The Trace of God

Home > Other > The Trace of God > Page 1
The Trace of God Page 1

by Baring, Edward; Gordon, Peter E. ;




  The Trace of God

  Series Board

  James Bernauer

  Drucilla Cornell

  Thomas R. Flynn

  Kevin Hart

  Richard Kearney

  Jean-Luc Marion

  Adriaan Peperzak

  Thomas Sheehan

  Hent de Vries

  Merold Westphal

  Michael Zimmerman

  John D. Caputo, series editor

  Copyright © 2015 Fordham University Press

  All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means—electronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or any other—except for brief quotations in printed reviews, without the prior permission of the publisher.

  Fordham University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party Internet websites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.

  Fordham University Press also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books.

  Visit us online at www.fordhampress.com.

  Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

  The trace of God : Derrida and religion / edited by Edward Baring and Peter E. Gordon. — First edition.

  pages cm. — (Perspectives in Continental philosophy)

  Includes bibliographical references and index.

  ISBN 978-0-8232-6209-0 (cloth : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-0-8232-6210-6 (pbk. : alk. paper)

  1. Derrida, Jacques. 2. Religion. I. Baring, Edward, 1980– editor.

  B2430.D484T73 2015

  194—dc23

  2014008413

  Printed in the United States of America

  17 16 15 5 4 3 2 1

  First edition

  Contents

  Introduction

  “Et Iterum de Deo”: Jacques Derrida and the Tradition of Divine Names

  Hent de Vries

  Not Yet Marrano: Levinas, Derrida, and the Ontology of Being Jewish

  Ethan Kleinberg

  Poetics of the Broken Tablet

  Sarah Hammerschlag

  Theism and Atheism at Play: Jacques Derrida and Christian Heideggerianism

  Edward Baring

  Called to Bear Witness: Derrida, Muslims, and Islam

  Anne Norton

  Habermas, Derrida, and the Question of Religion

  Peter E. Gordon

  Abraham, the Settling Foreigner

  Joseph Cohen and Raphael Zagury-Orly

  Unprotected Religion: Radical Theology, Radical Atheism, and the Return of Anti-Religion

  John D. Caputo

  The Autoimmunity of Religion

  Martin Hägglund

  Derrida and Messianic Atheism

  Richard Kearney

  Notes

  List of Contributors

  Index

  The Trace of God

  for Helen Tartar, in memoriam

  Introduction

  For over a quarter of a century, scholars have been interested in a set of questions broadly grouped under the heading “Derrida and Religion.” Since the 1980s, when Derrida began to apply deconstructive insights directly to questions of faith and religion, the provocation of this engagement has remained of major concern across the humanities.1 For this reason, it would be wrong to consider the question of Derrida and religion simply as a partial look at an important thinker, similar to, say, Hegel and aesthetics or Hume and politics, where research is limited to the overlap between the two: the conjunction in the phrase “Derrida and Religion” is not the compound limitation of the Boolean AND. Rather, as we shall see over the course of the volume, one of the merits of studying Derrida’s engagement with religion is that it brings to the fore several central debates over the meaning of his work, as well as offering new insights into political and theoretical issues that extend well beyond the boundaries inside which religious questions are often confined.2

  The greater share of the papers assembled in this volume were first presented, albeit in abbreviated form, at a conference on Derrida and religion that convened at Harvard University in March 2010.3 The passage of time provided us opportunities to invite other scholars to contribute, and the fruits of our editorial labor are now assembled here in published form. The richness of the topic demands a number of perspectives. For this reason in this volume we bring together established voices in the field—like John Caputo, Hent de Vries, and Richard Kearney—along with younger scholars whose work has begun to make its impact felt. Moreover, we have gathered contributions from a range of different academic fields: religious studies, philosophy, literature, political theory, and history. Forming the core of this collection is a set of investigations about the ways in which Derrida drew upon and worked over resources from a number of religious traditions. The essays ask how Derrida situated his writings within broader debates about religion, how ideas and concepts from Judaism, Christianity, Islam, and atheism function in Derrida’s texts. But this should not be seen as an attempt to find an “origin” for deconstruction or to settle some putative debate about Derrida’s beliefs. As we will try to show over the course of the Introduction, the question of “Derrida and Religion” is complex in its indeterminacy, resisting easy answers to questions such as whether Derrida harbored any personal commitments of faith, whether he even believed in God, and the no less vexed questions concerning the status of his own identification, practical, institutional, or existential, with Judaism.

