Pythagorus

Home > Other > Pythagorus > Page 32
Pythagorus Page 32

by Kitty Ferguson


  Except in the case of Giordano Bruno, whose offences by church standards were so flagrant and numerous that he would almost surely have been burned at the stake no matter where he thought the centre of the universe was, the Catholic church hierarchy had for centuries been rather sluggishly tolerant of new astronomical theories. Not a murmur was heard when Nicholas of Cusa, in the early fifteenth century, put the Earth in motion and removed it from the centre of the universe, nor when Copernicus published De revolutionibus in 1543. Two of Copernicus’ strongest supporters were prominent Catholic clergy. But in 1616, when both Galileo and his opponents were pushing the church for a ruling on the Copernican question, a decree was issued condemning the ‘new’ astronomy, though not actually calling it heresy – a technicality perhaps, but a victory for Galileo and the cardinals who supported him. In this decree, the Pythagoreans took an unfair hit:

  And whereas it has also come to the knowledge of the said Congregation that the Pythagorean doctrine – which is false and altogether opposed to the Holy Scripture – of the motion of the Earth and the immobility of the Sun, which is also taught by Nicolaus Copernicus . . . is now being spread abroad and accepted by many, as may be seen from a certain letter of a Carmelite Father.

  The Carmelite father who had put the Pythagoreans in the range of fire was the Reverend Father Paolo Antonio Foscarini. His letter, dated the year before the decree, was titled ‘On the Opinion of the Pythagoreans and of Copernicus Concerning the Motion of the Earth, and the Stability of the Sun, and the New Pythagorean System of the World’. Foscarini insisted this doctrine was ‘consonant with truth and not opposed to Holy Scripture’. The church’s ‘General Congregation of the Index’, which made official judgements on such matters, felt differently. Copernicus’ book De revolutionibus – seventy-three years after its publication – was ‘suspended until corrected’, and Foscarini’s work was ‘altogether prohibited and condemned’. It took seventeen more years of on-and-off sparring, and Galileo’s book Dialogo, for matters to come to a truly dangerous head in his famous trial. The Catholic church, for centuries the guardian and bastion of learning, had turned foolish to the point of malign senility and condemned herself and Italy – the ancient home of Pythagoras – to what was virtually a new scientific dark age. The centre of scientific endeavour and achievement moved, irretrievably, to northern Europe and England.

  As the scientific revolution continued north of the Alps in the mid-seventeenth century, Kepler’s three laws of planetary motion and his Rudolfine Tables, based on Tycho Brahe’s observations, rightly gave him his earthly immortality, but his polyhedral theory and most of Harmonice mundi were consigned to the cabinet of curiosities. No one took nested polyhedrons or cosmic chords and scales seriously or followed up on them as science. They had been the odd and unlikely midwives to Kepler’s ‘new astronomy’, helping birth the future, but in doing so had relegated themselves to the past. However, the conviction that numbers and harmony and symmetry were guides to truth because the universe was created according to a rational, orderly plan began to be treated as a given, trustworthy enough to underpin what would later be called the scientific method.

  No one was using the words ‘science’ or ‘scientific’ yet in their modern sense, but the process for determining what was and was not true about nature and the universe was continuing to evolve, and people were discussing and beginning to agree about how this process should work. The French scientist and philosopher René Descartes, one of the first to try to establish a solid foundation for human understanding of the world, chose mathematics as the only trustworthy road to sure knowledge.3 He tried to show that a single, united system of logical mathematical theory could account for everything that happens in the physical universe. Christiaan Huygens, Edmond Halley, and Isaac Newton all shared the conviction that when observations were inadequate, one could even with some confidence go out on a limb on the assumption that the universe is orderly, and discovering new examples of ‘order’ was beginning to be regarded as a sign that one was on the right track. Robert Hooke, in the field of biology, suggested that crystals like those that may have alerted the Pythagoreans to the existence of the five regular solids occurred because their atoms had an orderly arrangement.4 Robert Boyle wrote his book The Sceptical Chymist, which many identify as marking the beginning of modern chemistry, and cited Pythagoras, asserting that the final decisions of science must be made on the basis of both the evidence of the senses and the operation of reason. This balance, on which Kepler had performed such prodigious acrobatics as he struggled to write his Astronomia nova – without thinking of it as a ‘scientific method’ – was becoming the balance of science.

