Nordic Ideology

Home > Other > Nordic Ideology > Page 55
Nordic Ideology Page 55

by Hanzi Freinacht


  But another group of people scoff at these eager and arrogant develop­mentalists and ascenders. The issue is not to “go somewhere” or to “be­come someone” or to “develop”—it is to come home, to return to some­thing basic and fundamental within us, to just be, to rest with the here-and-now, to stop trying to control and steer anything, least of all history. We don’t need to aim for the sun, just be ourselves, just be simple. We must come closer to our nature, to what is real, to the authentic child that we really are. We can let go of all those egoic strivings, all those lofty ideas and ideals, of all ideo­logy and metamodernism schmetamodernism.

  Which one of these two perspectives is true, then—ascenders or desc­enders—those who seek to climb and develop or those who seek to stay simple and direct and simply be? You know the answer already. It is both and.

  We must grow and we must come home; we must both travel and stay; we must be both sincere and ironic. We both “must” and “not must” any­thing at all. We must grow up to become the children we always-already are . And political metamodernism must facilitate and make poss­ible the emergence of settings in which we can swarm as children.

  In the year 1212—in an event at the crossroads of fact and fiction, one that may not have taken place but has been told as true over the centu­ries—nearly 50,000 European boys and girls are said to have rebelled against their parents and the Church to join a crusade to the Holy Land; to win by love what their fathers had failed to take by force. But before they even reached Rome nearly all of them had fallen to hardship. Those who went on would pay for their innocent courage in brothels and slave markets. [151]

  The time was not ripe for a Children’s Crusade, for the naive will of swarms of idealistic warriors to commit their playful souls for the better­ment of the world by spiritual struggle. And yet that is, ultimately, what must happen. We don’t need tough and “mature” men, but playful boys and girls, just as Nietzsche said it. Human beings who are in love with life itself—and with glittering, gleaming faith and iron resolve in the face of utter meaninglessness.

  The world is maintained by men, it is reproduced by women—but it is created by children. By kids on mischievous adventures. What is the core principle of humanity if not the extension of childhood?

  In nature, maturity is the rule and childhood the exception. Childhood is rare. It is chosen. It has not yet paid the price of maturity: stagnation, ossification. It is fresh­ness, it is growth, it is movement, it is speed and exhilaration, it is higher freedom and deeper equality. As an animal rights advocate, I am all for caring about adults; they too have feelings. But in the last instance, this is a child’s world.

  Make no mistake—our world will be conquered, ruled and transfor­med by an army of children. Our struggle-reborn-as-play must con­tinue until reality itself has shifted, until a mill­ion complexly interrelated situa­tions have chan­ged, until what is writt­en on our banners has been inscri­bed into the constitutions of all countries and governing bodies of the world.

  And what is written on our banners is, ultimately, what is always-already written in our hearts: solidarity with all sentient beings, across all of space-time, from all possible perspectives, from the greatest depths of our love.

  Or do you have anything better to do?

  Appendix A:

  WHY COMMUNISM FAILED

  Welcome to Appendix A—why communism failed. Did you read through the book and found yourself hungry for more? Or did the red scare creep up on you so that you needed to calm your mind by finding out just how exactly this Hanzi Freinacht argues against comm­un­ism?

  Either way, please take a deep breath and chant the following hymn of utopia:

  “ Beasts of England, Beasts of Ireland,

  Beasts of every land and clime,

  Hearken to my joyful tidings

  Of the Golden future time.

  Soon or late the day is coming,

  Tyrant Man shall be o’erthrown,

  And the fruitful fields of England

  Shall be trod by beasts alone.

  Rings shall vanish from our noses,

  And the harness from our back,

  Bit and spur shall rust forever,

  Cruel whips no more shall crack.”

  The poem goes on for a while after that, and it gets even better. You know where it is from, don’t you?

  Although it might be imagined as a tune of insurgency against today’s factory farming, it’s actually the anthem from George Orwell’s Ani­mal Farm —the fable in which the animals take over a farm and run it them­selves under the banner: All ani­mals are equal.

