Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 64
Revolution and the Republic Page 64

by Jeremy Jennings


  Bossuet declared, was sacrilege. In this way, the mortal monarch acquired the

  quality of quasi-divinity whilst the monarchy as an institution was adorned with

  the trappings of religious sanctity: thus strengthened, the crown could be rendered

  immune from the perils of Protestant dissent.20

  Protestant dissent had indeed posed a formidable challenge to royal supremacy.

  From the mid-sixteenth century onwards, Huguenot writers developed a radical

  constitutionalist theory that not only emphasized the legal limits on absolutism but

  also came to relocate the original source of sovereignty among the people them-

  selves. In so doing, as Quentin Skinner has argued, they were to perform ‘the

  epoch-making move’ of transforming a purely religious theory of resistance into a

  political theory of revolution. On this view, there existed the moral right (as

  opposed to religious duty) to resist any ruler who did not honour the obligation

  to pursue the welfare of his people.21 After the massacre of St Bartholomew in 1572

  (when as many as two thousand Protestants were murdered in Paris) such ‘mon-

  archomach’ principles were deployed to justify outright rebellion and civil war.

  This was a battle that French Calvinists were destined to lose and one that allowed

  proponents of absolutism to claim, with some justification, that royal authority

  alone could protect France from the decline into anarchy, but the subversive

  potential of Calvinist political theory, much of it developed in exile in the Nether-

  lands, remained intact until the end of the ancien régime.

  For its part, the French state continued to persecute Protestants and what it

  regarded as Protestant tendencies within the Catholic Church, most notably

  Jansenism.22 The doctrinal controversy that separated Jansenism with its austere

  Augustinian theology from the humanistic optimism of the Jesuits constituted one

  18 Ibid. 15.

  19 See Politics Drawn from the Very Words of Holy Scripture (Cambridge, 1990), 160. For the

  broader context see William Farr Church, Constitutional Thought in Sixteenth-Century France: A Study

  in the Evolution of Ideas (Cambridge, Mass., 1941) and Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern

  Political Thought, ii. The Age of Reformation (Cambridge, 1978), 239–301.

  20 See Jean-Frédéric Schaub, La France espagnole: Les Racines hispaniques de l’absolutisme français

  (2003). Schaub shows that the French monarchy, in driving out Protestants from France, sought to

  emulate the example of Spain’s expulsion of Muslims and Jews.

  21 Skinner, Foundations, 335.

  22 See William Doyle, Jansenism (Houndmills, 2000) and Catherine Maire, De la cause de Dieu à la

  cause de la Nation: Le Jansénisme au XVIIIe siècle (1998). See also Maire (ed.), Jansénisme et Révolution

  (1990) and Maire, ‘Port Royal: The Jansenist Schism’, in Pierre Nora (ed.), Realms of Memory, i.

  Conflicts and Divisions (New York, 1996), 301–51. The classic study is by Lucien Goldmann, The

  Hidden God: A Study of Tragic Vision in the Pensées of Pascal and the Tragedies of Racine (London,

  1964). For a brilliant discussion of the theological issues at stake see Leszek Kolakowski, God Owes Us

  Nothing: A Brief Remark on Pascal’s Religion and on the Spirit of Jansenism (Chicago, 1995). Jansenism

  took its name from Cornelius Jansenius (1585–1638), Bishop of Ypres, whose study of the thought of

  St Augustine was published posthumously in 1640.

  302

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  of the great religious quarrels of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.23

  Much of the serious polemic focused upon discussion of the ‘Five Propositions’

  deemed by their opponents to be at the heart of Jansenist doctrine, but, in essence,

  what was at stake was a divergence over the extent to which Christianity had to

  make concessions to worldliness. For the Jesuits, the emphasis placed by Jansenists

  upon divine grace and moral rigour smacked of Protestant heresy whilst, for the

  Jansenists, the defence of human free will associated with Jesuit Pelagianism and

  Molinism was a pretext for confessional and spiritual laxity.24 By 1669 the Jesuits

  appeared victorious and the supporters of Jansenism had been largely reduced

  to silence and submission. Moreover, any potential political challenge posed by

  Jansenism to the claims of divine right monarchy had failed to materialize.