  Newton, born mid-century, capped off the Copernican revolution with his discovery of the laws of gravity and his 1687 book Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (‘Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy’), known as his Principia. A fervent believer in the harmony and order of the universe, he was convinced that the observable patterns in the cosmos were the visible manifestation of a profound, mysterious, underlying order. His theories of gravitation admirably supported the Pythagorean ideal of unity and simplicity. The same force, gravity, that kept the planets in orbit also dictated the trajectory of a ball thrown on Earth and kept human beings’ feet on the ground, and its laws could be stated in a simple formula. Though he was notoriously miserly about giving credit where credit was clearly due among his contemporaries, Newton, in an extraordinary gesture, wrote that his own famous law of universal gravitation could be found in Pythagoras. Nor was this the extent of Newton’s unusual attributions. He sought examples among the Greeks, the Hebrews, and other ancient thinkers, of ideas and discoveries that seemed – sometimes it was quite a stretch – to foreshadow his own. This was not modesty. Newton was by no means a modest man. It was more a way of elevating himself to the company of the greatest sages. Better than discovering something new was rediscovering knowledge that God had previously revealed only to extraordinary men of legendary wisdom. Newton thought of another link with Pythagoras when he used a prism and split the light of the Sun into seven colours. There were seven notes in the Pythagorean scale.5

  Gottfried Leibniz, Newton’s arch-rival and one of those contemporaries to whom Newton should have given considerably more credit, wrote in Pythagorean tones that ‘music is the pleasure the human soul experiences from counting without being aware that it is counting’.6 Leibniz tried to construct a universal language which had no words, that could express all human statements and resolve arguments in a completely unambiguous way, even, he hoped, bring into agreement all versions of Christian faith. His attempts to make good on this scheme included a use of numbers that would have pleased the Pythagoreans and annoyed Aristotle: ‘For example, if the term for an “animate being” should be imagined as expressed by the number 2, and the term for ‘rational’ by the number 3, the term for “man” will be expressed by the number 2×3, that is 6’.7

  Newton’s discoveries about gravity showed the cosmos seeming to operate like a stupendous, dependable mechanism, and, in the eighteenth century, scholars and amateur science aficionados picked up on that idea and became obsessed with mechanisms and machines. The demonstration of a new apparatus to explain or test a scientific principle was likely to cause more excitement than a lecture or a new theory at meetings of the Royal Society of London for Improving Natural Knowledge, or of the Birmingham ‘Lunar Men’ of Charles Darwin’s grandfather. It was the age of the ‘clockmaker’s universe’ and of England’s industrial revolution. Careful observation and experiment became the hallmark of science, but cautious generalisation was also encouraged, especially if it led to practical applications.

  In other ways, in the eighteenth century, the universe was failing to live up to its promise of simplicity. The Swedish botanist Carl Linnaeus was applying two-word Latin names to more and more species that travellers and voyagers to all corners of the world were discovering. Ther
e were a greater number than anyone had ever imagined. Linnaeus saw new plants in his garden, too, and began to suspect, a century before Darwin’s Origin of Species, that new species were emerging all the time. He decided that these had always existed in the mind of God but were just now coming into material existence, a very Platonic way of assuaging his religious scruples.

  Carl Linnaeus

  No one’s faith in the completeness of universal harmony and the power of numbers surpassed that of the French mathematician Pierre Simon de Laplace, whose lifetime spanned the turn of the eighteenth to the nineteenth century. For him, numbers and mathematics were an unshakably trustworthy bridge to the past and future – if one could know the exact state of everything in the universe at a given moment. His contention was that an omniscient being with that knowledge, with unlimited powers of memory and mental calculation, and with knowledge of the laws of nature, could extrapolate from that the exact state of everything in the universe at any other given moment.

  Meanwhile, Pythagorean themes appeared in other than scientific settings. The Whig party praised the governmental structure which brought together king and Parliament by means of ‘natural’ laws, with these words:

  What made the planets in such Order move,

  He said, was harmony and mutual Love.

  The Musick of his Spheres did represent

  That ancient Harmony of Government.

  That was by no means an isolated allusion. The harmony of the heavens had become a beloved poetic image. William Shakespeare, a contemporary of Galileo and Kepler, had given it beautiful expression in The Merchant of Venice, where he had Lorenzo tell Jessica,

  . . . soft stillness and the night

  Become the touches of sweet harmony . . .

  Look how the floor of heaven

  Is thick inlaid with patines of bright gold;

  There’s not the smallest orb which thou behold’st

  But in his motion like an angel sings.

  Such harmony is in immortal souls;

  But, whilst this muddy vesture of decay

  Doth grossly close it in, we cannot hear it.

  Shakespeare’s contemporary John Davies had written a ‘justification of dance’ titled ‘Orchestra’ that was full of such allusions – not only to the celestial music but also to the four elements. Davies was not making a scientific or philosophical statement. He was correcting one lady’s disparagement of dancing by pointing to its ancient, primordial origins.

  Dancing, bright lady, then began to be

  When the first seeds whereof the world did spring,

  The fire, air, earth and water did agree,

  By Love’s persuasion, nature’s mighty king,

  To leave their first disordered combating

  And in a dance such measure to observe

  As all the world their motion should preserve.

  . . . . .

  The turning vault of heaven formed was,

  Whose starry wheels he hath so made to pass

  As that their movings do a music frame

  And they themselves still dance unto the same.

  . . . . .

  All the world’s great fortunes and affairs

  Forward and backward rapt and whirled are

  According to the music of the spheres.

