Zoran Zivkovic - First Contact and Time Travel

Home > Other > Zoran Zivkovic - First Contact and Time Travel > Page 9
Zoran Zivkovic - First Contact and Time Travel Page 9

by Selected Essays


  does the usual sleep cycle (this time with dreams, including the bad ones as

  well, if you are already inclined to them or if you have a bad conscience). If you

  could observe the “external” world, it would seem to you that events go on

  there at incredible speed. And in reverse, to those “outside” it would seem that

  everything happening in your world would play out inconceivably slowly. But

  this spying on one another is not possible. Two temporal streams are irrecon-

  cilably split. In reality, that is.

  Does the accelerated pace of movement through time offer any literary

  consolation? Certainly. Human drama.

  Above all, melodrama. Are there any more exciting melodramatic situations

  than the meeting of close relatives in completely mistaken time phases?! For

  example: Just after giving birth to her daughter, a young mother sets off on a

  time dilation journey which will last only one year in her local time, but then,

  when she returns, she will encounter the world from whence she came which is

  twenty years older, so that she will meet her daughter who is now the same age

  as she. (Ursula Le Guin, “Semley’s Necklace”.) In a literary sense, the idea

  seems steadily attractive, although the terrain here has already been thoroughly

  investigated, because the factor of estrangement is relatively simple.

  The extreme cases of accelerated movement through time are those which

  occur in (only genre allowable) points of reaching and exceeding the speed of

  light. Would time then stop completely, or might it even begin to go

  backward? Would one here achieve regression (or ‘progression’, depending

  on one’s point of view) from old age to youth, and even further, to birth? (Dan

  Simmons, Hyperion.) What comes before (that is, in this backwards view,

  after) birth: death? Could it be considered that a man is dead before he is born?

  The estrangement is much less restricted here, but it is not certain that the

  human drama also grows proportionally. On the contrary. Everything in good

  measure. Extremes are an uncertain means of support.

  The genre also allows the possibility that temporal streams with different

  rates of movement into the future do not remain separate after all, but that

  they come into contact, interweave. What happens when a slow and a fast

  temporal stream meet? What kind of influence can they have on one another?

  Would the slower one be more authoritative than the fast one? (Roger Zelazny,

  “The Great Slow Kings”.) Or, perhaps, is the opposite true? (Frank Herbert,

  The Heretics of Dune.) The idea is not void of genre excitement, but it can seem

  Chronomotion

  47

  to be a bit stretched, unconvincing. At least as fertile ground for high quality

  human drama.

  Finally, what is the last moment at which, in one of two accelerated ways,

  one can arrive in the future? Is there, in and of itself, such a moment? The end

  of time? The end of the cosmos? Does the idea of the end of time make any

  sense whatsoever? What if time is not linear but cyclical? What if, instead of

  advancing, the only place where it is appropriate to talk about the end, we have

  an eternal returning, a melding of the end into a new beginning? This is

  stepping into the area of ultimate questions, of cosmology, and here human

  drama, after all, becomes secondary.

  Or does it? It is not completely certain. Reading the novels of Olaf

  Stapledon (Last and First Men, Star Maker) or some of Arthur Clark’s stories

  (“Transcience”)—written under the influence of Olaf Stapledon—most cer-

  tainly does not leave the reader indifferent. But what is exciting here is not so

  much the human drama as it is the vision which reaches immeasurably beyond

  human boundaries. The question remains open as to whether such visions can

  possess literary value and also human drama.

  So much for speed. Let us look at what happens with change in direction.

  Specifically, movement from the future into the past.

  One might say, at first glance, that in reality there is nothing to support such

  an idea. No time machines, at least as far as we know, have been noticed

  arriving from the future. Not now, and not at any earlier time.

  This, to be fair, still does not mean anything. Perhaps the world is teeming

  with such time machines but we do not notice them, because they either

  directly or indirectly are not making their presence known, that is, they are not

  influencing the past. Why don’t they? It is possible to come up with three

  principle reasons: They don’t want to, they don’t dare to, or they are unable to.

  If they dare to and are able to, but still do not want to, then only one cause

  for that can be discerned. They are behaving as impartial observers who are

  avoiding getting involved in any possible way with the object of their obser-

  vation. Those would, actually, be the ideal historians: They have a chance to

  directly study the past which they have absolutely no desire to desecrate by

  interfering with it. (Connie Willis, Doomsday Book) Here there is plenty of

  dramatic tension, but it is somewhat simplified: everything, actually, is

  reduced to whether it is possible to retain complete indifference toward the

  time being observed. The desire to take action in it can be truly powerful. It is

  fertile ground for an exciting story, but it basically remains summarily simple.