  You may recall that Old Major, an aged hog, teaches this song, “Beasts of England”, to the other animals before he dies; the whispers of a pro­m­ised revolution. And suddenly, shortly after, the opportunity for a revol­ution presents itself. Farmer Jones is driven from the land—and so the fields are trod by beasts alone. But, as the story goes, the scheming pig Comrade Napoleon seizes po­w­er and the ideals of the revolution are perverted, one by one, until the small pig elite finally declare that all animals are equal, yes, but some animals are “more equal than others”.

  Of course, Orwell wrote this as a commentary on the Soviet revo­lu­tion and the communist experiment. The Russian revolutionaries had been wary of “Bonapartism” in the early days of the Soviet Union, i.e. that some­one might snatch the momentum and take charge as dictator, like Nap­oleon Bonaparte had done in the wake of the French Revolution. Few sus­pected that the quiet and reserved Joseph Stalin was a Nap­oleon in disguise (which, undoubtedly, is what Orwell hinted at when he named the dictator-pig in Animal Farm ).

  I’m bringing this topic up—the communist experiment—because my own work on “political metamodernism” and “the Nordic Ideology” in­ev­itably gets compared to communism. The failure of communism is also a fruitful place to initiate a deeper discussion about political metamodern­ism.

  Although it is not a comparison I am entirely comfortable with, it is not irrele­vant. There is a kind of post-Marxist undercurrent in much of metamodern think­ing: to see society as evolving through discern­able sta­ges, and the curr­ent capitalist global society as one such stage, to relate to the totality of human experience and try to generate a more ratio­nal and existentially sound foundation for it, to want to develop not only society but also our inner lives and emotions, to strive for higher forms of free­dom, fairness and solidarity. Hey, I even named this book Nordic Ide­ology with an ironic wink at Marx and Engels’ The German Ideology.

  But if there is a vague spiritual lineage connecting political metamoder­nism to communism, it is only just that: a vague, spiritual link on a gene­ral and abstract level.

  So let me highlight some key differences be­tween my thinking and the many strands of Marxism. Let us begin by asking why communism failed, and what perspectives might be needed in its place.

  Don’t Blame Comrade Napoleon

  What went wrong with the Soviet Union and the com­munist revolution can hardly be said to hinge upon the wrongdoings or moral flaws of any single person like Joseph Stalin.

  Or Vladimir Lenin, for that matter. It’s true that Lenin represented a kind of authoritarian dev­iation from mainstream Marxist socialism, but it is also a fact that the only kind of socialist system (in name if nothing else) that has ever existed on any larger scale has been of the authoritarian bent. If you list all of the libertarian socialists, anarchists and left-wing Marxists, these are all theorists and philosophers. If you list the leading authorita­rian soc­ialists, these are all real leaders with real power. Coincidence?

  It’s not a coincidence. Some people like to say that “real socialism has never been tried”. But as you’ll see in the following, it has never been tried because it has never been possible in the first place. And this impossibility is exactly what has derailed all real attempts at socialism.

  Let’s go on with the story. Lenin’s doctrine which guided the 1917 rev­olution (or c
oup) was an authoritarian dev­iation of the ideals of sociali­sm, effectively banning worker control of factories and discarding other socialist elem­ents, and the other Bolshevik leader, Leon Trotsky, soon followed suit in this elitist top-down per­spective.

  Lenin died in 1924, Stalin took over and from there on it was mounting tot­alitarianism and violent oppression in spades, culminating in the 1937-38 Great Purge. If Stalin hadn’t won the power stru­ggle, other and similar problems had still been likely to occur. Stalin’s con­test­ant Trotsky (whose Orwellian pig alter ego is called Snowball) was even crazier. He was more optimi­stic about a communist revolution in Ger­many (and less opti­mistic about Stalin’s “soc­ial­ism in one country”) and would thus have been likely to have ado­pted a blatantly aggressive foreign policy—more wars, more peo­ple killed. Trotsky also had a more radical vision of the malleability of the human mind; that everyone could become Aristotle—an exceedingly dan­gerous and cult-like idea. Quoting Trotsky himself:

  “It is difficult to predict the extent of self-government which the man of the future may reach or the heights to which he may carry his technique. Social construction and psycho-physical self-education will become two aspects of one and the same process. All the arts—literature, drama, painting, music and architecture will lend this process beautiful form. More correctly, the shell in which the cultural construction and self-education of Communist man will be enclosed, will develop all the vital elements of contemporary art to the highest point. Man will become immeasurably stronger, wiser and subtler; his body will become more harmonized, his movements more rhyth­mic, his voice more musical. The forms of life will become dyna­mically dramatic. The average human type will rise to the heights of an Ari­stotle, a Goethe, or a Marx. And above this ridge new peaks will rise.” [152]

  There’s an interesting tension here: On the one hand, Trotsky appr­oa­ches some of the metamodern developmental perspectives, seeing the hu­m­an being as a project of playful self-recreation; on the other hand, he falls into the traps of utopianism (the non-relative kind) and idealizing his own image of what a good human being would be like. He didn’t realize that the only credible form of utopia is relative, and he never referred to any sound theories of psycho­logical devel­opment. He simply believed that once a socialist society had been achieved, then a new and better human­ity would emerge and a just social order would come into being once and for all. Consequently, everything became a means to this impossible end; “After all”, the zealous revolutionary would think, “what’s a few millions deaths if that’s the price of achieving an absolute utopian ideal?” This, of course, puts one on a path to totalitarian­ism. We must thus stay clear of the mistakes rep­re­sented by Trotsky and others like him. These are dan­gerous intellectual waters we are cross­ing.

  Present-day Marxists often say that critics of Marx have failed to grasp the depth and entirety of Marx’s writings, in particular the three volumes of his magnum opus , Capital . But if you read the writings of Lenin, Trotsky and Stalin, there can be little doubt they knew their Marx very well. And if you read e.g. Simon Sebag Montefiore’s bio­graph­ies on Stalin, it is app­arent that even Stalin was very intellectually gifted: rea­ding Dar­win at thirteen in one sitting, becoming an acclaimed poet at 16, master­­minding an impressive bank robbery at 29, and managing an in­credibly large and diverse workload as military leader and head of state—all while producing writings that were not necessarily innovative, but cer­tainly well written and incisive. For instance, you have Dialectical and Historical Materi­alism , in which he relates to not only Marxist doctrine but also a wider philosophical canon including Hegel, Kant, Feuerbach and others. As such, I seriously doubt a better and more detailed reading of Marx is the solution to the problems of Marxism, communism and soc­ialism.

  As you may know, Trotsky was eventually murdered on Stalin’s orders by a Soviet agent with an icepick to the head in Mexico City. But com­munism was doomed to fail long before this. Trotsky wouldn’t have saved the communist experiment. Nor would Lenin, had his health been better.

  So don’t blame Comrade Napoleon. Let’s find out what really went wrong.

  The Mainstream/Libertarian Account

  What then can account for the structural failure of the communist pro­ject, as viewed altogether? Well, in all places where you see communism (or “socia­list” states claiming to attempt to achieve full communism, which is when the state itself has been rendered obsolete), there are one-party sys­tems, human rights abuses, limits to civil liberties and severe problems with the eco­n­omy—as recent relapses in Venezuela re­mind us. These soc­ie­ties sim­ply don’t last; their social sustainability is severely limited.

  I suppose you’ve heard the common wisdom response? “Communism was not just a nice idea that turned out to be terrible in prac­tice—it was a terrible idea that was consequently (and predictably) terrible in practice!” All mainstream critiques of communism argue along these lines, more or less. This holds true from the more sophisticated versions, like in the Polish philo­sopher Leszek Kołakowski’s meticulous studies [153] of the inhe­rent flaws of Marxism, over Karl Popper’s The Open Society and Its Ene­mies , to Nobel Prize winner Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn’s massive, intense literary mas­ter­piece The Gulag Archi­pelago , which derives the horrors of comm­unist forced labor camps directly from Marxist-Leninist doctrines.