  John Milton, a later contemporary of Galileo and Kepler, like Shakespeare referred to the inability of human ears to hear this music:

  But else in deep of night when drowsiness

  Hath locked up mortal sense, then listen I

  To the celestial Sirens’ harmony . . .

  Such sweet compulsion doth in music lie,

  To lull the daughters of Necessity,

  And keep unsteady Nature to her law,

  And the low world in measured motion draw

  After the heavenly tune, which none can hear

  Of human mould with gross unpurged ear.

  Another Englishman, John Dryden, born in 1631, the year after Kepler died, like Davies gave music a voice in creation:

  From harmony, from heavenly harmony,

  This universal frame began:

  When Nature underneath a heap

  Of jarring atoms lay

  And could not heave her head,

  The tuneful voice was heard from high:

  Arise, ye more than dead!

  Joseph Addison, born later in the century, was the author of a poem that combined the ideas expressed in Psalm 19 with the image of the music of the spheres. Christian congregations still sing it, to music by Franz Joseph Haydn. The final verse says of the planets:

  What though in solemn silence all move round the dark terrestrial ball?

  What though no real voice nor sound amid their radiant orbs be found?

  In reason’s ear they all rejoice, and utter forth a glorious voice:

  Forever singing as they shine, ‘The hand that made us is divine.’8

  Johannes Kepler (and nearly everyone who has sung this hymn) would have disagreed with the Earth-centred cosmos these lines implied, but Kepler himself – who had imagined the planets arranged in perfect harmony at the moment of creation – could not have put it better. His harmony was a harmony audible to ‘reason’s ear’. Even a century after Addison, William Wordsworth, whose lifetime spanned the turn of the century from the 1700s to the 1800s, could still be certain no explanation or footnote was required when he wrote of ‘harmony from Heaven’s remotest spheres’.

  Pythagorean ideas and traces of the Pythagorean tradition also showed up in more surprising contexts. One of the most bizarre examples was the reimagining, in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, of Pythagoras as the hero of intellectual revolutionaries in Europe and Russia. This use, or misuse, of Pythagorean themes was brought to light by James H. Billington in his book Fire in the Minds of Men: Origins of the Revolutionary Faith.9 Billington showed that in the midst of confusion, when nothing was stable and dependable, Pythagoras became an icon of revolution, and his name and the ideals and symbols associated with him ran as leitmotifs through the decades of revolution and revolutionary thinking.

  In 1776, the year of the American Declaration of Independence and eleven years before the date usually identified as the beginning of the French Revolution, a group in Bavaria founded by one Adam Weishaupt and recruited from the Masonic lodges in Munich was calling itself ‘Illuminist’. Though ‘Illuminism’ was difficult for anyone at the time (or today) to define, for Weishaupt it meant a ‘revolution of the mind’, discarding and avoiding all ‘spiritualist distortions’ and occult practices and ideas. However, the name and concepts vaguely associated with Illuminism predated Weishaupt, and so, probably, did the connection with Pythagoras. Because Illuminists were usually as secretive as Pythagoras and his earliest followers, many questions about them cannot be answered, and a danger of being a secret society is that your popular and historical image may be created not by yourself but by your most vocal and influential enemies. Some credited the Illuminists with almost single-handedly precipitating the French Revolution. Others said they never really existed at all but were a ‘police myth’ conjured up by rightists to inspire public fear of clandestine plots, a myth half believed by the authorities themselves. Others assert that they were a fictional invention of propagandists who opposed Masonry and tried to tarnish its image by associating it with insurrection and revolution. Yet others claim that they were an extreme branch of Masonry, or something independent that ‘infected’ Masonry. The Masons also were intensely secretive, though not necessarily for the same reasons the Illuminists were.

  At the time of Columbus there were ‘Alumbrados’ in Spain whose mysticism centred around the idea that a human soul could be subjected to inner purification leading to complete submission to God’s
will and direct communication with and through the Holy Spirit. Eighteenth-century Illuminists also emphasised inner perfection and purification, but with a secular stress on reason and logic. This ideology, Billington writes, either first appeared in lodges of the Freemasons and other Masonic orders, such as Weishaupt’s in Bavaria, or else found fertile ground there and rapidly took over. For Masons, working towards inner perfection and purification was already central to their teaching, and it was also attractive to see themselves as re-creating an ancient brotherhood. In fact, it must have been difficult for a member of a Masonic lodge to know whether he was merely taking part in an inspiring ceremony full of ancient symbols, or dealing with something that really was supposed to have supernatural power, or fomenting revolution – or what, if any, of this made him an ‘Illuminist’. How much more difficult for anyone looking from the outside! Not only was there ‘fire in the minds of men’; there was also considerable confusion. The Illuminist slant, however, does seem to have been that the road to perfection and purification could and should be taken not only by individuals but by human societies. Had not Pythagoras engineered a marvellous reconstruction of society in Croton? However, Illuminists believed that this time, in the eighteenth century, the process was going to require enormous upheaval and the violent overthrow of existing authority.

 

‹ Prev