  If they want to and are able to, but do not dare to, then it can be supposed

  that there is some sort of injunction keeping them from it. The purpose of the

  prohibition could be the protection of the future which can be unexpectedly

  48

  Z. Živkovic

  and irreparably disturbed if the fine weave of the past is changed even in the

  slightest. Even the most harmless causes in this time can have truly heavy

  consequences in a later one. (The “Butterfly Syndrome”; chaos theory.) In

  order to avoid that, mechanisms or institutions are introduced to more or less

  effectively protect the past. (Poul Anderson, “Time Patrol”, or Isaac Asimov,

  The End of Eternity.) This is also not void of human drama, but in terms of the

  genre it is a bit unsophisticated and old-fashioned.

  Finally, if they want to and they dare to but are unable to, then most likely

  there is a paradox at hand which, so it seems, is inescapably accompanied by

  attempts to change the past. The most familiar among them is the following.

  A man goes back into the past and either accidentally or intentionally causes

  the death of one of his parents before he himself is conceived, thus thwarting

  his own birth. But if he was never born, then he could not return into the past

  and prevent his own birth by getting rid of one of his parents, so he was born

  after all and returned into the past where he thwarted his own conception,

  which means that he was never really born... And so forth. Reductio ad

  absurdum.

  This nonsensical mixing of cause and effect remains, judging by everything,

  as the final prevention of altering the past from the future, but it does not stop

  the writing of works for which time paradoxes are no kind of barrier. Those

  paradoxes are simply not taken into consideration here. What improbable


  results can then be achieved! (Robert Heinlein, “All You Zombies. . .”.) The

  problem, however, lies in the fact that here there is no real drama: it is mainly

  just being clever and witty in the genre. Who will conceive of a more

  perplexing thing than the others. A mere Gedankenexperiment, a thought

  experiment.

  In the end, what remains?

  Clearly, the challenge in the genre is greater if changes are accepted not in

  the speed but in the direction of movement through time. Ideally, a means of

  influencing things in the past should be found while avoiding the paradox trap

  which that influence implies. Is something like that at all possible? It is not, so

  it seems, if there is a presupposition that there is only one primary stream

  of time.

  If, on the other hand, one thinks that there are several streams (an infinite

  number), then the aforementioned paradox can be elegantly surpassed. In the

  place where the past is changed, a branching out occurs: Along one

  branch—the one from which a time-traveler sets out to intermingle “back-

  ward” in time—the change has no influence (that stream has already played

  out the way it did), but another, new branch appears which is completely

  dependent upon the change. Transforming the past does not change,

  Chronomotion

  49

  therefore, the future, but rather creates a new stream of time which exists in

  parallel. (Ursula Le Guin, “A Fisherman of the Inland Sea”.)

  This is a case of a first-class idea in the genre about a specific kind of chrono-

  tree with literally infinite branchings and forkings. The axis of the powerful

  dramatic tension here is created by the question of whether events in one

  stream can affect events in another, that is, is it possible to move from one

  stream into another? Likewise, what is the relationship between the different

  versions of the same character in the different streams of time? Obviously, this

  understanding of the chronomotion theme is also not bereft of the danger of

  paradox, but that does not have to be crucial in a literary sense. Science fiction

  is not an experiment in theoretical physics, but a work of fiction. And works of

  prose allow paradoxes. In moderate doses, it goes without saying, and espe-

  cially if they are well conceived.

  Translated from the Serbian by Randall A. Major

  4

  The Labyrinth Theme in Science Fiction

  In traditional literature, as well as in other likewise traditional forms of artistic expression, the theme of the labyrinth appears exclusively as a spatial phenomenon. In that context, it possesses three ontological properties which differen-

  tiate it from other similar themes, for example the themes of wandering,

  searching, that is, traveling in general.

  The first property would be movement in a defined, enclosed space, which

  essentially can have only two directions: toward the exit or back toward the

  entrance. The second property would be the existence of a dead-end street, a

  no way out of the basic peripatetic factors of the theme in question. Finally, the

  third property of the labyrinth theme is the facilitation of essential change in

  the protagonists during the story’s plot, which is, as literary theory teaches us,

  an essential condition of good fiction: Protagonists are not the same at the

  entrance and at the exit of the labyrinth.

  Within the genre of science fiction, the theme we are discussing has

  undergone a fundamental modification which caused certain alterations to

  its ontological properties. In SF texts, the labyrinth theme is no longer a

  locomotional (spatial) but chronomotional (temporal) phenomenon. Movement

  from the entrance to the exit here, however, is also limited by a closed system,

  which can also have only two directions: from the past toward the future, or

  from the future toward the past. Time has no third dimension.