  Derrida was born to a Sephardic Jewish family in the French colony of Algeria in 1930. He attended secondary school in Algiers, but to fulfill his ambition of being a writer, he responded to the call of the French metropolis. Derrida moved to France in 1949 to attend the Parisian Lycée Louis-le-Grand, and from there the École normale supérieure (ENS), an institute for higher learning in the Latin Quarter that has trained a large majority of the most important French philosophers, historians, and mathematicians, among others, over the last two centuries.

  After passing the agrégation in philosophy (a state exam qualifying lycée teachers) in 1956, Derrida deferred his obligatory military service and traveled to America to spend a year studying at Harvard, during which time he married Marguerite Aucouturier, the sister of a fellow Normalien. Return from America marked the beginning of his military duties and he spent two years teaching in a military school in Koléa, Algeria. Once this service was over, Derrida accepted first a lycée post in Le Mans, then a year later a position at the Sorbonne. He taught at the Sorbonne as an assistant under Paul Ricoeur, Suzanne Bachelard, and Jean Wahl until 1964, when he was offered the post of agrégé-répétiteur at the ENS, which served as his base for the next twenty years.

  Derrida was propelled into the intellectual limelight in the annus mirabilis of 1967, when he published three books: Voice and Phenomenon, Writing and Difference, and Of Grammatology. It was this final text that made Derrida’s name, associating him with the dominant structuralism of the time, while introducing readers to a new and powerful way of reading texts: what Derrida called “deconstruction.” His prominence in France brought him renown in America. Derrida’s introduction to American academia was facilitated by his last minute addition to the 1966 Johns Hopkins structuralism conference that had as its major goal the promotion of French ideas in the United States. Over the next forty years, in addition to his positions in France—at the ENS and then, after 1984, the École des hautes études en sciences sociales (EHESS)—Derrida held a number of visiting appointments in American universities. His presence especially at Johns Hopkins,
Yale, and later at UC Irvine, along with a growing group of scholars who drew on his work at these and other institutions, allowed the emergence of deconstruction as a significant school in American literary studies.4

  The success of Derrida’s writings in the English-speaking world elicited a backlash in the 1980s and ’90s. Many criticized him for the obscurity of his writing and his seeming failure to follow the traditional rules of academic endeavor. Moreover, several worried that his philosophy was nihilistic, stymied political action, and encouraged quietism. Most famously, several prominent academics initiated a campaign to refuse Derrida an honorary degree at Cambridge University in 1992, which even as it was unable to achieve its immediate goal served as a rallying point for those who feared the impact of Derrida’s ideas on academic study.

  At about the time these criticisms gained prominence, Derrida’s thought seemed to undergo a change, a change that, moreover, provided considerable counterevidence to those criticisms. Though the existence of “political,” “ethical,” and “religious” turns in Derrida’s writing has been called into question, not least in this volume, in the last two decades of his life Derrida did address contemporary issues with greater directness, a development that helped make Derrida’s work appealing to scholars in a number of disciplines beyond the literature departments where he had previously found most support.5 By the time of his death from pancreatic cancer in 2004, Derrida’s influence was noteworthy and widespread, reaching into legal studies, architecture, gender and race theory, political science, history, and religious studies, to name but a few.

