Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 9
Revolution and the Republic Page 9

by Jeremy Jennings


  arrive somewhere, he must always remember that one walks on the ground and that he

  no longer inhabits an ideal world.44

  Before the National Assembly in August this same logic was deployed to demon-

  strate the impossibility of formulating a declaration of the rights of man capable of

  application to all political associations and all forms of government when those

  responsible were necessarily constrained by ‘local circumstances’ and which, ‘given

  a people grown old amongst anti-social institutions’, would attain nothing more

  than ‘relative perfection’. Speaking on behalf of the comité des cinq Mirabeau

  indicated, for example, that in their endeavour to formulate a declaration of rights

  they had experienced great difficulty ‘in distinguishing between what belonged to

  the nature of man and the modifications it had received in this or that particular

  society’.45

  Mirabeau’s own solution to what he perceived as the dangers implicit in any

  declaration of rights was to argue that in these circumstances wisdom consisted in

  the recognition of the virtues of a juste milieu. Others showed themselves to be

  less sanguine when faced with the possibility (and the reality) of social chaos and

  anarchy. During August 1789 the most resolute opponent within the National

  Assembly of a declaration of rights proved to be Pierre-Victor Malouet. His

  argument, in summary, was that, if in America the morals, tastes, and circum-

  stances of the new nation were conducive to the existence of democracy and liberty,

  this was far from the case in France, where there existed ‘a vast multitude of men

  without property’ who, with good reason, at times became enflamed by ‘the

  spectacle of luxury and opulence’. While such inequality might be regrettable

  it nevertheless remained the case that those in a ‘dependent condition’ had to

  recognize the ‘legitimate limits’ to their ‘natural liberty’. As such, there was no

  purpose in telling ‘men deprived of understanding and means’ that they were ‘equal

  in rights to the most powerful, to the most fortunate’. ‘Why’, Malouet proclaimed,

  ‘begin by transporting [man] to a high mountain in order to show him his limitless

  dominion when upon descending he will find constraints at every step?’ The end

  result would only be disaster.46

  One dimension of this argument was that, if man had rights, as a member of

  society he also had duties and obligations. The fear, voiced explicitly by the Comte

  de Sinety, was that by talking only about rights men would be encouraged to

  44 Œuvres de Mirabeau: Discours et Opinions (1835), i. 103.

  45 Archives parlementaires, 8 (1875), 438–9, 453–5.

  46 ‘Opinion de M. Malouet sur la Déclaration des droits de l’homme’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations,

  161–4. For Malouet’s account of this turbulent period see Mémoires de Malouet (1868), i. 309–43.

  38

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  display their ‘natural leaning’ towards egoism, to the detriment of their fellows and

  of society as a whole. This ‘destructive vice’, in Sinety’s view, could be overcome if

  any declaration of the rights of man was in turn accompanied by a statement of the

  duties of the citizen.47 It was this contention that was supported by the Abbé

  Grégoire and others in a stormy debate that took place on 4 August, with Grégoire

  arguing that, when France was experiencing ‘a moment of insurrection’ by a people

  for long ‘tormented by tyranny’, it was necessary that man should know ‘not only

  the circle that he can traverse but also the barrier that he cannot cross’.48 On this

  occasion, the motion to place duties by the side of rights was defeated by 570 votes

  to 433.

  Writing some three years later Rabaut Saint-Étienne was to comment that the

  National Assembly had made known their rights to French citizens in much the

  same way as ‘a sick father, with not long to live, hands over to his heir the title of his

  possessions and of his money’. It was by no means certain, in other words, that the

  assembly would survive for long enough to pass the laws which followed from the

  principles outlined in the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen.49

  This proved to be the case. Condorcet, for example, in a pamphlet entitled

  Réflexions sur ce qui a été fait et ce qui reste à faire,50 commented upon the ‘anarchy’

  and ‘hatred’ that had resulted from a vaguely worded and defective declaration of

  rights. It was, he argued ‘the false impression that the people had seized of their

  rights, in imagining that the tumultuous will of a town, a borough, a village, and

  even a district, is a form of law and that the will of the people, in whatever manner it

  was manifested, had the same authority as a will expressed in a prescribed form by a

  recognized law’ that was at the heart of the problem. The people, Condorcet

  remarked plaintively as the unfolding of the Revolution pushed him nearer to his

  own personal tragedy, must recognize that they could not ask for more than they

  had been given.

  The dramatic events that followed can only be sketched in brief outline. The

  declaration of rights approved by the National Assembly at the end of August 1789

  was eventually to figure as a preamble to the revised monarchical constitution,

  approved on 14 September 1791. Three months earlier, however, Louis XVI had

  attempted to flee France, only to be intercepted with other members of his family at

  Varennes and forced to return to Paris in abject humiliation.51 Although given a

  second chance to prove his loyalty to the new regime, the monarch’s days were now

  effectively numbered. In the spring of 1792 France (recklessly) declared war against

  Austria and soon found herself being invaded, with the capital itself in danger.