  This might have remained the case had the State and the Church not persisted in

  the persecution of what survived of the Jansenist community. In 1709 its spiritual

  home, the monastery of Port Royal outside Paris, was closed down. Two years later

  the buildings were demolished in order to prevent them from becoming a site of

  pilgrimage. Then, in 1713, Pope Clement XI published the papal bull Unigenitus

  condemning 101 Jansenist propositions deemed to be false and heretical. This

  proved to be a major miscalculation and something of a pyrrhic victory. Unigenitus

  quickly became a metaphor for absolutism and a regalvanized Jansenist movement

  found growing support amongst both clergy and laity alike. Matters came to a head

  between 1730 and 1733 when Cardinal Fleury, Louis XV’s first minister, deter-

  mined to put an end to dissent once and for all by having it declared that Unigenitus

  had the status of a ‘law of Church and State’.

  How might these theological disputes have contributed to the origins of the

  Revolution of 1789? First, under the weight of persecution the Jansenist cause

  converged with that of the Parlements in their opposition to the arbitrary power and

  unlimited authority of royal absolutism and ecclesiastical hierarchy.25 Next, the

  continuous replaying of these Jansenist controversies throughout the eighteenth

  century severely undermined the legislative and religious symbols of absolutism,

  thereby, it is argued, contributing to the ‘desacralization’ of the monarchy and its

  ultimate delegitimation.26 Finally, in the wake of the so-called Maupeou revolution

  23 See Dale K. Van Kley, ‘Jansenism and the International Suppression of the Jesuits’, in Brown and

  Tackett, Cambridge History of Christianity, vii. 302–28, and Kley, The Jansenists and the Expulsion of the

  Jesuits from France, 1757–1765 (New Haven, Conn., 1975).

  24 The most famous Jansenist attack upon this aspect of Jesuit practice—known as casuistry—was

  Blaise Pascal’s Lettres provinciales of 1656. Pascal’s text highlighted what he regarded as the theological

  frivolity and hypocrisy of the Jesuits.

  25 See Julian Swann, Politics and the Parlement of Paris under Louis XV, 1754–1774 (Cambridge,

  1995). If Swann accepts that a ‘coterie’ of Jansenist magistrates exercised influence within the Parlement

  of Paris, he nevertheless suggests that ‘it is important not to allow the Jansenist tale to wag the

  parlementaire dog’: p. 38.

  26 See Kley, Religious Origins, and Jeffrey Merrick, The Desacralization of the French Monarchy in the

  Eighteenth Century (Baton Rouge, La., 1990). Merrick argues that ‘These conflicts, more than the

  Enlightenment, undermined the judicial fictions that bound the ancien régime together’: p.49.The

  counter-argument affirms that the desacralization of the monarchy was far less profound and

  widespread than this might suggest: see Roger Chartier, Les Origines culturel
les de la Révolution

  française (1990), 138–66, and Timothy Tackett, Becoming a Revolutionary: The Deputies of the

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  303

  of 1771 designed to emasculate the Parlements, Jansenists rallied to the cause of

  popular representation and, in so doing, contributed to the elaboration of the

  ideology of national sovereignty and citizens’ rights that was to emerge on the eve of

  the Revolution.27 Accepted with qualification, each of these arguments lends

  support to Roger Chartier’s conclusion that Jansenism ‘drew upon religion to

  build a radical critique of both ecclesiastical and ministerial despotism that, in

  certain places at least, most notably Paris, accustomed people to distrust established

  authorities’.28

  Not surprisingly, there were those who suspected the Jansenists of preparing

  the way for the Revolution and, at worst, of actually instigating it.29 These are

  exaggerated claims, not least because they rest upon a misplaced characterization of

  Jansenism as an occult party or sect intent upon the destruction of religion.

