The Book of Memory

Home > Other > The Book of Memory > Page 32
The Book of Memory Page 32

by Mary Carruthers


  questions address either insufficient definition in Tullius (e.g. objection 10)

  or apparent contradictions between what is found in Ad Herennium and

  in Aristotle (e.g. objections 3 and 7) or in Aristotelian psychology, as

  already commented upon by Albertus in his own treatise on the soul

  (e.g. objections 2 and 13). He also addresses those hostile to the whole

  scheme as being altogether too curious and elaborate. Such hostility did in

  fact exist among previous generations of Parisian masters, as we will see.

  Albertus is much interested in the ancient system’s use of vivid visual

  images against precisely visualized backgrounds set in order; it is this

  feature that makes Tullius’ system the best. He is obviously working with

  Tullius’ text, trying to adapt it to thirteenth-century circumstances and the

  memory training with which he is familiar; the results are instructive. He

  considers, for example, what the phrase ‘‘aut natura aut manu’’ means (Ad

  Her. III.16.29), since Tullius doesn’t clearly define it, and suggests (prob-

  ably correctly) that it refers to kinds of loci, the cloister-garth (pratum)

  being an example of a natural place, a house or an intercolumnar space of

  an artificial one (‘‘made by hand,’’ manu; see resp. 10).

  Judging by his comments on the five principal characteristics given

  for desirable background images, Albertus clearly understands that they

  are designed for ease in perception as one walks through one’s places

  in memory, seeing images on backgrounds. ‘‘Confusion,’’ he writes, ‘‘is

  engendered either in respect to the background-place or the matters located

  in it or to that which by its action makes visible the background and what is

  in it.’’26 If one crowds too much into one location, one will confound one’s

  images: ‘‘it heaps up a great many images, and so these images break up in

  the soul and do not remain, just as a great number of waves break up in

  water.’’27 This effect, however, is not what the Ad Herennium gives as the

  reason to avoid crowds; the concern there was with the initial making of

  backgrounds, and to avoid imprinting crowded places because of their

  adverse effect on the clarity of the backgrounds.

  One can also be confused if one’s places are too much alike, too close

  together or far apart, or improperly lit. Images must be seen clearly, for

  ‘‘something glaring confounds sight’’ whereas obscurity impedes it; in

  either case the images are not properly imprinted and therefore cannot

  be seen with the inner eye. Following these general guidelines, each person

  can form his own places from diverse sources. A comparison of the sources

  enumerated by Albertus with those in the Ad Herennium again indicates

  that Albertus had adapted his source. Tullius mentions these specific

  174

  The Book of Memory

  examples: aedis (a house), intercolumnium (the space between columns, a

  colonnade), angulus (a recess), fornix (an arch), all clearly Roman archi-

  tectural items. Albertus’s examples are equally clearly medieval: templum

  (a church), intercolumnium, pratum (cloister-garth), hospitalis (hospice or

  hospital). The only shared word is intercolumnium, though Albertus surely

  had a different sort of columned space in mind (perhaps a cloister or a

  columned church interior) than did the author of Ad Herennium. In fact,

  intercolumnium is the only specific kind of location in the architectural

  mnemonic that has an unbroken history – perhaps this is due to the

  continuing use of columns to mark off memory groups in the various tabular

  formats, such as the Canon Tables. These columnar formats feature images

  of architectural columns, often joined by arches, to frame the textual material.

  Albertus’s account of the Ad Herennium’s advice concerning image-

  making shows his fascination with the procedural details of this system.

  He gives first a complete account of the technique for creating images-

  for-things. He uses the examples given in the Ad Herennium, but it is clear

  that not all of its details are familiar to him:

  we place in our memory ‘‘a sick man in bed, who is a figure of the deceased, and

  we place the defendant standing by the bed, holding in his right hand a cup, in

  his left hand tablets, and a physician standing upright holding the testicles of

  a ram,’’ so that certainly in the cup should be the memory-cue of the poison

  which he drank, and in the tablets should be the memory-cue of the will which he

  signed, and in the physician may be figured the accusor and by the testicles the

  witnesses and accessories, and by the ram the defense against matter being

  adjudicated.28

  Albertus’s attempts to comprehend this scene show his editorial efforts to

  understand the Latin of a culture far outside his experience. Most notable is

  his change of the original ‘‘medico testiculos arietinos tenentem’’ to ‘‘med-

  icum astantem tenentem testiculos arietinos.’’ In the original text, the

  defendant and the sick man are the only two human figures in this scene,

  the defendant holding cup, tablets, and on his fourth finger (medicum, used

  in the ablative singular, is an abbreviated noun-form of the phrase digitus

  medicinalis) the ram’s testicles (in ancient Rome money bags could be

  made from the skin of ram’s testicles). 29 Albertus adds a third figure to this

  scene, a physician (medicus, used in the accusative singular) who is standing

  also by the bed, and he holds the ram’s testicles. And why a ram? Since they

  are noted for their territorial defensiveness, the ram can signify the pro-

  ceeding against the defendant. What is clear from this ingenious adaptation

  is Albertus’s effort to visualize a similitudo rerum. His particular misunder-

  standing here proves precisely his understanding of the general method.