  This line of argument (often put forth by libertarians and conserva­tives, but increasingly by everyone) holds—more or less explicitly—that comm­unism was a mistake be­cause it failed, morally and intel­lect­ually, to under­stand human nature it­self . This is the case even in Solzhenitsyn’s exist­en­tialist account.

  According to the libertarian mainstream account, humans are not coll­ectivist beings who value equal­ity over all—so the argu­ment goes—they are freedom-loving individuals who need to find their own paths in life in order to find meaning and dignity. As such they must be allowed to com­pete on free markets, serving them­selves first—in fair exchanges with one another, where goods and respect are earned by hard work and good cha­r­acter. They must reap the rewards of ind­ividual action, of innovation, of reason­able and free competition. In this view, the closer you come to a lib­ertarian capitalist standpoint, the farther away you are from Gulag and the secret police knocking on your door.

  But concealed beneath the nice-sound­ing libertarian creeds of a “free­dom-loving indiv­idual” is also a somewhat darker assu­m­ption: that peo­ple are most often rather selfish, and, the reasoning goes, if you try to cre­ate a society in which this truth is not honored, it will backfire seri­ously—be­cause it can ultimately only be built on self-deceit. Instead, the argu­ment goes on, we should build a soc­iety in which people can work for their en­lightened self-interest, which will generally produce more sustain­able rel­a­tions, more productive behaviors, and a greater abun­dance of goods and ser­vices on the markets (both quality and quan­tity).

  As in Adam Smi­th’s classical 1776 notion of “the invi­sible hand”, this arg­­u­ment marries a belief in freedom to a meas­ure of con­servatism; a sober and real­istic look at peo­ple’s moral qualities and real behaviors. It’s true that Smith warned about the corrosive effects of repetitive factory work, but his analysis stopped there. If we let people work self­ishly under controlled cir­cum­stances (policing, rule of law, private property, consu­mer rights, etc.), then they will, on average and over time, do some­thing that is coll­ect­ively good.

  Hmm, okay. There may be some truth to these received wisdoms of our day and age. But upon closer inspection, such an appeal to “human nature” and her inn­ate individuality is of course a rom­antic reciting of beliefs rather than a behavioral-scientific explanation. They just make vague assum­p­tions about “human nature” and engineer morally weighted conclusions from there. This mainstream account of why communism failed has pretty weak explanatory power.

  But aren’t there yet more general a
nd structural causes for the spect­a­cular failures of communism? I’m glad you asked, because indeed there are.

  A Jammed Information Feedback System

  If we’d like to take it one step farther towards a more solid critique, we can look at the issue from the perspective of society’s information pro­cessing .

  From this perspective, we can see that economic central planning is often a bad idea. The demand for goods and services is extremely difficult to predict on a large scale. Hence it is more intelligent to let many diffe­rent agents make all the small decis­ions, “as if their busin­esses depended upon it”, rather than letting the gov­ernment make up a five-year plan and be done with it. Simply because these many agents, working with varying time­frames and perspectives, can pro­cess much more infor­mation, they can carry out more calibrated, sustain­able and inno­­vative decisions.

  Once you have committed to a five-year plan, there is bound to be any number of errors: shortages and unwanted surpluses. People will have enor­mous incen­tives to trade with one another, to remedy the short­ages and do away with the surpluses—hence de facto reopening a free market, a rather innocent version of the “black market”. But for the socialist plan­ning to work, such free trade needs to be illegal.

  If there are such strong incentives for doing something that is illegal, the legal system must be stretched out to deal with a lot of people and sit­uations. And for a legal system to realistically do that, it has to perform a lot of quick trials (or go after the “kulak” farmers who insist on producing their own goods). Hence the quality of the rule of law is degraded, hence people stop respecting the system altogether, hence corruption becomes ramp­ant—in exactly the kind of system that depends upon the goodwill, mutual trust and soli­darity among citizens.

 

‹ Prev