  Nevertheless, a case can be made in defence of the argument that Jansenism

  did have a direct, if not decisive, influence upon the course of the Revolution.

  A considerable number of the clergy elected to represent their Estate in 1789 had

  Jansenist sympathies. One of these was the Abbé Grégoire, subsequently to achieve

  fame as the advocate of the ‘regeneration’ of the Jews and an opponent of slavery.30

  More significantly, and of grave consequence, the Jansenist contingent played a key

  role in driving through the legislation that established the Civil Constitution of the

  Clergy.31 As William Doyle has written of the latter: ‘Its hostility to the pope,

  subjection of bishops to election, and emphasis on the active role of the lay faithful,

  as well as a number of (now) lesser matters like the prohibition of formularies, were

  clearly of Jansenist inspiration.’32 Of course, the Revolution quickly outpaced its

  Jansenist supporters and it soon became apparent that many were far from happy

  to contemplate the consequences of their own actions. In effect, therefore, the

  Revolution killed off what remained of Jansenism and if, in subsequent years, it

  survived this was largely to be in the form of a spiritual ancestry dear to later

  French National Assembly and the Emergence of a Revolutionary Culture (1789–1790) (Princeton, NJ,

  1996), 102 and 304.

  27 Doyle, Jansenism, 83. See also Kley, ‘The Jansenist Constitutional Legacy in the French

  Prerevolution’, in Keith Michael Baker (ed.), The French Revolution and the Creation of Modern

  Political Culture, i. The Political Culture of the Old Regime (Oxford, 1987), 169–201; Kley, ‘Du parti

  janséniste au parti patriote (1770–1775)’, and Shanti-Marie Singham, ‘Vox populi vox Dei: Les

  Jansénistes pendant la révolution Maupeou’, in Maire, Jansénisme et Révolution, 115–30, 183–93.

  28 Chartier, Les Origines culturelles, 208. See also Jonathan Israel, Enlightenment Contested:

  Philosophy, Modernity and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752 (Oxford, 2006), 699–712. Israel,

  ibid. 710, quotes Diderot to the effect that the Jansenists did more to diminish respect for the Church

  and raise the prestige of philosophy than the philosophes did in the forty years prior to the publication of

  the first volume of the Encyclopédie.

  29 See Marcel Gauchet, ‘La Question du Jansénisme dans l’historiographie de la Révolution’, in

  Maire, Jansénisme et Révolution, 15–23.

  30 See Rita Hermon-Belot, L’Abbé Grégoire, la politique et la verité (2000); J. D. and R. H. Popkin

  (eds.), The Abbé Grégoire and his World (Dordrecht, 2000) and Alyssa Goldstein Sepinwall, The Abbé

  Grégoire and the French Revolution: The Making of Modern Universalism (Berkeley and Los Angeles,

  Calif., 2005).

  31 See Tackett, Becoming a Revolutionary , 290–1; Kley, Religious Origins, 353–60; and Maire,

  ‘Port Royal: The Jansenist Schism’, 333–4.

  32 Doyle, Jansenism, 83.

  304

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  republicans. The point, however, is that, for all that the Revolution came to

  constitute a fundamental challenge to the Church and to Christianity more

  generally, it is a mistake to conceive the relationship between the Revolution and

  Catholicism exclusively in terms of mutual antagonism.

  It is similarly a mistake to believe that Christianity was in principle hostile to

  science and that Catholicism in France remained untouched by the intellectual

  developments of the early modern period. If Jonathan Israel has insisted upon the

  need to pluralize our conception of the Enlightenment—from the very outset, he

  has argued, there were two enlightenments, one radical and one moderate main-

  stream33—then Helena Rosenblatt has suggested that we should be prepared to

  contemplate the existence of a Christian Enlightenment.34 There is evidence, she

  asserts, of a common commitment among those she describes as Enlightened

  Christians to embrace reasonableness, toleration, a relatively optimistic view of