  The arts of memory

  175

  But a more taxing passage awaited him, the description of the technique

  of similitudines verborum for memory of words, using as its example the

  line, apparently cited from a popular Roman play, ‘‘Iam domum itionem

  reges Atridae parant,’’ ‘‘Now for their journey home the kings, sons of

  Atreus, prepare.’’ Every commentator on the Ad Herennium has floundered

  about here. A major portion of the difficulty is attributable to the fact that

  the images which the Ad Herennium suggests one use to remember these

  Latin words are visual puns which depend entirely on contemporary

  allusions – a reference to two celebrated Roman families, in one instance,

  and to two well-known contemporary actors in the other. To remember

  the first half-line one thinks of Domitius ‘‘raising hands to heaven while he

  is whipped with thongs by the Marcii Reges’’ (‘‘iam domum itionem

  reges’’), both Domitius and Rex being names of distinguished Roman

  families. Caplan, the Loeb translator, comments that the scene ‘‘is doubt-

  less our author’s own creation,’’ and it is difficult to understand why it

  involves whipping, except as an instance of the general principle of forming

  images related to one another through violent activity. The second half-line

&n
bsp; is recalled by a scene of the two famous actors, Aesop and Cimber, making

  ready for their roles as Agamemnon and Menelaus in a play about the trials

  of Iphigenia (‘‘Atridae parant’’).

  Albertus’s attempt to deal with this passage was complicated by an

  incorrect manuscript reading, one he apparently selected over the more

  correct one, for both versions were known to him. For domum itionem,

  ‘‘journey home,’’ his version read domi ultionem, ‘‘revenge at home.’’ So in

  Albertus’s account (see Appendix B) somebody named Domitius is being

  whipped (in revenge for something) by martial (that is, ‘‘warlike’’) kings.

  Then, having made a certain sense of the scene in the first memory

  location, he makes a hash of the one in the second. The original text

  advises that to remember the phrase ‘‘Atridae parant,’’ one should imagine

  two well-known actors, Aesop and Cimber, preparing for their roles as

  Menelaus and Agamemnon (‘‘the sons of Atreus’’) in a play about

  Iphigenia. Here again Albertus was not helped by his chosen manuscript

  (one of the so-called ‘‘E recension’’), which left out the explanation in the

  original text (see Ad Her. III.21.34) that the two named figures were actors

  preparing for their roles in a play.30 Besides leaving this information out,

  Albertus’s version had also added the adjective vagantem, ‘‘wandering,’’ as

  an adjective modifying the name, Iphigenia. So what Albertus found in his

  manuscript was a reference to two people named Aesop and Cimber who

  either prepared Iphigenia for wandering, or incited her to wander. Albertus

  tried to make a mnemonic association by linking the notion of ‘‘preparing’’

  176

  The Book of Memory

  with that of ‘‘wandering,’’ for, as he observes, one who prepares (parat se)

  for something wanders about.

  Those who have also struggled with obscurities in ancient texts cannot

  help admiring Albertus for plunging into this crux instead of silently

  reporting it, though in this case discretion might have served him better.

  The nature of his effort indicates again his grasp of the essential features of

  the method and purpose of image-making, if not of this particular example

  of it. He raises these two specific instances of image-making from Ad

  Herennium as the basis for others’ objection to the whole method (objec-

  tion 10), on the grounds that it is is metaphorical and obscure, and there-

  fore a hindrance rather than a help to memory. Better to remember the

  things themselves (the actual words of a text) than to adopt this cumber-

  some, confusing method.

  Albertus defends the method with vigor precisely because it is meta-

  phorical, grounds that must be of interest to students of medieval fictional

  literature. He quotes almost in full the advice of Ad Herennium on the

  making of striking and unusual images, and replies at length to possible

  objections (objs. and resps. 16–21). The images one composes must be

  striking and vivid, rare and unusual, ‘‘quae quasi mirabiles sunt, imagines

  nobis constituamus’’ (obj. 20). What is unusual and marvelous strikes us

  and is retained in the memory more than what is ordinary (‘‘mirabile plus

  movet quam consuetum’’); moreover, what is marvellous, by its forceful

  impression on us, causes us to remark it, and that engenders both inquiry

  and reminiscence. For this purpose, fabulous metaphorical images, com-

  posed from marvels (‘‘compositae ex miris’’) are best: ‘‘metaphorica plus

  movent animam et ideo plus conferunt memoriae.’’ For as Aristotle says (in

  Metaphysics, I.1, where he also says that experience is made of many

  memories), this was why the earliest philosophers wrote their ideas down

  in poetry, because fables composed of marvels were more moving to the

  memory and to inquiry (‘‘fabula, cum sit composita ex miris, plus movet’’).

