Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 20
Revolution and the Republic Page 20

by Jeremy Jennings


  deputies were to be found an astonishing, if not unrivalled, selection of literary and

  intellectual talent. By the side of poet and historian Alphonse de Lamartine were to be

  found Félicité de Lamennais, the socialists Louis Blanc, Pierre Leroux, and Philippe

  Buchez, the historian Edgar Quinet, Alexis de Tocqueville, the writer Victor Hugo,

  and the anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. Lesser luminaries included Victor Con-

  sidérant, Alexandre Ledru-Rollin, the liberal Catholics Henri-Dominique Lacordaire

  and Charles de Montalembert, and economic pamphleteer Frédéric Bastiat.98 In the

  first few months, it was Lamartine who effectively dominated the chamber.99

  If the Constituent Assembly of the Second Republic found it no easy task to

  agree upon the rights to be accorded to its citizens, questions relating to the

  organization of executive and legislative power proved equally problematic. However,

  97 Ibid. 107.

  98 See Michel Winock, Les Voix de la liberté: Les Écrivains engagés au XIXe siècle (2001), 315–46.

  99 For Lamartine’s political views see Renée David (ed.), Alphonse de Lamartine, la politique et

  l’histoire (1993).

  90

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  they were subject to the most extensive and detailed discussion. The assembly set up a

  constitutional committee, which began work in late May 1848. Its report was passed

  on to the fifteen bureaux of the assembly, who in turn reported back to the committee

  on 24 July. The committee then revised its proposals, placed them before the

  Assembly, with discussion of each article taking place between 4 September and 27

  October. Amended, the proposals were reviewed again by the committee, and

  received final approval by the Assembly on 4 November 1848.100 ‘Never perhaps’,

  wrote Maurice Deslandres in 1933, ‘has any constitution been so meticulously and so

  lengthily drawn up; if it was not perfect it was certainly not for want of thought and

  labour.’101

  There were certain areas of relative agreement. In line with the traditions

  established in the 1790s, the first article of the constitution affirmed that ‘sover-

  eignty resides in the universality of French citizens’. Despite the doubts of some,

  and references in debates (as in the past) to the cases of servants and the illiterate,

  the suffrage was granted to all males over 21 years of age. Voting was to be both

  secret and direct, with voters choosing from lists of candidates for each département.

  Without the latter, as one deputy explained, France would only see the election of

  candidates representing ‘the interest of the village, the canton, the arrondissement,

  and not general interests’. The priest and the landowner, it was feared, would

  dominate in each locality.102 Article 34 stipulated that deputies, elected for three

  years, represented not their département but ‘France in her entirety’, whilst Article

  35 specified that they could not be put under a specific mandate by their electors.

  The emphasis therefore again fell upon ensuring the independence of representa-

  tives from particular or sectional interests. This was not to be the last echo from the

  past. Under Article 32, the Assembly, as the expression of the national will, was

  deemed to sit ‘permanently’. When it chose to adjourn, a commission composed of

  its members would have the right to recall the Assembly ‘in a case of emergency’.

  More contentious was the debate surrounding the familiar question of whether

  the Republic should operate with one or two parliamentary chambers. Two things

  stand out here. The first is that it was at this point that the divisions between ‘les

  républicains de la veille ou du lendemain’ became most evident. The former, those

  who had been republicans before 1848, tended to support a one-chamber arrange-

  ment, whilst the latter, those who had converted (often with deep misgivings) to the

  Republic after the Revolution of 1848, usually inclined towards a two-chamber

  model. Secondly, the debates of 1848 were in many respects a rerun of those of the

  revolutionary decade after 1789.

  This, for example, was how Alexis de Tocqueville defended the call for two

  chambers.103 To believe, he argued, that a two-chamber system amounted to

  the institutionalization of aristocratic power was a mistake and rested upon a

  100 See François Luchaire, Naissance d’une constitution: 1848 (1998), 193–270.

  101 Maurice Deslandres, Histoire constitutionnelle de la France de 1789 à 1870 (1933), ii. 345.

  102 Piero Craveri, Genesi di una constituzione: Libertà et socialismo nel dibattio constituzionale del

  1848 in Francia (Naples, 1985), 138.

  103 Ibid. 129–31.

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  91

  misunderstanding of the proper functioning of parliamentary institutions. There

  were at least three justifications that could be provided to support such a model.

