Ancient Philosophy

Home > Nonfiction > Ancient Philosophy > Page 13
Ancient Philosophy Page 13

by Julia Annas


  Ancient philosophy is so varied that there is no good detailed history of the entire tradition by a single author. A very brief introduction is T. Irwin, Classical Thought (Oxford, 1989). Also good is C. Gill, Greek Thought (Oxford, 1995). W. K. C. Guthrie’s six-volume History of Greek Philosophy (Cambridge, 1962–1981), ends at Aristotle and is uncritical, but is a good guide to sources. Histories of ancient philosophy have for some time taken the form of studies of particular philosophies or issues, rather than a single narrative of the whole tradition. Many can be found in the bibliographies of the works mentioned below.

  A introductory reader, with texts arranged round issues rather than chronologically, is Julia Annas, Ancient Voices of Philosophy (Oxford, 2000). A more comprehensive reader for advanced students, also arranged topically, is Terence Irwin, Classical Philosophy (Oxford, 1999).

  Chapters on philosophy at various periods can be found in the Oxford History of the Classical World (Oxford, 1986). Excellent reference works are the Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd edition (Oxford, 1996), and The Encyclopaedia of Classical Philosophy, ed. Don Zeyl (Westport, 1996).

  The forthcoming multi-author Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy and Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political Thought are good guides to the areas they cover.

  An extremely useful series is the Cambridge Companions to Ancient Thought, edited by Stephen Everson. These are Epistemology (1990), Psychology (1991), Language (1994) and Ethics (1998).

  Notes

  The Notes mention only authors and topics not covered in the Further Reading.

  Chapter 1

  Euripides’ play is available in many modern translations. The Epictetus passages are Discourses I 28 and II 17; many modern translations are available. Plato’s account of the divided soul can be found in Books 4 and 9 of the Republic, and in Phaedrus, especially 244–257; also in parts of Timaeus. Galen’s comments are from his On the doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato III 3; there is a translation in the Corpus Medicorum Graecorum, the collected texts and translations of Greek medical writers. For further explorations of this theme in ancient philosophy see A. Price, Mental Conflict (Oxford, 1995), and C. Gill, Personality in Greek Epic, Tragedy and Philosophy (Oxford, 1996), especially Chapters 3 and 4.

  Chapter 2

  The case for seeing the Republic as primarily an ethical work, as in the ancient tradition, is developed in Chapter 4 of Julia Annas, Platonic Ethics Old and New (Ithaca, 1999).

  There has been extensive work on the impact of ancient Greek culture on the Victorians, but there is little good on ancient philosophy. Of the available books, the best is Frank Turner, The Greek Heritage in Victorian Britain (New Haven, 1981); see also his article, ‘Why the Greeks and not the Romans in Victorian Britain?’ in G. W. Clarke (ed.), Rediscovering Hellenism: the Hellenic inheritance and the English imagination (Cambridge, 1989).

  On the role of the Utilitarians see Kyriakos Demetriou, ‘The Development of Platonic Studies in Britain and the Role of the Utilitarians’, Utilitas 8 (1996). Two excellent articles are John Glucker, ‘Plato in England: the Nineteenth Century and After’, in H. Funke (ed.), Utopie und Tradition: Platons Lehre vom Staat in der Moderne (Würzburg, 1987) and ‘The Two Platos of Victorian Britain’ in K. Algra et al. (eds.), Polyhistor (Leiden, 1996).

  I have considered England; for the early American tradition see Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics (Cambridge MA, 1994). The European tradition differs between countries and is highly complex: see the papers in Ada Neschke-Hentschke (ed.), Images de Platon et Lectures de ses Oeuvres: les interprétations de Platon à travers les siècles (Louvain-Paris, 1997.

  Grote’s Plato and John Stuart Mill’s long review of it are still richly rewarding; see Mill’s Collected Works, vol XI (Toronto, 1978).

  The quotations from Popper are from The Open Society and its Enemies, vol 1 (London, 1945). John Wild’s book was published in Chicago in 1953. Whitehead’s very famous remark is from Process and Reality (Cambridge, 1929), Part 2, chapter 1, section 1. The History of the University of Oxford is edited by T. Aston, and the quotation is from p. 529 of vol. 5, The Eighteenth Century (Oxford, 1986).