  Derrida’s work became influential in a number of different academic disciplines chiefly because his philosophy unlocked new and productive strategies for reading texts. Right from his first published essays up until his last books, Derrida dedicated most of his writing to the close study of the texts of other thinkers: philosophers, playwrights, novelists, social theorists, and theologians, mostly from the Western tradition. Deconstruction is in this way disciplinarily nomadic. Engaging with this archive, Derrida hoped to uncover moments where texts seemed to transgress their own self-imposed limits. For instance, while Husserl had wanted to develop a “philosophy of presence,” Derrida sought out those moments in Husserl’s works where he was led to rely on an idea of absence.6 Though Marx promulgated a materialist philosophy, Derrida drew attention to the moments in Marx’s thought where he was compelled to draw on ghostly metaphors.7

  In highlighting such moments of aporia, Derrida did not want to show up the frailties of some of the world’s most important philosophers. Rather, it was his contention that these moments demonstrated the rigor of their thinking; here they followed the logic of their arguments even as it contradicted their deepest-held commitments. Further, these small cracks in their putatively coherent philosophical systems spoke against the possibility of such coherence and thus showed the limitations of the philosophical project as traditionally understood.

  In his most famous deconstruction, from Of Grammatology, Derrida extended this critique to the entire Western metaphysical tradition. Despite the multitude of different philosophical schools, Derrida argued that European philosophy was unified by the privilege it granted the spoken voice over the written word.8 This, Derrida claimed, pointed toward the deepest presuppositions of the tradition. According to Derrida, the philosophical tradition cleaved to a “logocentric” understanding of the relation between speech and writing: speech was extolled as the phenomenon of immediacy and purified “presence,” while writing was condemned or merely tolerated as derivative, a supplement to the pure event of spoken meaning. Whereas the voice was supposed to have a direct intentional connection to what it signified, writing was the “sign of a sign,” the written word signifying the spoken one; it enjoyed only a mediated relationship to the signified object.

  Despite this asserted priority of the spoken over the written word, Derrida sought to bring attention to several moments in the history of philosophy when scholars had to appeal to metaphors of writing to explain even speech, metaphors that belied their attempts to present writing as derivative. Such moments suggested to Derrida that the instability and assumed secondarity of writing—produced by what he called “différance”—served as a better model for thinking than speech. Moreover, the movement of différance challenged any claims of absolute priority or any absolute foundation for philosophy. For this reason the recognition in literature of the power and limitations of metaphor, and its refusal to make definitive claims about the world, was more justifiable than the constant yearning of the philosopher to get at the world as it really is; hence the famous “deconstruction of literature and philosophy.”

  “A Determined Moment in the Total Movement of the Trace”

  An overview of the connections and meeting points between Derrida’s work and religion would be impossible in such a short introduction, even more so in view of Derrida’s explicit engagement in his later life with the Western religious tradition, including texts by Kierkegaard, Saint Augustine, and Meister Eckhart. In the following few pages, we will merely present a brief overview of those strands in Derrida’s thought that have made this topic so pressing and so complex.

  In the classic formulations of deconstruction, Derrida seemed to oppose religion unilaterally. Derrida argued in Of Grammatology that the precedence of the voice, even in secular philosophy, was dependent upon the idea of an “infinite understanding” that could reach the signified immediately and declare it to be a stable reality, independent of the structures (and complications) of language.9 In this way, “the époque of the sign,” Derrida assured us, was “essentially theological.”10 Conversely, in one of his first elaborations of grammatology, Derrida urged a type of writing freed from the constraints of “metaphysics and theology.” As Derrida noted in an early interview, différance “blocks every relationship to theology.”11 A central injunction of Derrida’s thought (if there is such a thing) might be that we must free ourselves from the grip of the infinite, especially in its most canonical formulation: the God of much religious philosophy.

