is an intellectual operation. Such concentration is

  ‘‘exceedingly difficult’’ and ‘‘will only occur in the case of those who

  exercise their minds in solitude.’’ Averroe¨s is speaking of consciously con-

  trolled procedures here, and it is note-worthy that he believes that the

  power of imagining predictively and originally can be achieved by con-

  scious meditation as well as by sudden inspirations. But ordinarily it is in

  sleep or trance, or in particular cases like epilepsy, that the faculties will all

  unite and the dreamer ‘‘will behold the wonders of the world.’’72

  Before turning the discussion directly to the processes of recollection, let

  me summarize for the sake of emphasis the chief features of a memory-

  image. Most importantly, it is ‘‘affective’’ in nature – that is, it is sensorily

  derived and emotional
ly charged. It is not simply an abstraction or a

  mental ghost, despite its critical usefulness to all rational processes. Nor

  does the language of computation adequately describe what a memory was

  thought to be – it is not a mere algorithm or schema of the sort that

  accounts for what a machine does, though, as we will see, many mnemonic

  techniques function, at least in part, like algorithms. But they are never just

  that. Successful memory schemes all acknowledge the importance of

  tagging material emotionally as well as schematically, making each mem-

  ory as much as possible into a personal occasion by imprinting emotional

  associations like desire and fear, pleasure or discomfort, or the particular

  appearance of the source from which one is memorizing, whether oral

  (a teacher) or written (a manuscript page). Successful recollection requires

  that one recognize that every kind of mental representation, including those

  in memory, is in its composition sensory and emotional. Recollection

  76

  The Book of Memory

  may employ schemes, but it is like reading a book, that is, an event involving

  judgment and response (intentio) in addition to intellect. 73

  One other feature distinguishes a memory-image from every other sort.

  Aristotle says that ‘ Memory is of the past,’’ and ‘‘all memory involves time.’’74

  Because time is bound into their nature – memories are presently existing

  images of things that are past – memories differ from other sensorily pro-

  duced images, as recognition (of something present) differs from recollection

  (a matter which I discussed in Chapter 1). Their temporal nature also means

  that memory’s re-presentation is less importantly mimetic, or objectively

  reiterative of the original perception, than it is temporal, because it makes

  the past perception present. Aristotle says that we judge time-lapses and the

  relative duration of time by an imaging process similar to that by which we

  judge magnitude (449b 30ff., and 452ab), by constructing a sort of scale

  model in the mind. Aristotle spends a good deal of his brief treatise on this

  particular problem, suggesting a solution which Sorabji describes in pp. 18–21.

  What is important to later thinkers about this discussion is Aristotle’s insist-

  ence that memorial phantasmata are both representations of things (in the

  senses discussed in Chapter 1) and ‘ re-presentations’’ of experience no longer

  present. Time is a dimension of all images in the memory.

  Thus, recollection was understood to be a re-enactment of experience,

  which involves cogitation and judgment, imagination, and emotion.

  Averroe¨s and Aristotle both insist on this: ‘‘the one who recollects will

  experience the same pleasure or pain in this situation which he would

  experience were the thing existing in actuality.’’75 Memory’s success is

  heavily dependent on the recollector’s skill in being able to form memory-

  images that are ‘ rich’’ in associations, as ‘ iconic’ (to use another term from

  neuropsychology) as possible. All mnemonic advice stresses the benefits

  to be gained from forming memories as scenes that include personal

  associations. Hugh of St. Victor, for instance, stresses the need to impress

  the circumstances during which something was memorized as part of the

  associational web needed to recall it: the sort of day it is, how one feels, the

  gestures and appearance of one’s teacher, the appearance of the manuscript

  page, and so on.

  R E C O L L E C T I O N

  In his Libri rerum memorandarum (1345), Petrarch gives the following

  account of the recollective abilities of one of his friends:

  It was enough for him to have seen or heard something once, he never forgot; nor

  did he recollect only the subject [res], but the words and time and place where he

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  77

  had first learned it. Often we spent entire days or long nights in talking: there was

  no one I would rather listen to; for after the passage of many years the same things

  being spoken of, if I were to say much more or less or say something different, at

  once he would gently admonish me to correct this or that word; and when

  I wondered and inquired just how he could have known this, he recalled not only

  the time in which he would have heard it from me, but in the shade of which holm

  oak, by what riverbank, along what sea shore, on the top of what hill (for I had

  walked long distances with him along the coasts), I recognizing each particular. 76