  Chapter 3

  Xenophon’s story comes from his Memorabilia (Reminiscences of Socrates), Book II, 1. Evidence for the sophists’ ideas can be found in R. McKirahan’s Philosophy before Socrates (Indianapolis, 1994). Ancient eudaimonist theories are set out and discussed in Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (Oxford, 1993). Aristotle’s major theoretical discussion of happiness is in Book 1 of the Nicomachean Ethics. The views of Epicurus and the Stoics on happiness are best studied in books 1–4 of Cicero’s On Moral Ends (De Finibus); see the English translation by Raphael Woolf (Cambridge, 2001).

  Chapter 4

  On Socrates see Christopher Taylor’s Socrates (Oxford. 1998), an excellent short introduction. Socrates’ own account of the oracle is in the Apology. Socrates served as the symbolic figure of the ideal philosopher for most ancient schools; the Epicureans are the main exception; for them the ideal philosopher should be as serious and unironic as Epicurus. Plato’s most elaborate account of knowledge is in the central books of the Republic; his attacks on relativism, and indications of his concern with empirical knowledge, are in the Theaetetus. Aristotle’s discussion of the structure of a science is in the difficult Posterior Analytics; see also the opening chapters of Books 1 and 2 of the Metaphysics for his account of the development of knowledge, and Parts of Animals, Book 1, chapter 5, for a defence of studying widely differing kinds of subject-matter. An indispensable introduction to the wide range of ancient theories of knowledge is S. Everson (ed.), Epistemology (Cambridge, 1990).

  Chapter 5

  For Aristotle’s logic see Robin Smith’s translation of the Prior Analytics (Indianapolis, 1989) and his chapter in the Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, ed. J. Barnes (Cambridge, 1995). There is unfortunately no good English translation of the sources for Stoic logic; see the relevant sections of Inwood and Gerson, and of Long and Sedley. The sources are collected in Karlheinz Hülser, Die Fragmente der Dialektiker der Stoiker, 4 vols (Stuttgart, 1987).

  On Hellenistic science see G. Lloyd, Greek Science after Aristotle (London, 1973). For clear introductions to Aristotle’s metaphysics and philosophy of science see the chapters in the Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. There is little sustained philosophical discussion of Stoic and Epicurean metaphysics; there is, by contrast, a huge literature on Plato’s ‘theory of Forms’: see the Cambridge Companion to Plato.

  Chapter 6

  The Further Reading gives suggestions for following up the history of ancient philosophy. The quotation from Martin West is from ‘Early Greek Philosophy’ in The Oxford History of Greece and the Hellenistic World, (Oxford, 1986). The comment that Plato is just Moses in Greek is fragment 8 of Numenius, a second-century Platonist who tended to see all Great Ideas in different cultures as being the same. Eusebius, in X 1 and XI 1 of his Preparation for the Gospel, claims more strongly that Greek philosophy steals all its ideas from the Jewish scriptures. The contrasting quotations about the nature of the beginnings of Greek philosophy are from John Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy (London, 1892) pp. v, 13, 28, and from Francis Cornford, Principium Sapientiae: a study of the origins of Greek philosophical thought (Cambridge, 1952) pp. 154–155.