  All inquiry begins in wonder (‘‘ex admirari’’), he continues, quoting the

  Metaphysics again (I.2), for the start of philosophical thought is in wonder-

  ing about causes, about befores and afters and whys. Though he does not

  explicitly invoke it, Albertus clearly makes an etymological connection

  between miris and admirari, and thus a relationship of some compatibility

  between fabula and philosophari – the link between them being through the

  requirements of inventive memory.

  Some of his work shows Albertus’s use of a technique of composing vivid

  visual images, which incorporate the principle of being marvellous and

  active. Familiarity from memory training with the technique of vigorous

  The arts of memory

  177

  image-making, even in the context of theological debate (where it becomes

  a useful tool for keeping any sort of discourse in mind), provided a

  scholarly audience with a habit of encountering such imagery even in the

  context of commentary and treatise, without finding it inappropriate. And

  Albertus’s stress upon the mnemonic usefulness of what is marvellous and

  unusual gives a crucial ethical justification for using even fantastical or

  salacious or violent images. Albertus makes it clear that the criterion for

  creating mnemonic images is not decorum but utility. Because the memory

  is physiologically constituted in such a way that it better retains what is

  unusual and emotionally charged rather than what is expected or routine,

  material must be marked with those sorts of images. Students of literature

  have always remarked the penchant for strikingly peculiar allegory in many

  of the pre-modern arts. But it may well be that some of what we suppose to

  be allegory, and thus to have a specifically iconographic meaning (if only

  we knew what it was), is simply a mnemonic heuristic. 31

  Albertus’s Postilla in Isaiam (commentary on Isaiah), of which a reliable

  modern edition exists, affords several interesting examples of Albertine

  imagination. First, as is also true of Aquinas’s work, quotations from pagan

  authors, including the poets, are much in evidence. In this commentary, he

  quotes from Cicero twenty-three times, most frequently from De inven-

  tione; he also quotes ‘‘Homer,’’ Horace (five times), Ovid (seven times),

  Martial, Vitruvius, and Virgil, among several others. Moralized stories of

  the pagan gods, including Jupiter, Priapus, Venus, and the jackal-god

  Anubis, also find their way into his commentary. Frequently these tales

  are used to point the Augustinian moral that the pagan gods were no better

  than devils, corrupt; indeed one of Albertus’s richest sources is The City of

  God. Another is evidently from some sort of early version of Ovide moral-

  iseé, so popular later in the century and into the following one.

  Commenting on the phrase ‘‘in auribus meis’’ (Is. 5:9), Albertus says:

  Wherefore in the fables of the poets in Ovid [Met. II, v, 47ff.] great Jupiter, who

  represents the god of gods, when he needed to strike down Phaeton, who was

  burning up the sky and earth and all therein, took up his javelin beside his ear, that

  he might clearly teach that it is judicious first carefully to listen and weigh the

  merits of t
he persons and their causes, and then to smite the killers. 32

  But not all of Albertus’s vivid visual images are so self-evidently literary in

  character. For example, commenting on Is. 35:6, ‘‘Then shall the lame man

  leap as an hart,’’ Albertus moralizes the verse with an unusual image rather

  like the ‘‘curious, emblem-like ‘pictures’’’ found by Beryl Smalley in

  Holcot’s Moralitas.33 ‘‘The soul,’’ Albertus says, ‘‘has two feet, that is

  178

  The Book of Memory

  intellect and emotions. When they are equal, and emotion is made equal in

  truth to the intellect, then a man walks well. If however one or the other is

  bent, the intellect through error or emotion through desire, a man is

  lame.’’34

  Two other examples are also curious. In commentary on Is. 47:2,

  Albertus writes of the phrase revela crura, ‘‘make bare the thigh,’’ that it

  is a custom of prostitutes to reveal their legs in order to incite desire.

  ‘‘Wherefore Venus was painted with her skirt raised to reveal her leg that

  she might provoke lust.’’35 Smalley discovered this passage, and comments

  on it that its source is not in any pictorial tradition for ‘‘the mythographers

  all represent Venus as naked . . . Curious and of an observant turn of mind,

  [Albertus] may have seen or read some study of her wearing a dress. Maybe

  he simply invented her as a personification of harlotry.’’

  Then there is the ram which runs amok in the middle of Albertus’s

  commentary on Aristotle’s De memoria, composed between 1254 and 1257,

  when Albertus had left his teaching career in Paris for an administrative

  one in Cologne. Invoking the Ad Herennium on the making of memory-

  images as a practical instance of Aristotle’s understanding of how memory

  works by association, he comments on the phrase ‘‘testiculos arietinos’’

  (Ad Her. III.20.34). Frances Yates translates the passage as follows:

  For example, if we wish to record what is brought against us in a law-suit, we

  should imagine some ram, with huge horns and testicles, coming towards us in the

  darkness. The horns will bring to memory our adversaries and testicles the

  dispositions of the witnesses. 36

  Yates wonders wittily whence such a vigorous beast could appear: ‘‘How has it

 

‹ Prev