The Book of Memory

Home > Other > The Book of Memory > Page 18
The Book of Memory Page 18

by Mary Carruthers


  wax tablets (cerae) or papyrus, and the arrangement of the images on them

  is like writing; subsequent delivery is like reading aloud. The backgrounds

  must be arranged in a series, a certain order, so that one cannot become

  confused in the order. One can thus proceed forwards from start to finish,

  or backwards, or start in the middle (one might recall here the artificial

  memory system described in Aristotle’s De memoria et reminiscentia, which

  also allows one to scan, sort, and move about mentally in a similar way).

  The formation of the backgrounds in the mind should be done with

  special care and precision, ‘‘so that they may cling lastingly in our memory,

  for the images, like letters, are effaced when we make use of them, but the

  backgrounds, like wax tablets, should abide’’ (III, 18, 31). One should

  practice daily seeing one’s backgrounds and placing images on them. It is

  also useful, in order to keep track of where one is, to place a mark on every

  fifth or tenth one – a golden hand, or the face of a friend named Decimus.

  In memorizing backgrounds, one should avoid crowded places, because

  too many people milling about confuse and soften their outlines.

  Background loci should be well lighted but not glaring; they must not be

  too much alike but differ enough in form to be clearly distinguishable one

  from the next; they should be of moderate size and extent, ‘‘for when

  excessively large they render the images vague, and when too small often

  seem incapable of receiving an arrangement of images’’ (III, 19, 32). (Notice

  that grouped images are placed in a scene within a single locus, serving like a

  stage; the analogy between memory art and theatre is ancient and persis-

  tent.)123 If we are not pleased with the real backgrounds available to us, we

  may create some in our imagination and ‘‘obtain a most serviceable

  distribution of appropriate backgrounds’’ (III, 19, 32).

  These backgrounds should be viewed from about thirty feet away, ‘‘for,

  like the external eye, so the inner eye of thought is less powerful when you

  have moved the object of sight too near or too far away’’ (III, 19, 32). Both

  the ‘‘auctor ad Herennium’’ and Cicero use the word intervallum in

  articulating this rule, meaning ‘‘the distance between two points.’’ I under-

  stand this word differently in the context of mnemotechnical advice from

  the way it is translated by Harry Caplan, the Loeb editor. He refers it to the

  distance between the background places themselves. Now, while one is

  advised to make these distinctive from one another in order to avoid over-

  lapping and confusion, the Ad Herennium’s author explains the need for

  the rule quoted above in terms of the viewer’s ability to see an object clearly.

  This concern also accords with an aspect of mnemonic advice from the

  Middle Ages.124 So I understand intervallum to refer to the distance of the

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  91

  viewer from the background, optimally (according to Tullius) thirty feet; it

  is thus a principle of perspective, the viewer’s stance in relation to the

  background.

  The images to be placed in these backgrounds are then described in

  detail. The principles governing their creation are consistent with ancient

  observations that recollection is achieved through association, and that

  images, especially visual ones, are more easily and permanently retained

  than abstract ideas. So we associate the materials of memory through a

  system of consciously selected visual–verbal puns or pictures, whatever will

  serve to fix the association of image with idea. One can use such a system to

  remember things (memoria rerum) or to remember ‘‘words’’ (memoria

  verborum). Remembering ‘‘things’’ means remembering subject matters,

  the main words in quotations, the chief theses of an argument, the gist of

  a story, or the like. Remembering ‘‘words’’ means exact word-for-word

  memorization, and should be reserved for an extract from the poets (III,

  19, 34) – the Ad Herennium recommends the practice for children, and for

  adults only as an exercise to sharpen memory for matters (III, 24). In each

  kind of memorizing, punning images are used to make orderly association,

  but he admits that word-for-word memorization in this fashion is cum-

  bersome and burdens the mind; exact memorizing is better served by

  repeating a passage two or three times to set it in the memory by rote

  before one begins to attach images to it (III, 21, 34).

  Much the same advice is found in Cicero’s De oratore but more briefly

  because the subject ‘‘is well known and familiar’’ (II, 87, 358).125 Visual

  images are the keenest of all and best retained by the memory; auditory

  or other perceptions are retained when attached to visual ones (II, 87, 357).

  Images are retained more easily than abstract thoughts, but they ‘‘require

  an abode,’’ for ‘‘the embodied cannot be known without a place’’

  (‘‘corpus intelligi sine loco non potest’’). 126 One needs a large number of

  loci, distinctly visible, and at moderate distances (modicis intervallis), and

  images that are ‘‘lively, sharp, and conspicuous, with the potential to

  present themselves quickly and to strike the mind.’’ Practice will form

  the necessary habits for mastery of these skills, and Cicero mentions several

  methods of forming suitable images, involving homophony, puns, rebuses,

  and the like. All this mental image-forming, he says, should be practiced

  ‘‘according to the systematic approach of a consummate painter, who keeps

  the different localities distinct from each other by employing a variety of

  shapes [modo formarum varietate locos distinguentis]’’ (II, 87, 358), a phrase

  which Rackham, the Loeb translator, observes ‘‘denotes what we call

  ‘perspective.’’’127 One should remark here Cicero’s important, though

  92

  The Book of Memory

  commonplace, comparison between the forming of images and painting;

  one should also remark that he acknowledges the importance of the view-

  er’s perspective.