  Index

  A

  Academy, the xiv, 5, 75, 107

  style of argument 57, 71–2, 102–3

  ad hominem argument 62–3, 71, 102

  Anaxagoras of Clazomenae xiii, 99, 113

  Anaximander xii, 96, 97, 113

  Anaximenes xii, 96, 113

  ancient Greece see Greek city-states

  animals 9–10, 80, 83–6, 88–9

  anthropocentrism 86, 89, 98

  Antiochus 106, 113

  anti-schools 107–8

  Antisthenes xiii, 57, 113

  appearances 38, 69–70, 73–4, 78

  Arcesilaus 113

  Archimed
es 80, 113

  arete 47

  Arete 44

  argument (reasoned) 37, 76, 82, 104–5

  as a means to knowledge 27, 62–3, 72, 78, 100–3

  criticized 44, 108, 110–11

  in ancient tradition xi, 11, 17, 19, 96

  Aristippus xiii, 36, 44, 57, 113

  ethics 43, 46

  Aristippus the Younger 44

  Aristotelian syllogisms 77

  Aristotle xiii, 22, 26, 92, 113

  and Middle Ages 90–1, 93

  ethics 41–2, 49–52, 53, 118

  influence of 15–16, 19, 75, 104–5

  logic and epistemology 65–7, 76–8, 119

  metaphysics 80–1, 82, 85, 96

  astronomy 80

  Athens 19, 24, 58, 107–8

  Atlantis 25

  Atomism xiii, 44, 99

  Atticus 52

  Augustine xiv, 113

  authority xii, 44, 91, 93

  axiomata 78

  B

  beautiful, the 82

  Berkeley, George (Bishop) 93

  bogus philosopher 104, 112

  Buddhism 68, 111

  Burnet, John 98, 120

  Byzantine Empire 19, 108

  C

  canon 19, 35, 110

  Carneades 113

  causes (Aristotelian) 81, 84, 85

  certainty 64

  Chaerephon 56

  change 80, 83, 98–9

  character 47–8

  charioteer 9, 10

  children 26, 28

  choice 4–5, 41, 52

  Choice of Heracles 36, 38–9, 42, 46–7, 53

  Christianity xiv, 19, 94, 109–10

  ancient philosophy in 26, 88, 90–1

  Chryssipus of Soli 3, 4, 113

  Cicero 113, 119

  Colotes 60

  common good 24, 25, 28

  common sense 57, 66, 73, 97–9

  ethics 42, 49

  psychology 3, 5, 9–10

  complexity 88

  conservativism 53

  context (historical) 33–4, 91, 93, 110

  of readers 18, 20–2, 33–4

  contingency see random events

  Cooper, Anthony Ashley 38

  Cornford, Francis 98, 120

  cosmology 81, 82, 85, 87–90, 95–6

  craft see expertise

  creator 87, 88

  culture 29, 53, 56, 65

  ancient 2, 89, 103–5, 112

  curriculum 75–6, 79

  Cynicism xiii, xiv, 57, 107–8

  Cyrenaics 43, 44

  D

  Dante 91

  Darwin, Charles 86, 88

  deductions (Aristotelian) 76–7

  Delacroix, Eugene 12, 13

  deliberate action 1, 7, 10, 12

  de Matteis, Paolo 38

  democracy 24, 28, 29

  Democritus of Abdera xiii, 44, 99, 101, 113

  design see teleological explanation

  desire 6, 8–9, 42

  dialectic 102–3

  dialogue form 5, 22, 102, 104

  Diogenes of Sinope 107, 113

  disagreement 11, 16–17, 42, 72, 101

  and relativism 33, 72

  discussion see argument

  dogmatism 68, 70, 71

  E

  Eastern philosophy 68, 110–11

  eclectic schools 105–6

  economic activity 24, 28, 80

  education 25, 28–9, 103–4, 112

  Egypt 20, 94, 95, 107

  elitism 24, 29, 53

  emotions xi, 1–9, 10–11, 16, 48

  Empedocles of Acragas xiii, 99, 113

  empiricism 73, 74, 111

  England 26, 27–9

  Epictetus 3, 51, 113, 117

  on inner conflict 10, 45

  Epicureans 19, 74, 81, 103, 119

  Epicurus of Athens xii, 20, 22, 44, 113

  epistemology and physics 73–4, 78, 89–90

  in philosophical schools 101, 103–5

  view of happiness 45–6, 48, 118–19

  epistemology 55, 62, 76, 119

  ancient approach distinctive 56–8, 71–2, 74

  ethics 40–1, 47–8, 50, 53

  hedonistic 43, 45

  in Republic 29, 32

  Euclid 63, 64, 80

  eudaimonism 41, 46, 53, 118

  Euripides see Medea

  Eusebius 95, 120

  excellence 47

  experience 78, 82, 98–9

  as a source of knowledge 64–5, 73–4, 87

  pleasure as an 42–3

