Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 45
Revolution and the Republic Page 45

by Jeremy Jennings


  statue was placed on the top of the column in the place Vendôme and three years later

  the building of the Arc de Triomphe was completed. This was followed by the return

  of the Emperor’s ashes in 1840.

  It would be wrong to believe that this reappraisal of Napoleon received a

  universal welcome. There were many legitimists and republicans in particular

  who felt deep unease at what was occurring and who were (rightly) troubled by

  the possible future political consequences. Nevertheless, as Quinet’s account re-

  vealed, this reworking of the Napoleonic myth was integral to the manner in which

  his generation came to terms with the defeat and national humiliation that

  accompanied the return of the Bourbon monarchy. More intriguing still was the

  facility with which this generation believed that the aspirations embodied in both

  liberalism and nationalism could be combined.

  No one better expressed these sentiments than Armand Carrel. Through both

  his writings and his actions he provided a vivid, not to say romantic, illustration of

  the hopes and ideals of his age.56 Born in Rouen in 1800, Carrel was educated at

  the military academy of Saint-Cyr before entering the army in 1821. His political

  sympathies were quickly disclosed through membership of the most notorious of

  the secret societies of the Restoration period: the Carbonari. Inspired by the original

  Neapolitan model, the French version attracted as many as 30,000 adherents,

  organized on military lines but with no recognizable programme beyond that of

  the desire to remove the Bourbon monarchy.57 The movement’s not unexpected

  54 See Œuvres complètes de Edgar Quinet, 213.

  55 Ibid.

  56 See James S. Allen, ‘Y-a-t-il eu en France une “génération romantique de 1830”?’, Romantisme,

  28–9 (1980), 103–8.

  57 Alan B. Spitzer, Old Hatreds and Young Hopes (Cambridge, Mass., 1971).

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  211

  failure led Carrel to resign from the army in 1823, only for him soon afterwards to

  depart for Spain in order to take up arms in support of the liberal cause and against

  the French army sent to defend Ferdinand VII. His regiment of volunteers was

  named after Napoleon II and fought in the uniform of the Imperial army. Captured

  and imprisoned, upon his release Carrel secured employment as secretary to the

  historian Augustin Thierry. There followed, in rapid succession, the publication (as

  part of a series of national histories) of his Résumé de l’histoire de l’Ecosse58 and his

  Résumé de l’histoire des Grecs modernes,59 the creation of La Revue Américaine (which

  ran from July 1826 to June 1827), participation in some of the most distinguished

  journals of the epoch—Le Constitutionnel, Le Globe, La Revue Française as well as

  the Saint-Simonian Le Producteur—and, in 1827, the appearance of his Histoire de

  la Contre-Révolution en Angleterre.60 January 1830 saw the publication of the first

  issue of Le National, of which Carrel remained the editor until his death in a duel in

  1836.

  Carrel’s preoccupation with the nation and the oppression of nationalities was

  evident from the outset. His history of Scotland, for example, provided him not

  only with ample evidence of the intolerable injustices inflicted upon a subject

  population but also with series of events which could be genuinely portrayed as a

  national uprising against foreign domination. The ‘audacious expedition’ of

  Charles Edward Stuart was not an attempt to reclaim the monarchy for Catholic

  absolutism but rather ‘the last effort of a population armed for independence and

  implacable in its hatred of England’. Likewise, his outline of Greek history revealed

  both a people struggling to free itself from slavery and a nation whose hopes for

  independence had been sacrificed to the principles of stability proclaimed by the

  Holy Alliance. ‘The Greek revolution’, Carrel proclaimed, was ‘a new and sad proof

  of the relative strength of governments and nations’.

  Equally visible was an attachment to liberal principles of constitutional govern-

  ment designed to limit the absolute power of monarchs. Reflecting upon the civil

  war in Spain and what he saw as ‘a hatred of French domination’, he concluded that

  if, in the first instance, Spain’s liberal constitution of 1812 had been perceived by

  the people only as ‘an instrument of resistance against foreign usurpation’, they had

  later come to understand that ‘the constitution and Ferdinand could not coexist’.61

  In far greater detail, he argued that the experience of ‘counter-revolution’, the

  attempt by James II to impose his will upon the nation, ‘had taught the English

  people that its liberties were at variance with a royalty lacking consent and that in

  order to preserve royalty to any advantage it was necessary to regenerate it, to

  separate it from the principle of legitimacy’.62 The ‘enlightened’ section of the

  English population, Carrel believed, had come to accept that, if monarchy was

  necessary in a country divided into classes, it should not be in a position to

  58 Résumé de l’histoire de l’Ecosse (1825).

  59 Résumé de l’histoire des Grecs modernes (1825).

  60 Histoire de la Contre-Révolution en Angleterre (1827).

  61 ‘De l’Espagne et de sa Révolution’ in Œuvres littéraires et économiques d’Armand Carrel (1854),

  113–37. First publ. in La Revue Française (Mar. 1828).