  47 André-Louis-Esprit, comte de Sinety, ‘Exposition des motifs qui parasissent devoir déterminer à

  reunir à la Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen, celle des devoirs du citoyen’, in Fauré, Les

  Déclarations, 175–81.

  48 Henri-Baptiste, abbé Grégoire, ‘Opinion sur la necessité de parler des devoirs dans la Déclaration

  des droits de l’homme et du citoyen’, in Fauré, Les Déclarations, 189–90. See also de Baecque, L’An 1

  des droits de l’homme, 121–5.

  49 Rabaut Saint-Etienne, Précis historique, 191–2.

  50 Œuvres de Condorcet, ix. 441–68.

  51 See Mona Ozouf, Varennes: La Mort de la royauté (2005).

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  39

  Amid mounting chaos, on 10 August the Tuileries Palace was stormed, in one

  insurrectionary gesture overturning both the constitution and the king. A month

  later, France was declared a republic, with Louis XVI being subsequently put on

  trial and executed in January 1793.

  The new legislative assembly, now known as the Convention, had therefore

  both to save France from defeat and to promulgate a new constitution. To its

  credit, it did both, although at a high price. In the first instance, this momentous

  task fell to the group of deputies known as the Girondins, led by Brissot and

  armed with the intellectual support of Condorcet. Given the dramatic circum-

  stances, discussion of the rights of man received
only intermittent attention.

  Nevertheless, by the time that the Girondins fell from power in early June

  1793 they had secured the approval of a new declaration of rights (running to

  thirty articles).52 Largely inspired by Condorcet’s proposals of February of that

  year,53 this new declaration included as rights both the right to equality and the

  right to what was termed ‘la garantie sociale’. There was however much agonizing

  about the force to be given to both the right to property and the right to

  insurrection, the Girondins showing themselves eager to protect the former and

  to restrict the latter to legal means. Mounting popular discontent combined with

  the ferocious assault of the Jacobins made this position increasingly difficult to

  sustain. Robespierre, leading the Montagnard attack, damned the proposals of

  the Girondins, denouncing a declaration of rights made ‘not for man, but for the

  rich, for the monopolists, for the speculators, for tyrants’.54

  A few weeks later the Girondins were removed forcibly from power, the

  Jacobins losing no time in presenting their own declaration of the rights of man

  and the citizen on 24 June 1793. The right to equality was now firmly established

  as one of the four natural rights of man, with the right to property losing its

  ‘inviolable and sacred’ status. If the right to resist oppression was characterized as

  a consequence of these rights, its importance was underlined with the description

  of insurrection as ‘the most sacred of rights and the most necessary of duties’.

  Despite this change of tone and emphasis, the definition of the right to liberty as

  the right to do whatever did not infringe the rights of others remained essentially

  unchanged, as did the definition of property. Indeed, property was now specified

  as the right which ‘belonged to every citizen to enjoy and to dispose of his goods,

  his income, the fruits of his labour and his industry as he pleases’.55 Similarly, if

  the end of society was described as ‘the common good’, the egalitarian impetus

  was restricted to the recognition of the ‘sacred debt’ owed by society towards its

  members and the vague commitment to find work or the means of subsistence for

  those without employment. Robespierre’s proposal for the progressive taxation

  of income was ignored.

  52 See Jaume, Les Déclarations, 262–4.

  53 Ibid. 240–3.

  54 Speech by Robespierre on 24 April 1793: see Œuvres de Maximilien Robespierre, ix. Discours

  Septembre 1792–27 Juillet 1793 (1958), 461.

  55 See Jaume, Les Déclarations, 299–303.

  40

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  Beyond this, the declaration of rights that was to act as a preamble to the

  republican constitution of Year 1 set out a series of individual and collective rights

  intended to protect the citizen from an oppressive government. All, like the new

  constitution itself, were to be suspended with the proclamation of the decree that

  revolutionary government was to operate ‘until the return of peace’.

  Amongst the victims of the Terror were not only both Georges Danton and

  Condorcet, but also Olympe de Gouges, executed on 3 November 1793. Her crimes,

  in the eyes of the Jacobins, were many, but here she merits attention because of her

  remarkable text, Les droits de la femme, dedicated to Marie-Antoinette, Queen of

  France, and penned in 1791. By any standards, this must be one of the most

  subversive documents ever written. It bristles with irony and scorn, lampooning

  the universalistic pretensions of the Revolution, parodying the seventeen articles of

  the declaration of 1789. ‘Law and justice’, de Gouge proclaimed, ‘consist in restoring

  all that belongs to others; thus the only limits to the exercise of the natural rights of

  women are perpetual male tyranny.’ Woman, she continued, ‘has the right to mount

  the scaffold; she must equally have the right to mount the rostrum’. De Gouges

  claimed for women the same rights as those enjoyed by men. Property should belong

  to both sexes. Careers and positions should be open to women as for men. Women

  should be granted an equal share not only of wealth but of public administration.

