This Will Make You Smarter

Home > Other > This Will Make You Smarter > Page 35
This Will Make You Smarter Page 35

by John Brockman


  Hit: A signal is present, and the signal is detected (correct response)

  False Alarm: No signal is presented, but a signal is detected (incorrect response)

  Miss: A signal is present, but no signal is detected (incorrect response)

  Correct Rejection: No signal is presented, and no signal is detected (correct response)

  If the signal is clear, like a bright light against a dark background, and the decision maker has good visual acuity and is motivated to watch for the signal, we should see a large number of Hits and Correct Rejections and very few False Alarms and Misses. As these properties change, so does the quality of the decision. It is under ordinary conditions of uncertainty that signal-detection theory yields a powerful way to assess the stimulus and respondent qualities, including the respondent’s idiosyncratic criterion (or cutting score) for decision making.

  Signal-detection theory has been applied in areas as diverse as locating objects by sonar, the quality of remembering, the comprehension of language, visual perception, consumer marketing, jury decisions, price predictions in financial markets, and medical diagnoses. The reason signal-detection theory should be in the toolkit of every scientist is because it provides a mathematically rigorous framework for understanding the nature of decision processes. The reason its logic should be in the toolkit of every thinking person is because it forces a completion of the four cells when analyzing the quality of any statement, such as “Good management positions await Sagittarius this week.”

  Everyday Apophenia

  David Pizarro

  Assistant professor, Department of Psychology, Cornell University

  The human brain is an amazing pattern-detecting machine. We possess a variety of mechanisms that allow us to uncover hidden relationships between objects, events, and people. Without these, the sea of data hitting our senses would surely appear random and chaotic. But when our pattern-detection systems misfire, they tend to err in the direction of perceiving patterns where none actually exist.

  The German neurologist Klaus Conrad coined the term “apophenia” to describe this tendency in patients suffering from certain forms of mental illness. But it is increasingly clear from a variety of findings in the behavioral sciences that this tendency is not limited to ill or uneducated minds; healthy, intelligent people make similar errors on a regular basis. A superstitious athlete sees a connection between victory and a pair of socks; a parent refuses to vaccinate her child because of a perceived causal connection between inoculation and disease; a scientist sees hypothesis-confirming results in random noise; and thousands of people believe the random “shuffle” function on their music software is broken because they mistake spurious coincidence for meaningful connection.

  In short, the pattern-detection responsible for so much of our species’ success can just as easily betray us. This tendency to oversee patterns is likely an inevitable by-product of our adaptive pattern-detecting mechanisms. But the ability to acknowledge, track, and guard against this potentially dangerous tendency would be aided if the simple concept of “everyday apophenia” were an easily accessible concept.

  A Cognitive Toolkit Full of Garbage

  Ernst Pöppel

  Neuroscientist; chairman of the Human Science Center, Munich University; author, Mindworks: Time and Conscious Experience

  To get rid of garbage is essential. Also mental garbage. Cognitive toolkits are filled with such garbage simply because we are victims of ourselves. We should regularly empty this garbage can or, if we enjoy sitting in garbage, we’d better check how “shorthand abstractions” (SHAs) limit our creativity (certainly itself a SHA). Why is the cognitive toolkit filled with garbage?

  Let us look back in history (SHA): Modern science (SHA) can be said to have started in 1620 with Novum Organum (“New Instrument”), by Francis Bacon. It should impress us today that his analysis (SHA) begins with a description (SHA) of four mistakes we run into when we do science. Unfortunately, we usually forget these warnings. Francis Bacon argued that we are, first, victims of evolution (SHA)—that is, that our genes (SHA) define constraints that necessarily limit insight (SHA). Second, we suffer from the constraints of imprinting (SHA); the culture (SHA) we live in provides a frame for epigenetic programs (SHA) that ultimately define the structure (SHA) of neuronal processing (SHA). Third, we are corrupted by language (SHA), because thoughts (SHA) cannot be easily transformed into verbal expressions. Fourth, we are guided, or even controlled, by theories (SHA), be they explicit or implicit.

  What are the implications for a cognitive toolkit? We are caught, for instance, in a language trap. On the basis of our evolutionary heritage, we have the power of abstraction (SHA), but this has, in spite of some advantages we brag about (to make us seem superior to other creatures), a disastrous consequence: Abstractions are usually represented in words; apparently we cannot do otherwise. We have to “ontologize”; we invent nouns to extract knowledge (SHA) from processes (SHA). (I do not refer to the powerful pictorial shorthand abstractions.) Abstraction is obviously complexity reduction (SHA). We make it simple. Why do we do this? Evolutionary heritage dictates rapidity. However, speed may be an advantage for a survival toolkit but not for a cognitive toolkit. It is a categorical error (SHA) to confuse speed in action with speed in thinking. The selection pressure for speed invites us to neglect the richness of facts. This pressure allows the invention (SHA) of a simple, clear, easy-to-understand, easy-to-refer-to, easy-to-communicate shorthand abstraction. Thus, because we are a victim of our biological past, and as a consequence a victim of ourselves, we end up with shabby SHAs, having left behind reality. If there is one disease all humans share, it is “monocausalitis,” the motivation (SHA) to explain everything on the basis of just one cause. This may be a nice intellectual exercise, but it is simply misleading.