  “The Labyrinth Theme in Science Fiction.” Written in 1980. Originally published in Serbian in 1981 in the monthly magazine “Delo”, 1–2 / 1981, 150–154, Belgrade, Serbia. First published in English in “Two Essays on Time Travel”, “Foundation” #127, Science Fiction Foundation, Harold Wood, Essex, UK, August 2017, 77–83.

  © Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

  51

  Z. Živković, First Contact and Time Travel, Science and Fiction,

  https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-90551-8_4

  52

  Z. Živkovic

  Yet, while both directions are possible in the model of the spatial variant of

  the labyrinth theme—toward the exit or back toward the entrance—and they

  are basically of equal impact, when discussing the temporal variant, there is one

  significant difference which occurs in the existence of the dead-end street.

  While in the spatial labyrinth it is possible to reach a dead-end street whether

  one is moving toward the exit or toward the entrance, one can reach a no-way-

  out situation in the temporal labyrinth exclusively while moving from the

  future toward the past.

  In that direction, the dead-end street appears in the form of certain logical

  and causal paradoxes, retaining, however, its basic function as a peripatetic

  factor. Finally, when discussing the third ontological property of the labyrinth

  theme, in the temporal variant as well there is a transformation of the

  protagonist, but in this case it is generally much more drastic than in the

  spatial variant: in the first case, the change in the characters occurs exclusively

  in terms of their weltanschauung, while in the latter they can change their

  entire generic identity, mostly due to the effect of logical and causal paradoxes

  related to the specific nature of the dead-end street within the temporal

  variant.

  It is obvious, therefore, that the focus of the chronomotional type of the

  labyrinth theme lies in the factor of the dead-end street, which basically

  appears only in one morphological type, with a wide range of variations. All

  SF works which utilize the concept of movement from the future into the past

  are faced with the obligation to take the following paradox into consideration.

  A protagonist who lives in time A returns to the past in time B, where he does

  something which will result in his disappearance from the future; this disap-

  pearance is motivated by linear causality: the hero, for example, kills one of his

  ancestors before he is able to leave his progeny behind, and thus the hero’s very

  own birth is thwarted. The chain of causation, however, does not end there. If

  the protagonist is not born, meaning that he did not exist in time A, then he

  could not have possibly returned to time B and kill his ancestor there; and in

  that case, the ancestor did manage to leave his progeny behind, and thus the

  protagonist is inevitably born in the future!

  Thus, we have a paradox, a dead-end street. If it is presupposed that he

  returned to the past and killed his ancestor there, the protagonist could only be

  born if he was never born! Contradictio in adiecto. We have been led there by

  the disciplined application of linear causality, which is unmistakably in force in

  the case of the spatial labyrinth: Namely, it has long been known that the

  absolutely certain way of g
etting out of every closed system of this type,

  regardless of how complicated it is—all one has to do is follow one wall,

  starting at the entrance, and sooner or later one has to find the exit.

  The Labyrinth Theme in Science Fiction

  53

  Here, cause and effect act in a linear fashion. There is, however, one

  significant moment which is usually overlooked because it is not so obvious:

  We said—sooner or later. In other words, between cause and effect there is

  always a given temporal gap, only it is always true that the cause (in terms of

  linear causality) comes before the effect. One cannot, namely, first exit from the

  labyrinth and only then start following one wall beginning at the entrance.

  Ultimately, cause and effect are, in every practical sense, simultaneous (when

  you press the switch the light practically—although not really—goes on in

  the room).

  However, can such a sequence of cause and effect remain in force when

  discussing chronomotion from the future into the past? It is clear that in this

  case the linear flow of time does not work, in the sense that—already

  depending on how we look at things—in certain cases the future precedes

  the past. Concretely, if the act of murdering an ancestor is understood as a

  consequence of the protagonist’s setting off from the future into the past then,

  from the perspective of some sort of absolute time, it would seem that here the

  consequence (in the past) preceded the cause (in the future), which is in

  opposition to the fundamental principles of linear causality.

  The objection could be made, however, that absolute time is not authori-

  tative here, but rather the individual time of the protagonist. At the moment of

  the ancestor’s murder, regardless of the fact that it takes place in the past, he is older than at the moment when, although it happens in the future, he set off

  on his time travel. In that case, the cause would precede the effect after all and

  linear causality would be preserved.

  Accepting the authority of the individual time of the protagonist in defining

  the chronological order of cause and effect confronts us, however, with another

  difficulty. The individual time of the hero could serve as a valid measure for the

  establishment of the order of cause and effect in chronomotive cases, if it were

 

‹ Prev