  human nature, and a positive attitude towards reform and progress. These same

  people, she adds, ‘sought ways to reconcile their faith with the new sciences

  emerging in Europe’.35

  French Catholicism, as unlikely as it might seem, was no exception. Here too

  members of the Catholic community were receptive to science, shunned blind

  dogma, and defended religion in terms of its social usefulness. When, from the

  mid-eighteenth century onwards, Christians in France faced a growing challenge

  from deism and atheism some responded by adopting another vocabulary integral

  to the Enlightenment, that of sentiment and sensibility. Thus, to see France and her

  religious history in terms of a stark and irreconcilable division between secular

  philosophes and religious anti-philosophes is a gross over-simplification. As Rosenblatt

  concludes: ‘the boundaries between Enlightenment and counter-Enlightenment

  were, in fact, often blurred’.36

  The fact of the matter was, however, that from Voltaire onwards many of the

  French philosophes specialized in a particularly virulent and vitriolic form of anti-

  clerical and anti-religious polemic. In large part, this arose from the association of

  the Church with absolutism and with intolerance, an association given vivid

  substance by Louis XIV’s revocation of the Edict of Nantes and the subsequent

  departure into exile of over 200,000 French Protestants. The Church was an arm of

  the State and few opportunities, if any, were missed to publicize the persecutions

  and punishments meted out by organized religion. Held in particular opprobrium

  was a corrupt and self-seeking priesthood intent on keeping the faithful in a

  condition of credulous superstition and fear. Yet, even among the philosophes, the

  33 Israel, Enlightenment Contested, 11. Israel’s thesis is an explicit rejection of Peter Gay’s earlier

  claim that ‘there was only one Enlightenment’: see Gay, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation, i. The

  Rise of Modern Paganism (1973), 3. See also Margaret C. Jacob, The Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists,

  Freemasons and Republicans (London, 1981).

  34 Rosenblatt. ‘The Chri
stian Enlightenment’, in Brown and Tackett, Cambridge History of

  Christianity, vii. 283–301. See also Ann Thomson, Bodies of Thought: Science, Religion and the Soul

  in the Early Enlightenment (Oxford, 2008).

  35 Rosenblatt, ‘The Christian Enlightenment’, 284.

  36 Ibid. 290.

  Religion, Enlightenment, and Reaction

  305

  prevailing opinion was that religious faith, purged of idolatrous disfigurations,

  could be sustained by reason

  There is little need here to explore the details of this immense controversy,

  despite the obvious temptations provided by the work of the great teacher of doubt,

  the sometime Protestant Pierre Bayle.37 Suffice it to say that mainstream opinion

  was disinclined to accept Bayle’s contention that atheism was no greater evil than

  idolatry and that a society of atheists could be well-ordered and durable. Mon-

  tesquieu was a case in point. For all its naturalistic premises, De l’Esprit des lois

  affirmed that the Christian religion played a central role in preserving morality and

  maintaining the stability of society.38 ‘He who has no religion at all’, Montesquieu

  wrote, ‘is that terrible animal who feels his liberty only when it claws and

  devours.’39 Voltaire, perhaps surprisingly, was another. His Essai sur les moeurs of

  1745 denied that morality had been made known to us through either scriptural

  revelation or miraculous means but nevertheless concluded that it was divinely

  ordained. He wrote, for example, of the ‘fatal and invincible destiny by which the

  Supreme Being enchains all the events of the universe’.40 The slightly earlier

  Elements de la philosophie de Newton accepted the Newtonian ‘argument from

  design’ postulating the existence of a benign Deity who had created the world in

  accordance with mathematical principles. In brief, many philosophes, if they broke

  with Christian orthodoxy, were happy to embrace a form of deism and, as such,

  were prepared to believe that reason disclosed the mind of the Creator and that this

  Creator had instilled in our own minds knowledge of both his attributes and the

  fundamental principles of ethical life. Indeed, they tended to believe that, once

  religion had been stripped of the fraudulent accretions of the past, its essential and

 

‹ Prev