  Executive power needed to be strong but in order to prevent it from abusing its

  power there was room for another body which could control certain of its actions

  (the signing of treaties, etc.). Executive power was placed in ‘a perilous position’

  when it found itself confronted by a single chamber. Conflict would be inevitable;

  with the result that one or the other would quickly destroy its opponent. Next,

  a single chamber would be consumed by what Tocqueville described as ‘legislative

  intemperance’, the desire to legislate ‘without cease’. ‘The body that represents

  all ideas, all interests,’ he argued, ‘drives everything forward, destroys everything:

  it is irresistible.’ Finally, he made the point that if the existence of two chambers could

  not prevent a revolution, it could at least militate against poor government causing

  revolutions. There would exist ‘a diversity of views’ from which both would profit.104

  In short, Tocqueville and his allies did everything possible to refute the

  charge that the argument for two chambers was an argument in defence of

  aristocratic power. It is this that explains why their frequent point of reference

  was no longer the English monarchical constitution but rather the American

  republican model.105 Tocqueville himself added a new preface to the 12th

  edition of De la Démocratie en Amérique, in which he argued that the principles

  of the American constitution were ‘indispensable for all Republics’.106 He

  similarly told the electors of Cherbourg that ‘in America, the Republic is not

  a dictatorship exercised in the name of liberty; it is liberty itself, the real and true

  liberty of all the citizens’.107

  From this perspective, the emphasis fell upon seeking to ensure that legislation

  was subject to scrutiny by different groups of people who, although representing

  the same ‘democratic’ interest, would ‘moderate’ the possibly impetuous and ill-

  considered actions of a single chamber possessed of the inclination to believe that it

  alone spoke in the name and with the authority of the ‘national will’. ‘Do not

  doubt’, Duvergier de Hauranne told his parliamentary colleagues, ‘that in voting

  for two chambers we will satisfy the need for order, the need for moderation, the

  need for stability, which is what the entire country now demands: by voti
ng for two

  chambers we will prove that we wish to bring the revolutionary crisis to an end and

  to return to an era of legal government.’108

  Discussion of the relevance of the American constitutional model was by no

  means confined to the parliamentary chamber and its constitutional commission.

  The text of the American constitution was reprinted in several new editions and it

  104 See Lucien Jaume, ‘Tocqueville et le problème du pouvoir exécutif en 1848’, Revue Française de

  Science Politique, 41 (1991), 739–55.

  105 See René Rémond, Les-États-Unis devant l’opinion française 1815–1852 (1962), 831–58; Odile

  Rudelle, ‘La France et l’expérience constitutionnelle américaine: Un modèle présent, perdu, retrouvé’,

  in Marie-France Toinet (ed.), Et la Constitution créa l’Amérique (Nancy, 1988), 35–52; and Marc

  Lahmer, La Constitution Américaine dans le débat français, 1795–1848 (2001), 291–381.

  106 Alexis de Tocqueville, Œuvres complètes (1961), i/1, pp. xliii–xliv.

  107 Ibid. (1990), iii/3. 44–5.

  108 Le Moniteur Universel (26 Sept. 1848), 2596.

  92

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  was the subject of frequent commentary in the press.109 It was also debated in

  numerous brochures and pamphlets.110 The most vigorous and articulate member

  of the ‘American school’ was Édouard Laboulaye.111 In 1849 Laboulaye was

  appointed to the chair of comparative law at the Collège de France. His inaugural

  lecture was entitled De la Constitution Américaine et de l’Utilité de son étude (1850).

  In 1849 he had published his Considérations sur la Constitution. The latter text

  began with a full-blooded criticism of socialist wishful thinking and of abstract

  declarations of rights. Laboulaye then presented a systematic critique of those

  constitutional proposals––specifically, a unicameral chamber and a weak execu-

  tive––that ignored the lessons to be learnt from America. It was not a question of

  slavishly copying the American constitution but of recognizing the merits of a

  system that had brought internal peace, prosperity, and liberty. In 1851 Laboulaye

  returned to this theme in his La Révision de la constitution: Lettres à un ami.112

  The proponents of the two-chamber American model readily acknowledged that

  public opinion was against them. Despite the fact that, in their view, the correctness

  of their position was proven by both reason and experience––principally, the

  descent of one-chamber government into revolutionary dictatorship contrasted

  with the long-established stability and success of the American constitution––

  their fear was that the rhetoric of the past, littered as it was with references to the

  indivisibility of sovereignty and the unity of the national will, would carry the day.

  This proved to be the case. The report drawn up by the constitutional committee

  and presented to the Assembly by Armand Marrast spoke in the following terms:

  ‘Sovereignty is one; the nation is one; the national will is one. Why therefore should

  we want the delegation of sovereignty to be divisible, national representation to be

  split into two, the law, which emanates from the general will, to give a double

  expression to a single thought?’113 The same text justified this position by reference

  to what it took to be an incontestable fact: ‘the homogeneity of the French people’.

  Time and time again the opponents of the two-chamber model returned to this

  theme. For example, Marcel Barthe, deputy for the Basses-Pyrénées, argued: ‘If we

  consider the elements making up our country, we find a people that is completely

  109 See e.g. Clarigny, ‘Des institutions républicains en France et aux Etats-Unis’, Le Constitutionnel

  (10 and 24 June, and 5 July 1848) and J. A. Dréollé, ‘Lettres sur la Constitution américaine’,

  L’Opinion publique (28 Nov., 10 and 19 Dec. 1848). The latter cited Tocqueville’s ‘excellent work’

  but went on to contrast the political immaturity of the French with the maturity of the Americans.