  Striking in this account is the friend’s mnemonic use of unrelated, expe-

  riential detail to mark what we think of as objective information. Some

  contemporary psychologists are inclined to think that the memory used in

  reproducing information accurately (called ‘‘rote’’ or ‘‘semantic’’ memory)

  is unrelated to what is called ‘‘event’’ or ‘‘episodic’’ memory, our ability to

  recall events in vivid detail from our own past, because personal memories

  are subject to re-creation and inaccuracy, whereas the usefulness of rote

  memories (such as remembering that 6 7 ¼ 42) depends exactly on their

  unchangingness. But in Petrarch’s account, recollection of personal expe-

  riences is used to ensure greater accuracy of memory, an accuracy which he

  recognizes when he acknowledges that his friend, recollecting the event as a

  whole, was able to correct Petrarch’s own memory of the information –

  quotations and learning – they had exchanged. Personalizing bits of

  information helps to distinguish one bit from another, and thus is an

  aspect of the mental addressing system itself. Each memorized bit, in this

  technique, is regarded in the first instance not as information to be

  reproduced but as a personal event, with full phenomenological status.

  Accuracy comes about through the act of recreating in memory the

  complete occasion of which the accurate quotation is a part.

  The whole matter of memory error seems to be quite differently con-

  ceived by the ancients from the one that fuels modern anxieties about

  ‘‘making mistakes.’’ For us, making a mistake of memory is a failure in

  accuracy, a failure exactly to iterate the original material. In antiquity and

  the Middle Ages, problems involving memory-phantasms are described as

  heuristic (recollective) rather than as reproductive problems, and are due to

  a failure to imprint the phantasm properly in the first instance, thus

  causing confusion and recollective loss. One must be careful to form

  one’s imagines securely and distinctly in the first place, and by repetition

  and practice ensure that they are in long-term memory. One must make

  them sufficiently distinct from one another, and use a set order with a

  clearly established beginning, like ‘‘one’’ or ‘‘A.’’ One should not tire the

  memory by trying to memorize too much at a time, or too quickly, for this

  78

  The Book of Memory

  produces an over-loading problem. Forgetting is a technical error, due to

  such things as insufficient imprinting or mis-addressing, and errors of

  recollection are thus perceptual in nature, if the min
d’s ‘‘eye’’ cannot see

  clearly or looks in the wrong place. But if one’s images are clearly made,

  and if one’s routes to them through the mass of individual phantasms

  stored in memory are properly marked, and fortified through practice, one

  will safely and securely find one’s place. As Quintilian says, ‘‘however large

  the number [of items] we must remember, all are linked one to another like

  dancers hand in hand, and there can be no mistake since they join what

  precedes to what follows, no trouble being required except the preliminary

  labor of memorizing’’ (my italics).77 A common image for items associa-

  tively grouped in memory is that of catena or chain; perhaps the very

  notion of texta itself, which literally means ‘‘something woven,’’ derives

  from the same mental phenomenon. And the language that describes the

  formation of associations as ‘‘hooking’’ material to other things leads to a

  metaphor of recollecting as fishing: as one pulls up one’s line, all the fish on

  one’s hooks come with it (as painted in the border shown in figure 28).

  The idea also informs the common metaphorical extension in Latin

  of the word silva, ‘‘forest,’’ to mean a mass of unrelated and disordered

  material. Within his memorial forest, a trained student, like a knowledge-

  able huntsman, can readily find the places (loci) where the rabbits and deer

  lie. Quintilian observes that:

  just as all things do not grow in every country, and you would not find a particular

  bird or animal if you did not know its birthplace or its haunts, while even kinds of

  fish differ . . . so every Argument is not found everywhere, and we have therefore

  to be selective in our search. 78

  The spatial nature of this mental search is clearer in the Latin: ‘‘ita non

  omne argumentum undique venit ideoque non passim quaerendum est.’’

  As the huntsman finds game and the fisherman fish, so the student finds his

  stored material – by knowing its habits and habitats. Accuracy is a feature

  of the memory-image which is determined at the imprinting stage.

  Quintilian counsels having someone read aloud from a text so that one

  can check the accuracy of one’s image of it during the process of setting it in

  the memory, and to check oneself periodically by re-reading. Evidently

 

‹ Prev