  Furthermore, we can only claim to achieve an absolute ground, or assert the theological, to the extent that we are able to deny or efface the movement of différance. But since the movement of différance—or as Derrida sometimes said, the “trace”—is this effacing, the theological could no longer be thought of as an ultimate foundation. In a phrase that has achieved considerable currency in this collection as in others, Derrida stated that the theological was a “determined moment in the total movement of the trace.”12 Such claims have lent considerable support to the assumption that Derrida partook in a Nietzschean and antireligious tradition whose goal was the overthrowing of all religious belief.13

  “Passing As an Atheist”

  The presentation of Derrida’s work as antithetical to religious thinking gains support from Derrida’s most direct response to the religion question: he wrote in 1991 that he “rightly passed for an atheist.”14 But the words “rightly” and “pass” seem to pull in different directions, and the phrase gains its potency from its refusal to give a simple answer. The ambiguity in Derrida’s statement can be heightened if we recall that an atheistic strand is interwoven into much of the religious tradition. Across its history, religious thinkers have concerned themselves with rejecting rival assertions of the divine, at times even more assiduously than denials of it. Indeed, at least to its victims, iconoclasm is often indistinguishable from atheism. For some, Derrida’s thought seems to resemble this religious “atheism” more closely than the secular variant. His broader philosophical targets are reminiscent of the traditional antipodes of much religious thought, including humanism, which many religious philosophers see as Man’s attempt to take the place of God, and human philosophical certainty, which has been criticized by those arguing for human humility in the face of the divine at least since Pascal. This aspect of Derrida’s thought first attracted religious scholars in the early 1980s, including the “Death of G
od” theologian Thomas Altizer and the religious studies scholar Mark Taylor.15

  More particularly, and especially during the early part of his reception, religious scholars observed that the strategies of Derrida’s readings often seem to repeat, perhaps even mimic, those of the apophatic tradition, or negative theology.16 Such a comparison suggested itself, in part, because of the ways in which Derrida emphasized the constant failure of language to secure stable meaning. Just as all images of the divine might be declared inadequate, Derrida’s thought highlighted the difficulty and incompletion of any intentional relation between a word and its object. Meaning constantly threatened to slip away. Parallels to negative theology can also be seen in Derrida’s treatment of this slippage itself. Derrida declared early on that différance was “neither a word nor a concept,” and his attempt to refuse the hypostatization of différance by appealing to an open-ended list of non-synonymous substitutions—trace, pharmakon, supplement, hymen, etc.—resembled the representative modes of that tradition.17 For many religious scholars, Derrida’s thought thus can be read, like negative theology, as a reaction against dogmatic forms of the divine and for them it opens up the intriguing possibility of a phenomenon that John Caputo has called “a religion without religion.”18 But this reading of Derrida’s thought has also drawn the attention of critics, like John Milbank, who see in the relentless attack on determined religious forms only a liability in deconstruction.19

  The interpretation of deconstruction as a renewal or postmodern reprise of negative theology runs up against a second difficulty. Derrida seemed to dispense with the very element that has traditionally separated the religious rejection of idolatry from the atheist rejection of God. In the religious tradition, the smashing of idols was often performed in the name of a “true” God.20 False idols were swept away because they did not live up to the divine. But one of the defining features of deconstruction has been its resistance to such a structuring antithesis of the genuine and the false, the divine and the merely idolatrous. The goal of grammatology is to redeem writing from the secondary status to which it had always been relegated and, more precisely, to complicate the categories of the “fallen,” the “derivative,” and so forth. In Voice and Phenomenon Derrida criticized Husserl for maintaining the structuring ideal of pure presence, against which all forms of indication are found wanting, even if he was never able to achieve that presence in his phenomenology.21 Similarly, in his famous text “Structure, Sign, and Play in the Human Sciences,” Derrida did not criticize Lévi-Strauss because he asserted the certainty of science, but rather because, while recognizing the impossibility of such certainty, he continued to measure the failings of actually existing science by it. Deconstructive readings often draw attention to the tension inherent in maintaining the teleological power of a principle whose possibility we refuse.22

 

‹ Prev