  Above all, see Michel Chevalier, ‘Étude sur la Constitution des États-Unis’, Le Journal des Débats,

  Politiques et Littéraires (25 May, 6, 15, and 22 June, 4, 11, and 21 July 1848).

  110 See e.g. Hyacinthe Colombel, Quelques réflexions concernant la Constitution qu’on élabore pour la

  France (Nantes, 1848); J. Magne, Esquisse d’une Constitution: Ce que la France républicaine pourrait,

  avec avantage, emprunter aux institutions des Etats-Unis (1848); and Abel Rendu, Les deux Républiques

  (1850).

  111 See Walter D. Gray, Interpreting American Democracy in France: The Career of Edouard

  Laboulaye (Newark, NJ, 1994).

  112 Both Considérations sur la Constitution and La Révision de la Constitution were repr. in Questions

  constitutionnelles (1872).

  113 ‘Rapport fait au nom de la commission de Constitution, après avoir entendu les représentants

  délégués des bureaux, par le citoyen Armand Marrast, représentant du peuple. Séance du 30 août

  1848’, in Luchaire, Naissance d’une constitution, 203.

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  93

  homogeneous . . . there exists only one great nation, speaking the same language,

  living under the same laws, the same administration, the same rules; from one

  extremity to the other there exists a nation indivisible in all of its parts.’ Moreover,

  this homogeneity was written into the course of French history. ‘If we consider’,

  Barthe continued, ‘our history we see that since the first centuries of the monarchy,

  it has constantly moved towards unity, something that has been attained through

  the greatest of efforts and the most generous of sacrifices . . . Our forefathers, with

  their victories and their blood, made this unity.’ Here was to be found ‘the greatness

  and the strength of France’. For good measure, Barthe then added that the French

  ‘love equality more than they love liberty’.114

  Similar arguments were advanced by other deputies, the focus invariably falling

  upon the idea that unity was the special ‘genius’ of France. Again these views found

  an echo in wider public discussion. For example, Émile Dehais, in a text specifically

  designed to refute the arguments presented by François Guizot in his De la

  Démocratie en France, countered that ‘of all states, the United States is the one

  upon which we should least model ourselves. This is why. France is the most

  unitary country that exists and the republic of the United States is federal. To claim

  to give to the one certain fundamental institutions of the other and to rely upon the

  example of this other in order to demonstrate the necessity of these institutions is to

  prove almost nothing.’115

  It was Alphonse de Lamartine, the supreme orator of the 1848 Revolution, who

  brought the parliamentary debate to a close. The pages of Le Moniteur Universel

  record that when he stood up to speak he was received with ‘a deep silence’. What,

  he began, was a constitution if not ‘the exterior form of a people’? It should not be

  something arbitrary but should express the ‘reality of the nature of the nation’.

  Following this logic, why did both England and the United States have two

  chambers? With regard to the former, Lamartine ind
icated that he blushed to

  reply because everyone knew the answer: England was ‘almost exclusively an

  aristocracy’. In France, by contrast, the only aristocracy that existed was the

  ‘aristocracy of enlightenment, the aristocracy of intelligence’. There was no theoc-

  racy, no military caste, and no privilege: all were judged on their personal merit.

  What of America’s Senate? What reality did it represent? The need for federalism

  rather than the spirit of democracy was the answer. It revealed the ‘imperfection’

  and ‘the shortcomings of national unity’ in America and was the continuation of a

  form of ‘anarchy’. The French nation, by contrast, displayed ‘a completely demo-

  cratic unity’, a unity of rank, of origin, and of interest, given expression through

  ‘the sovereignty of all’. To contemplate the creation of a second parliamentary

  chamber, therefore, was to run the risk of artificially introducing an element of

  aristocracy and of division into France. Moreover it was to propose a weakening

  of the sovereignty of the French nation.116

  114 Le Moniteur Universel (27 Sept. 1848), 2606.

  115 Émile Dehais, Du Gouvernement de la France, précedé d’une lettre à M.Guizot sur la Démocratie

  (1851), 214.

  116 Le Moniteur Universel (28 Sept. 1848), 2620–2.

  94

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  The opportunity of reply fell to liberal monarchist Odilon Barrot, who again

  called upon the deputies to remember the need for a mechanism that would

  ‘moderate’ the ‘all-powerful’ nature of ‘French democracy’. Not surprisingly, the

  amendment to introduce two chambers was decisively defeated by 530 votes to

  289. Moreover, the deputies believed that on the outcome of this debate depended

  the future of the Republic. They were to be mistaken, and this was because almost

  their next decision was to approve the direct election of the president. This was

  their great constitutional innovation and this also was their great political error. The

  argument against the direct election of the president was clear enough. Sovereignty

  resided in the people and was expressed through the election of their parliamentary

  representatives to a single chamber. Therefore the head of the executive should be

  chosen by and be responsible to that assembly. To do otherwise, as the future

 

‹ Prev