  Men and women should be equal in the eyes of the law.

  Nothing came of these demands, the Jacobins effectively banning women

  from public life. A decade later the Napoleonic Civil Code of 1804 reversed even

  the limited improvement to the legal status of women introduced during the

  Revolution. Much the same occurred with formulations of rights in general. As

  Jacques Godechot has written, the Constitution of 1795, which followed the

  removal of the Jacobins from power, ‘was drawn up with the aim of preventing

  a return to the regime of Year II, that is, the dictatorship of a group of men

  who believed themselves to be directly mandated by the “people”’.56 What this

  meant has been lucidly summarized by Marcel Gauchet. ‘With Thermidor’, he

  writes, ‘the hour of duties sounded’.57 Accordingly, the declaration of rights

  approved by the Convention on 22 August 1795 came replete with a set of nine

  specific duties, each clearly intended to encourage the individual citizen to obey

  the law, respect property, and serve the patrie.58 Just as significantly, the rights

  proclaimed were no longer taken to be natural but to be those enjoyed by men

  in ‘society’. Reference to men being born free and equal in rights was dropped,

  with equality now being defined simply as equality before the law. The right to

  resist oppression was removed, as was any mention of the rights to free speech

  and freedom of the press. In this way it was hoped that the revolutionary and

  insurrectionary potential of the rights of man would be curbed. Four years later, the

  Constitution of Year VIII, drafted with Napoleon Bonaparte in mind, simply

  dispensed with a declaration of rights altogether.

  56 Jacques Godechot, Les Constitutions de la France depuis 1789 (1970), 94.

  57 Marcel Gauchet, La Révolution des droits de l’homme (1989), 257.

  58 See Jaume, Les Déclarations, 307–9.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  41

  I I I

  It was among the increasingly vociferous ranks of Catholic and monarchical

  reaction that criticisms of the merits of the language of the rights of man came

  most frequently to be heard. Initially supporters of the monarchical cause in the

  National Assembly, such as Durand de Maillane, showed little restraint in deploy-

  ing the language of natural rights to defend their position, believing that the

  proclamation of rights would play an indispensable part in returning the monarchy

  to its ‘pure and noble origin’.59 Quickly, however, the supporters of a constitution-

  al settlement on the moderate right began to have grave doubts about the potential

  dangers of this strategy. The Comte de Montlosier, future member of the Club

  Monarchique, concluded his Essai sur l’art de constituer les peuples ou Examen des

  opérations constitutionnelles de l’assemblée nationale de France with a forty-page

  outline entitled ‘Aperçu d’un projet de constitution’, replete with its own ‘Déclara-

  tion des droits de l’homme’.60 In this he had few kind words for the declaration of

 
26 August 1789. If, Montlosier argued, there were two types of revolution––one

  which followed the dictates of reason and of nature, another which was prepared in

  ‘silence’ and in the ‘shadows’––so too there were two ways of formulating a

  declaration of rights. The best method was ‘to take man as he is today’, within

  society as it existed, in order to examine ‘the best place for him in this situation’.

  The incorrect method was to look at the nature of man in isolation, abstracted from

  all ‘social conventions’. The latter, ‘analytical’ process, while it might be appropriate

  for a solitary thinker in the calm of his study and distanced from events, when

  applied to the highly charged context of an assembly comprised of ‘twelve hundred

  people’, had produced a set of ‘true, ambiguous or false maxims’ which, taken

  together, lacked either ‘structure or coherence’. What sense, Montlosier remarked,

  did it make to suggest that ignorance, forgetfulness, and contempt for the rights of

  man were the sole causes of public misfortune? What about superstition, fear, the

  desire to dominate, pride, necessity, hunger, laziness, and epidemics? In what

  possible way could man be said to be born free and equal in rights? Of what sort

  of liberty were they talking? Physical liberty? Moral liberty? And if man ‘were to

  remain free only in this manner’, Montlosier mocked, ‘I think that of all creatures

  he would truly be the greatest slave’. Moreover, it was not at all clear what was

  meant by such terms as property, security, and resistance to oppression. The end

  result was that a set of ‘philosophical adages’ had become a weapon used by man

  against society itself.

  Montlosier’s own statement of rights took on a very different complexion,

  beginning with a proclamation that personal slavery was against the nature and

  rights of man and that the right of property was grounded in the right of all men to

  own what they had produced through their labour. It ended with the assertion that,

  59 Pierre-Toussaint Durand de Maillane, ‘Opinion sur les divers plans de Constitution’, 137–50.

  60 François-Dominique de Reynaud, comte de Montlosier, Essai sur l’art de constituer les peuples ou

  Examen des opérations constitutionnellles de l’Assemblée nationale de France (1790).

 

‹ Prev