  62 Carrel, Histoire de la Contre-Révolution, 4.

  212

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  withdraw ‘national liberties’ at will. Carrel also felt that a reformed monarchy

  resting upon the consent of the nation was in accord with the ‘new interests’ that

  had emerged within English society. It was this characteristically liberal theme that

  he deployed elsewhere in his writings in the 1820s to demonstrate what he took to

  be the connection between trade and national renaissance.

  The title and content of one article, ‘Du commerce de la grèce moderne,

  consideré dans son influence sur la régénération politique de cette nation’, is

  sufficient to illustrate this point.63 The recent struggle for national independence

  in Greece, Carrel argued, had its source in the commercial expansion of the Greek

  economy. ‘A certain degree of prosperity’ had in turn produced a desire for a ‘liberal

  education’, confirming the ‘intellectual superiority’ of the Greeks over their Turk-

  ish masters. ‘It is certain’, Carrel wrote, that the ‘enlightened, well-off, industrious

  class created by business within the Greek nation has constantly tended . . . to upset

  the balance that, since the conquest, existed between the means of oppression of the

  conquerors and the means of resistance of the subjugated’.64 It was but a short step

  from ‘affluence’ to ‘emancipation’. However, as befitted a government driven by ‘a

  superstitious and ferocious egoism’, the Turks had taken the alternative of extermi-

  nation and terror rather than that of liberation.

  The specifically domestic implications of this argument were spelt out in Carrel’s

  response to Stendhal’s charge, in D’un nouveau complot contre les industriels, that

  Saint-Simoniani
sm was nothing else but a glorification of businessmen and of vulgar

  materialism.65 ‘The workers are for us’, Carrel wrote in Le Producteur, ‘not a class

  within society but society itself ’ and it was through their useful work that ‘old

  Europe’ was to be reformed. The future, he acknowledged, would in all probability

  be less prolific in ‘transcendental virtues’ but so too it would be less characterized

  by vice and corruption. The enlightenment and well-being that would arise out

  of ‘the application of the skills that each one of us has received’ would ensure that

  ‘public virtues’ would flourish where now only ‘private’ ones existed. The sciences,

  arts, and industry, would become a new ‘Panthéon national’: it was in this sense, and

  not in Stendhal’s deprecating sense, that society would be ‘materialized’.

  As we saw in the previous chapter, the stress upon the relationship between

  commerce or ‘industrie’ and the emergence of new and advanced political forms

  was a theme commonly to be found in the writings of French liberals at this time.

  On this account, constitutional and limited government was appropriate to all

  modern peoples intent upon the pursuit of material ease through industry. By the

  same token, the activity of war had become a deadly anachronism. Carrel, for all

  his immense admiration for Constant and their shared assumptions about the

  beneficial influence of commerce,66 disagreed both with the interpretation of

  recent French history that this implied and with the view that the uniform tendency

  63 Œuvres littéraires et économiques, 67–96. First publ. in Le Producteur (Oct.–Nov. 1825).

  64 Ibid. 92.

  65 Carrel, ‘A Propos d’une brochure’, in Œuvres littéraires et économiques, 93–6. First publ. in Le

  Producteur (Dec. 1825).

  66 See the obituary notice written by Carrel for Le National, in Œuvres politiques et littéraires

  d’Armand Carrel (1857), i. 424–6. Constant was described as ‘a great defender of liberty’.

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  213

  of modern society was or should be towards peace. When this is understood, we

  move closer to understanding what made Carrel, unlike Constant, a liberal and a

  nationalist.

  For liberals of Constant’s generation the tumultuous events of 1789–1815 were

  not only ones that had had to be personally lived through but they had also vividly

  demonstrated how legitimate demands for political equality could be subverted first

  into a reign of terror and then into an authoritarian military regime. From this

  experience derived a general reluctance to draw any positive lessons from the

  experience of these twenty-six years. The mood in liberal circles was to start to

  change in the 1820s when a new generation of historians began to produce the first

  full-length, relatively unpolemical accounts of the revolutionary period.67 First

  Adolphe Thiers (born 1797) with his ten-volume Histoire de la Révolution française

  (published 1823–7) and then Auguste Mignet (born 1798) with his more modest

  two-volume Histoire de la Révolution française depuis 1789 jusqu’en 1814 (published

  in 1824) described in detail, and despite their obvious mutual detestation of

  Robespierrre and the Jacobins, a process of revolution that, taken as a whole and

  regardless of its inevitable excesses, had nevertheless transformed France from top

  to bottom and brought it to the dawn of a new era.68 It was this innovative

  assessment of the Revolution and its outcome that made its mark upon Carrel.