  expertise 51, 56, 58–9

  as a model for knowledge 63–5, 67, 72

  explanation 2, 11–12, 15–16, 96–9

  and knowledge 59, 62

  in Aristotle 66–7, 81, 3, 84–6

  external goods 49–50, 51–2

  F

  family life 25, 26

  fascism 29, 31, 32

  final causes 84, 85

  first principles 63–4, 66–7

  formal argument 65, 77, 78

  Forms, the 25, 65, 81, 82, 119

  Frege, Gottlob 79

  function 83, 84, 85, 86

  G

  Galen 10–11, 12, 117

  Garden, the 44, 105

  geometry 63, 65–6

  see also mathematics

  giving an account 62–3, 67–8, 74, 100

  see also explanation

  God 87, 88, 90, 98

  gods 44, 57, 89, 97

  Great Thinkers 17, 110

  Greek city-states 19, 28, 117

  Grote, George 27

  Guardians 24, 25, 28–9, 32

  gymnosophists 68

  H

  happiness 38, 40–2, 104, 112

  and virtue 25, 49–50, 51–2

  hedonist accounts of 36, 43, 45–6, 81

  hedonism 43, 44, 46, 57

  Hellenistic philosophy xiii–xiv, 5, 79–80, 119

  texts lost 20, 22

  Heraclitus of Ephesus xii-xiii, 97, 113

  Herculaneum 20

  Heron of Alexandria 80

  Hippias of Elis xiii, 37

  I

  ideal society 24, 28–30, 31

  as a model for the soul 25, 32

  Idealism (British) 27, 29

  India 68, 111

  induction 74, 78

  inner conflict 6–10

  interpretation xii, 12, 18, 20

  challenges of 22–3, 27, 33–4, 93

  investigation 27, 63, 65, 98

  empirical 79–80, 84, 93, 96

  sceptical 67–9, 70

  Islamic tradition 26

  J

  Jowett, Benjamin 27–9, 30

  Judaism 90, 94, 95, 109

  justification 55, 64, 74

  Justinian (Emperor) 108–9

  K

  Kant, Immanuel 51, 52, 79

  knowledge 15–16, 63–5, 93, 95

  conditions on 43, 55–9, 69–72, 78

  empirical 66–7, 79–81, 83–4, 119

  see also explanation

  L

  Laws 26, 32

  Leucippus xiii, 99

  literature 25, 102–3

  living by appearances 69–70

  logic 76–9

  logon didonai 62

  logos 62, 97

  Ludan of Samosata 111

  M

  Madhyamika school 111

  Marcus Aurelius 3, 51

  materialism 19, 111

  mathematics 63–4, 66, 80, 82

  matter 80, 84–5, 87, 96

  Medea 1, 12–14

  explanations of 2–4, 7, 10

  medicine 80

  Meletus 58

  meritocracy 28, 32

  metaphysics 29, 80–1, 119

  see also cosmology

  Middle Ages 19, 26, 77, 79

  and Aristotle 90–1, 93

  middle term 77

  Mill, John Stuart 27, 40, 60, 83, 118

  misfortune 25, 50, 51

  modal logic 77

  Mos
es 95, 120

  mysticism xii, 19, 110, 111

  N

  Nagarjuna 111

  nature 81, 83–4, 89–90, 108

  necessity 76

  Neoplatonism xiv, 27, 107

  nineteenth century 26, 28–30, 118

  non-moral value 51

  Numenius of Apamea 95, 120

  O

  observation 66, 74, 87

  see also experience

  oracle at Delphi 56, 58, 119

  originality 95, 106, 120

  P

  paradoxes xiii, 3, 98–9

  Parmenides xiii, 98, 113

  Parmenides 82

  passion see emotions

  Phaedo 82

  Phaedrus 9

  Philodemus 21, 74

  philosopher-kings 24, 25, 30

  philosophia 94

  philosophos 58

  philosophy xi, 11, 24, 84, 91

  a distinct way of thinking 37, 64–5, 102–3

  and disagreement 11, 33, 94

  as a subject 24, 101, 75, 104–6, 112

  history of xii-xiv, 5, 22, 100, 108–11

  in Graeco-Roman world 2, 56, 94–8, 120

  transmission of texts 18–20, 22–3, 27, 33–4

  phronesis 48

  physics 79–81, 84

  Plato xiii–xiv, 22, 37, 57, 110, 113

  as a systematic thinker 75–6, 101–4

  cosmology 81, 82, 87

  epistemology 50, 63–5, 72, 119

  political thought 26, 32

  psychology 5, 6–11, 15, 117

  Republic 24, 25, 27–9, 33–4

  Platonism 5, 102, 108

  pleasure 38, 40–3, 45–6, 48

  Plotinus xiv, 107, 113

  Popper, Karl 30, 31, 118

  popular religion 88

  Posterior Analytics 65, 66

  post-modernism 33

 

‹ Prev