  Quintilian has sometimes been regarded as skeptical of the whole idea of

  artificial memory, but, as Frances Yates observed, this reputation is not

  founded.128 He extolls memory highly – ‘‘all learning depends on memory’’

  (‘‘omnis disciplina memoria constat’’: Inst. orat., XI, ii, 1) – and believes,

  like all the authors of antiquity, that a natural memory can and should be

  cultivated by practiced techniques. It is memory which ‘‘makes available to

  us the reserve of examples, laws, rulings, sayings, and facts which the orator

  must possess in abundance and have always at his finger-tips’’; it is the

  treasury of eloquence, ‘‘thesaurus hic eloquentiae’’(XI, ii, 1).

  Quintilian’s skepticism is directed towards the image-making schemes to

  accomplish ‘ memory for words,’ such as that described in Ad Herennium.

  How, he says, can such a cumbersome method enable one to grasp a long

  series of connected words, such as the five books of the second process against

  Verres
(Cicero’s Verrine Orations)? One cannot even represent every sort of

  word by an image (for instance, conjunctions). Quintilian admits that one

  might devise a method of shorthand symbols (notae) as Metrodorus is said to

  have devised, but he himself counsels learning a long work by dividing it into

  short sections, which one then memorizes one at a time, so that by frequent

  and continuous practice one learns the words in each brief section, and then

  unites the fragments in order (XI, ii, 28). He suggests embedding cues (notae)

  to stimulate the memory, especially in passages hard to recall – these cues

  could take the form of associated images or some other method (perhaps

  numerical or other notae). He also suggests learning a passage by heart from

  the same wax tablet upon which it was originally written down, thus effecting

  a transfer from the external tablet to the tablet of memory, and counsels

  reading passages aloud once or twice over so the mind is ‘ kept on the alert by

  the voice’’ (XI, ii, 32–34). For memory work, the voice should not rise above a

  murmur, however. It also helps if another reads aloud to us so that we can

  test what we have memorized, identify hard passages, and mark them. By

  such means, he says, he has trained his own natural memory, which is not at

  all exceptional. And he ends with his famously skeptical assessment of

  reported feats of prodigious memory, such as those of Theodectes, supposed

  to be able to remember any number of verses after a single hearing: ‘‘We

  ought to believe [such a thing], however, simply because believing it gives us

  hope’ (XI, ii, 51).

  It is noteworthy that Quintilian’s reservations are directed more at

  schemes which promise accurate ‘‘memory for words’’ than at ‘‘memory

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  93

  for things.’’ This attitude is compatible with the basically ethical value

  given to memory training. Memory for words, like any merely iterative

  reproduction of items in a series, can deteriorate rather quickly into mere

  trickery, and is associated by Quintilian with sophistical rhetoric (a prej-

  udice which extends at least into the thirteenth century, as we will see in

  Chapter 4). Even the Ad Herennium commends memory for words pri-

  marily as good exercise for memory for things. Memoria ad res compels the

  recollector to actively shape up material for an occasion, whether as

  composer or viewer or reader, and thus is ethically more valuable, consis-

  tent with the moral emphasis given to rhetoric by Cicero, Quintilian

  himself, Augustine, and the traditions of monastic prayer. Especially in

  composition, memory for things is preferred to rote iteration, even when

  the speaker has accurate command of the original words. This is, of course,

  exactly the reverse of modern prejudice.

  Quintilian’s reservations concerning elaborate schemes of loci and imag-

  ines have reinforced our own modern puzzlement in the face of such an

  apparently cumbersome and odd procedure. Even Frances Yates, who

  studied these schemes so thoughtfully, confessed herself puzzled by their

  seemingly cluttered nature, especially that for memoria verborum. What

  purpose could they serve, except demonstrating ‘ vanity and ostentation in a

  man who, where memory was concerned, took more pride in his art rather

  than in his natural powers,’’ as Quintilian says of Metrodorus (XI, ii, 22).