  Of course we depend on communication (SHA), and this requires verbal references usually tagged with language. But if we do not understand, within the communicative frame or reference system (SHA), that we are a victim of ourselves by “ontologizing” and continually creating “practical” SHAs, we simply use a cognitive toolkit of mental garbage.

  Is there a pragmatic way out, other than to radically get rid of mental garbage? Yes, perhaps: Simply not using the key SHAs explicitly in one’s toolkit. Working on consciousness, don’t use (at least for one year) the SHA “consciousness.” If you work on the “self,” never refer explicitly to self. Going through one’s own garbage, one discovers many misleading SHAs, like just a few in my focus of attention (SHA): the brain as a net, localization of function, representation, inhibition, threshold, decision, the present. An easy way out is, of course, to refer to some of these SHAs as metaphors (SHA), but this, again, is evading the problem (SHA). I am aware of the fact (SHA) that I am also a victim of evolution, and to suggest “garbage” as a SHA also suffers from the same problem; even the concept of garbage required a discovery (SHA). But we cannot do otherwise than simply be aware of this challenge (SHA), that the content of the cognitive toolkit is characterized by self-referentiality (SHA)—that is, by the fact that the SHAs define themselves by their unreflected use.

  Acknowledgments

  Thanks to Steven Pinker for suggesting this year’s Edge Question and to Daniel Kahneman for advice on its presentation. Thanks to Peter Hubbard of HarperCollins for his continued support. And thanks to Sara Lippincott for her thoughtful and meticulous editing.

  Index

  The pagination of this electronic edition does not match the edition from which it was created. To locate a specific passage, please use the search feature of your e-book reader.

  absence and evidence, 281, 282–84

  abstractions, shorthand, see SHAs

  Adaptation and Natural Selection (Williams), 196

  adoptions, 194

  Aether, 338–39

  Afghanistan, 19

  agreeableness, 232–33

 
Aguirre, Anthony, 301–2

  Alexander, Richard, 321

  Alexander, Stephon H., xxvii, 296–98

  algebra, 6, 24

  Alter, Adam, 150–53

  altruism, 194, 196–97

  aluminum refining, 110

  Amazon, 25

  Anasazi, 361

  Anderson, Alun, 209–10

  Anderson, Ross, 262–63

  anecdotalism, 278–80

  anomalies, 242–45

  Anthropocene thinking, 206–8

  anthropologists, 361

  anthropophilia, 386–88

  anyons, 191

  apophenia, 394

  Arbesman, Samuel, 11–12

  archaeology, 282–84, 361

  architecture, 246–49

  ARISE (Adaptive Regression In the Service of the Ego), 235–36

  Aristotle, 9, 28–29, 35

  art:

  bricolage in, 271–72

  parallelism in commerce and, 307–9

  recursive structures in, 146–49

  Arthur, Brian, 223

  Ascent of Man, The, 340

  Asimov, Isaac, 324–25

  assertions, 267

  assumptions, 218–19

  atoms, 128

  attention, 130, 211

  focusing illusion an, 49–50

  spotlight of, 46–48

  attractiveness, 136, 137

  authority and experts, 18, 20, 34

  Avery, Oswald, 244

  Avicenna, 9

  Aztecs, 361

  Bacon, Francis, 395

  bacteria, 15–16, 89, 97, 166, 290–91, 292–93, 338

  transformation of, 243, 244, 245

  Baldwin, Mark, 152

  Banaji, Mahzarin R., 389–93

  banking crisis, 259, 261, 307, 309, 322, 386

  Barondes, Samuel, 32

  Barton, Robert, 150–51

  base rate, 264–65

  Bass, Thomas A., 86–87

  Bayesian inference, 70

  behavior, ignorance of causes of, 349–52

  behavioral sciences, 365–66

  belief, 336–37

  proof, 355–57

  Bell, Alexander Graham, 110

  bell curve (Gaussian distribution), 199, 200

  benchmarks, 186

  bias, 18, 43–45

  confirmation, 40, 134

  self-serving, 37–38, 40

  in technologies, 41–42

  biochemical cycles, 170–71

  bioengineering, 16

  biological ecosystems, 312–14

  biological teleology, 4

  biology, 234, 312

  biophilia, 386

  Bird, Sheila, 274

  birds, 155, 359

  chickens, 62–63, 155

  herring gulls, 160

  songbirds, 154–55

  black box, 303

  Blackmore, Sue, 215–17

  Black Swan, The (Taleb), 315

  black-swan technologies, 314–17

  Blake, William, 44

  blame, 35–36, 106, 386

  blindness, 144

  Bloch waves, 297

  Boccaletti, Giulio, 184–87

  body, life-forms in, 13, 290–91, 292

  Boeri, Stefano, 78

  Bohr, Niels, 28

  Bolyai, János, 109

  Bony, Jean, 247–48

  Bostrom, Nick, 275–77

  bottom-up thinking, 157–59

  Boyer, Pascal, 182–83

  bradykinesia, 63

  brain, 48, 129–30, 148, 149, 150, 158, 172, 346, 347, 389, 394

  consciousness and, 217

  evolution of, 10, 207, 257

  mind and, 364, 366

  neurons in, see neurons

  plasticity of, 250–51

  predictive coding and, 132–34

  self and, 212

  size of, 257

  of split-brain patients, 349–50

  synapses in, 164

  temperament traits and, 229–30

  white and gray matter in, 162–63

  Bramante, Donato, 248–49

  Brand, Stewart, 15–16

  Bray, Dennis, 171–72

  bricolage, 271–72

  Brin, Sergey, xxv

  Bronowski, Jacob, 340, 341–42

  Brooks, David, xxv–xxviii

  Brown, Louise, 165

  Bryson, Bill, 387

  Buddha, 373

  business planning, 186

  Buss, David M., 353–54

  Byars, James Lee, xxix–xxx

  Cabot, John, 90

  calculus, 34, 109

  Calvin, William, 201–2

  cancer, 390

  body scans and, 69, 259–60, 264, 265

  tests for, 264–65

  cannibalism, 361–62

  carbon, 81, 82

  carbon dioxide (CO2) emissions, 202, 207, 217, 262

  car insurance, 66–67

  Carr, Nicholas, 116–17

  Carroll, Sean, 9–10

  Cartesian science, 82–83

  Caspi, Avshalom, 279

  cats, 286

  causality, 34–36, 58–61, 396

  blame, 35–36, 106, 386

  confabulation, 349–52

  correlation and, 215–17, 219

  of diseases, 59, 303–4

  entanglement and, 331

  information flow and, 218–20

  nexus, 34–35

  root-cause analysis, 303–4

  in universe, 9–10

  web of causation, 59–60, 61

  central-limit theorem, 107–8

  certainty, 73, 260

  proof, 355–57

  uselessness of, 51–52

  see also uncertainty

  Challenger, 236

  chance, 7, 18

  change, 127–28, 290

  fixation on, 373

  chaos theory, 103, 202

  character traits, 229

  charitable activities, 194

  cheating, 351

  chess, 343

  chickens, 62–63, 155

  children, 148, 155, 252

  chocolate, 140

  cholera, 338

  Chomsky, Noam, xxv

  Christakis, Nicholas A., xxvii, 81–83, 306

  Church, George, 88–89

  CINAC (“correlation is not a cause”), 215–17

  civil rights movement, 370

  Clark, Andy, 132–34

  Clarke, Arthur C., 61

  climate change, 51, 53, 99, 178, 201–2, 204, 268, 309, 315, 335, 386, 390

  CO2 levels and, 202, 207, 217, 262

  cultural differences in view of, 387–88

  global economy and, 238–39

  procrastination in dealing with, 209, 210

  clinical trials, 26, 44, 56

  cloning, 56, 165

  coastlines, xxvi, 246

  Cochran, Gregory, 360–62

  coffee, 140, 152, 351

  cognition, 172

  perception and, 133–34

  cognitive humility, 39–40

  cognitive load, 116–17

  cognitive toolkit, 333

  Cohen, Daniel, 254

  Cohen, Joel, 65

  Cohen, Steven, 307–8

  cold fusion, 243, 244

  Coleman, Ornette, 254, 255

  collective intelligence, 257–58

  Colombia, 345

  color, 150–51

  color-blindness, 144

  Coltrane, John, 254–55

  com
munication, 250, 358, 372

  depth in, 227

  temperament and, 231

  companionship, 328–29

  comparative advantage, law of, 100

  comparison, 201

  competition, 98

  complexity, 184–85, 226–27, 326, 327

  emergent, 275

  computation, 227, 372

  computers, 74, 103–4, 146–47, 172

  cloud and, 74

  graphical desktops on, 135

  memory in, 39–40

  open standards and, 86–87

  computer software, 80, 246

  concept formation, 276

  conduction, 297

  confabulation, 349–52

  confirmation bias, 40, 134

  Conner, Alana, 367–70

  Conrad, Klaus, 394

  conscientiousness, 232

  consciousness, 217

  conservatism, 347, 351

  consistency, 128

  conspicuous consumption, 228, 308

  constraint satisfaction, 167–69

  consumers, keystone, 174–76

  context, sensitivity to, 40

  continental drift, 244–45

  conversation, 268

  Conway, John Horton, 275, 277

  cooperation, 98–99

  Copernicanism, 3

  Copernican Principle, 11–12, 25

  Copernicus, Nicolaus, 11, 294

  correlation, and causation, 215–17, 219

  creationism, 268–69

  creativity, 152, 395

  constraint satisfaction and, 167–69

  failure and, 79, 225

  negative capability and, 225

  serendipity and, 101–2

  Crick, Francis, 165, 244

  criminal justice, 26, 274

  Croak, James, 271–72

  crude look at the whole (CLAW), 388

  Crutzen, Paul, 208

  CT scans, 259–60

  cultural anthropologists, 361

  cultural attractors, 180–83

  culture, 154, 156, 395

 

‹ Prev