  The work of Thiers, he wrote, ‘is the first where this magnificent and terrible epoch

  is described with an appropriate breadth and impartiality’,69 whilst that of Mignet

  invited people ‘to return to the truth of the Revolution, to recall the eternal justice

  of its claims, to admire its invincible perseverance in its struggles, to understand it

  in each of the necessities imposed by the alternative of conquering or being

  destroyed’.70 Of Napoleon Bonaparte, Carrel accepted that the consequence of

  his rise to power had been to extinguish liberty ‘as if the word had never been

  pronounced and the Bastille never taken’, but here he was prepared to accept that

  ‘the man of war does not appear to merit the reproaches directed at the man of

  politics’. In the same article Carrel commented that a society in ‘perpetual peace’

  would fall into ‘decay’. ‘Look’, he remarked by way of justification, ‘at the state of

  France at the end of the eighteenth century. Without doubt a war should be just

  but grounded in justice and following a long interval of peace it can reinvigorate the

  morals and character of nations.’71 Carrel, then, was prepared to locate his liberal-

  ism within the traditions of the Revolution and to embrace its glorious military

  achievements.

  67 See Olivier Bétourné and Aglaia I. Hartog, Penser l’histoire de la Révolution: Deux siècles de passion

  française (1989), 35–56.

  68 See Yvonne Knibiehler, ‘Une révolution “nécessaire”: Thiers, Mignet et l’école fataliste’,

  Romantisme, 28–9 (1980), 279–88.

  69 ‘Histoire de la Révolution française de M. A. Thiers’, Œuvres littéraires et économiques, 104. First

  publ. in Le Constitutionel (Jan. 1826).

  70 Ibid. 108–9.

  71 ‘Mémoires sur les campagnes des armées de Rhin et de Rhin et Moselle’, Œuvres littéraires et

  économiques, 174–207.

  214

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  All of this figured by way of preparation for Carrel’s greatest and most

  significant undertaking: the editing, at first with Adolphe Thiers and François

  Mignet and then alone, of Le National. Financed by the banker Jacques Laffitte

  with Talleyrand’s moral support, the first issue appeared on 3 January 1830. Its

  audience, we are told, was largely composed of middle-class patriots, students,

  soldiers, and the occasional artisan. Whilst never attaining anything like a mass

  circulation—estimates put its circulation at between 2,000 and 4,000—Le

  National was, in a sense, the paper of the July Revolution. Not only did its

  young editors help to launch the protests that led ultimately to the downfall of

  the Bourbon monarchy but, as events unfolded, the offices of Le National

  became the unofficial headquarters of the opposition.72

  Thiers immediately made clear his and the journal’s position. The Charte of

  1814, daily flouted by Charles X, had to be fully respected and if implemented

  would produce a system of constitutional and representative government broadly

  similar to the English model. As the months proceeded, to this was added fierce

  criticism of the Polignac ministry, support for the 221 deputies who in March 1830

  voted against the government, and finally, with what were seen as the efforts of the

  forces of counter-revolution to shackle the press, the call for Louis-Philippe to

  occupy the throne.

  Carrel played a part in each of these campaigns, producing a series of brilliant

  articles attacking ‘le parti prétendu monarchique’ and ‘le parti royaliste’. From the

  outset he was a supporter of the July Monarchy but he, unlike Thiers, remained

  outside government, proclaiming that Le National would ‘nev
er become a ministe-

  rial broadsheet’. What followed, therefore, were hectic years of journalistic activity,

  court appearances, and vigorous campaigning in defence of the principles of 1830.

  For Carrel, the July Revolution had been, above all, the work of the people and it

  was to them that the victory was due. Moreover, Carrel was convinced that the July

  Revolution could not possibly degenerate in the same manner as the great revolu-

  tion of 1789. This was because the people were ‘much less ignorant and much more

  moral’ than had previously been the case and, more significantly, because 1789 and

  1830 were different events with different scenarios. If both had been victories over

  the same principle—divine or absolute monarchy—then the scale of opposition

  that had been faced bore no comparison. The first had confronted not just the

  monarchy, but also a powerful nobility and the clergy, as well as the armies of

  Europe, and it was for this reason that the ‘power and the passions of the multitude’

  had needed to be unleashed. In 1830, by contrast, ‘the monarchy, through a change

  of dynasty, became the accomplice of the revolution, whilst as a result of the

  principle of equality before the law the interests of the privileged classes were at

  one with the interests of the nation’. Thus there would be no emigration, no new

  Coblenz, ‘no absolutist crusade against France’.73

  Nevertheless, the mistake, in Carrel’s view, was to imagine that all that had

  occurred was that one government had replaced another. It was the whole system of

  72 See J. P. T. Bury and Robert Tombs, Thiers (London, 1986), 18–39.

  73 Œuvres politiques et littéraires d’Armand Carrel, i. 227–33.

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  215

  Charles X that had been removed and with that came the realization that France

  could no longer ‘be governed by the sword’. The restored Bourbon monarchs had

  never been able to accept that the liberties and rights contained in the Charte had

  not been granted to France by the monarchy but had been gained by ‘our arms and

  our civilization’. 1830 made it indisputably clear that the monarchy owed its

  existence to an act of ‘the national will’. ‘It is the people’, Carrel wrote, ‘who are

  in possession of the original sovereignty and royalty which exists by virtue of a

 

‹ Prev