  Quintilian’s criticism of the Greeks (and one should note that all the

  people whose extravagant claims he criticizes are non-Romans, though

  similar claims, as we know from Pliny, were current concerning the

  prodigious memories of Julius Caesar) is likely to have been in part a

  Ciceronian pose, that of the practical, sparely educated Roman. This is

  the persona adopted in De oratore by both Crassus and Antonius, the

  heroes of the dialogue, both men highly learned in Greek but affecting to

  despise ‘‘Greeklings.’’ ‘‘Crassus,’’ Cicero says, ‘‘did not so much wish to be

  thought to have learned nothing, as to have the reputation of looking down

  upon learning, . . . while Antonius held that his speeches would be the

  more acceptable to a nation like ours, if it were thought that he had never

  engaged in study at all’’ (De orat., II, 5). Quintilian, we recall, was modeling

  himself upon Cicero’s example, against excesses of artifice and style that he

  detected in Seneca and Tacitus. Though this literary context may help to

  explain Quintilian’s skeptical pose regarding the Greeks, it does not help to

  ease our modern skepticism concerning how the system of backgrounds

  and images could work for many people, as it evidently did, being ‘‘well

  known and familiar’’ to Cicero’s audience.

  94

  The Book of Memory

  A remarkable demonstration of how it might work has come recently

  in psychological literature. The distinguished Soviet neuropsychologist,

  A. R. Luria, published a lengthy case-study (The Mind of a Mnemonist) of a

  Russian journalist of prodigious memory, who became a professional

  ‘‘mnemonist’’ or performing memory-artist. Luria studied him over a

  thirty-year period, from the 1920s through the 1950s, testing him frequently

  and asking him in detail about the systems he had worked out for retention

  and recall. The system used by Shereshevski, the subject (whom Luria refers

  to as ‘‘S.’’ in his study), was almost exactly that of the ancient architectural

  mnemonic, based upon ‘‘places’’ and ‘‘images,’’ although he was entirely

  self-taught in memory arts. Luria himself seems unaware of the ancient

  system; at least he does not mention it. Moreover, Luria refers to an

  account of a Japanese mnemonist, who had also worked out a system of

  ‘‘placing’’ images very similar to that of S.129 The study of S. gives valuable

  insight into the praxis of the ancient system.

  Luria observes first that everything S. recalled was in the form of words

  (including numbers, nonsense syllables, and seen or described objects) and

  that he responded to hearing words by at once converting them into vivid

  and remarkably stable visual images. He did this on a word-by-word basis,

  so that to recall a long series of words he needed to find a way of

  distributing his mental images in an orderly row or sequence. He seems

  most often to have used a street which he visualized in precise detail in his

  memory, often a street in the town he grew up in but also streets in

  Moscow, where he then lived – Gorky Street served him often. As Luria

  describes the process: ‘‘Frequently he would take a mental walk along that

  street . . . beginning at Mayakovsky Square, and slowly make his way down,

  ‘distributing’ his images at houses, gates, and store windows. At times,

  without realizing how it had happened, he would suddenly find himself

  back in his home town . . . where he would wind up his trip in the house he

  had lived in as a child’’ (p. 32). This technique enabled S. to reproduce at

  will a series from start to finish, or in reverse order, or from any point. He

  could also tell at once, given one word in a series, which word
occurred on

  either side of it, its ‘‘neighbors,’’ so to speak (we recall Aristotle’s similar

  description of this recollective phenomenon in De memoria).

  His recollection of these visual images was so stable that when asked to

  recall passages or series he had memorized even years earlier he could do so

  promptly and accurately. Luria and his associates concluded quickly that

  S.’s memory was essentially limitless and gave up trying to measure its

  capacity. The key to this capacity was the stability of his images and places.

  As Luria concludes, ‘‘the astonishing clarity and tenacity of his images, the

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  95

  fact that he could retain them for years and call them up when occasion

  demanded it, made it possible for him to recall an unlimited number of

  words and to retain these indefinitely.’’130

  Nonetheless, S. did occasionally make errors. Luria determined, how-

  ever, that these were not errors caused by loss but errors of perception. In

  revisiting his places, S. sometimes failed to notice or saw badly an image

  which he had placed in a poor location. As S. described these errors to

  Luria:

  I put the image of the pencil near a fence . . . the one down the street, you know.

  But what happened was that the image fused with that of the fence and I walked

  right on past without noticing it. The same thing happened with the word egg.

  I had put it against a white wall and it blended in with the background . . .

  Sometimes I put a word in a dark place and have trouble seeing it as I go by. (36)

  His solution to the problem was as follows:

  What I do now is to make my images larger. Take the word egg I told you about

  before. It was so easy to lose sight of it; now I make it a larger image, and when

  I lean it up against the wall of a building, I see to it that the place is lit by having a

  street lamp nearby . . . I don’t put things in dark passageways any more . . . Much

  better if there’s some light around, it’s easier to spot then. (41)

  Crowds and noise confused him (37) because they interfered with his

  ability to perceive his images and places, and stray noise confused his

  concentration. S. described his problem: ‘‘You see, every sound troubles

  me . . . it’s transformed into a line and becomes confusing. Once I had the

 

‹ Prev