Young William James Thinking

Home > Other > Young William James Thinking > Page 9
Young William James Thinking Page 9

by Paul J Croce


  power, for good or ill, of science, which was becoming “a sort of god— a

  blind, arbitrary, capricious deity.” With such prospects still only on the ho-

  rizon, James settled into the routine work of the semester, and in its last

  weeks he had most of the term’s work still to do, including evaluation of the

  most basic chemical ele ments and compounds: “Chemistry comes on toler-

  ably, but not as fast as I expected. I am pretty slow with my substances, hav-

  ing done but twelve since Thanksgiving and having thirty- eight more to do

  before the end of the term.” Still uncertain about his abilities, much less

  about the future of science, he motivated himself with a simple and deliber-

  ate maxim: “Nothing can be done without work.” 17

  In the fall of his first semester, James also wrote a long letter to a cousin,

  hastily ending it because he had to get back to work: “This writing in the

  middle of the week is an unheard-of license, for I must work, work, work.

  Relentless Chemistry claims its hapless victim.” But there were obstacles;

  he found the claims of science and scientists increasingly implausible because

  they conveyed a disturbing tone of arrogant finality. His chemistry teacher,

  Charles Eliot, contributed to this impression. For example, early in his second

  First Embrace of Science  41

  year, when James was suffering from a boil on his elbow, “Eliot with voice

  of absolute certainty told me to keep painting it with iodine.” James was

  skeptical, but remained respectful in this scientific setting, so “how could I

  help hopefully painting away.” The treatment did nothing to heal the boil

  but soon made matters worse: “[A]bout three days ago, . . . my arm began to

  swell voluminously.” He allowed that “the iodine seems to prevent the

  formation of a crater” but concluded with light mockery, “[W]hat else it

  does, heaven and Eliot alone know.” 18 While Eliot and the rest of the Har-

  vard faculty were comfortable with the scientific authority supporting such

  regular medical practices, James in his family had used a range of alterna-

  tive therapies, which contributed to his skepticism about Eliot’s confident

  suggestions.

  During his second year, James attended the lectures of Joseph Lovering,

  professor of physics. In September 1862, he recorded the professor’s overview

  of the course: “We shall treat of Acoustics, Electricity, Magnetism, Electro-

  Mag[netic] Optics & heat from a mechanical point of view and shall treat them

  together as they are all bound by the mechanical notion of undulation. ”19 This

  class exposed him to some basics of the scientific method, along with the as-

  sumption of materialist and even mechanical explanations for the action of

  physical phenomena, and the argument that diverse phenomena can be ex-

  plained by unified forces; these theories offer ironic parallels to those of his

  father, who would also unify forces but with spiritual explanations.

  Lovering was a beloved teacher but not an innovative researcher. Al-

  though he was permanent secretary of the American Association for the

  Advancement of Science from 1854 to 1873, his own investigations were

  largely observations and correlations of information. He graduated from

  Harvard in 1833, and he spent his whole career there. When James knew

  him, he was serving as regent of the college, a position like a modern regis-

  trar. Eliot praised him for his “capacity for assiduous routine labor.” He

  brought those virtues into the classroom as well, where he stated scientific

  facts and laws with great clarity, illustrated them successfully with routine

  experiments, offered occasional oratorical drama, and frequently recited

  exact passages from textbooks. His brief studies at the Divinity School and

  his idealistic Unitarian faith added to his appeal as a lecturer on campus

  and on the popu lar lecture cir cuit, including many pre sen ta tions at the Low-

  ell Institute. Through Lovering, James’s exposure to theories of the mecha-

  nistic uniformity of nature were laced with idealism about the divine architect

  behind the laws of classical physics.20

  42  Young William James Thinking

  James did not rec ord many direct responses to these mainstream scien-

  tific ideas that he was learning from Eliot and Lovering during his first

  years of formal study, but when he did, he raised doubts about strictly mech-

  anistic approaches. For example, at the beginning of his second year, he con-

  sidered the possibility that “our modern ‘forces’ light, magnetism &c. [are]

  no more physical entities than we now consider Bacon’s ‘forms’ are.” Baconi-

  anism was the paragon of strict empiricism associated with scientific work,

  but Francis Bacon himself combined his attention to evidence from the senses

  with theories about hidden forms that could explain the secret workings of

  material facts. James suggested that forces associated with science may

  also have, like Bacon’s forms, nonempirical qualities: magnetism, for exam-

  ple, instead of being a physical entity, was much like “malleability or any

  other property of matter.” This implies that forces are not things but func-

  tions of matter— that is, forces are the ways in which matter behaves. This

  focus on the functional properties of matter rather than its tangible empiri-

  cal qualities suggests his later turn away from traditional empiricism, with

  his proposition that consciousness exists not as an entity but rather as a

  function. In 1863, well before formulating radical empiricism, his words

  about the functional properties of matter emerged as part of his early re sis-

  tance to materialist views of nature. He would gain support for doubts

  about some of the assumptions of his formal education from some scientists

  themselves, including his reading of Michael Faraday, who was both a co-

  discoverer, with Henry James’s friend Joseph Henry, of electromagnetic

  induction in 1831, and an ardent Sandemanian. This religious sect empha-

  sized the simplicity of early Christian life and the direct action of the divine

  in the world. The elder James was also a follower of Sandemanianism in the

  1830s on his path toward Swedenborgianism. In these contexts, even while

  studying mainstream materialistic science, William James was immedi-

  ately drawn to asking philosophical questions about the natu ral facts of his

  scientific investigations. 21

  Despite William James’s dedication to science, his formal studies made

  him restless. A science education would be more impor tant to him for how

  he assimilated the material rather than for what he was taught. He was

  more interested in the relations between science and other fields and in the

  broad implications of his new learning. During his months as a chemistry

  student, his teacher Charles Eliot reported that “James was a very in ter est-

  ing and agreeable pupil,” readily “mastering the pro cesses” and passing the

  exams. He also observed patiently that James was “tolerably punctual at

  First Embrace of Science  43

  recitations,” but he “was not wholly devoted to the study of Chemistry.”

  Moreover, “his mind was e
xcursive,” a trait he showed even more outside

  the classroom. James spiced up chatting letters to friends with deeper

  thoughts, even signing them with mock gravity, identifying himself as “Your

  guide / Phi los o pher / & Friend.” He applied those speculative interests to

  the exploration of “other sciences and realms of thought” beyond his chem-

  istry assignments, and when he was in the laboratory, he liked to try his

  hand at “novel experimenting.” 22

  In the next few years, James experimented with a few diff er ent sciences,

  while grazing in a wide range of other, nonscientific fields. After just three

  semesters of full- time study of chemistry, he took a leave from the Law-

  rence Scientific School for the spring of 1863. As early as November 1861, he

  had already planned to “spend one term at home.” His reading suggests that

  his time away from school was a season of shift in scientific interests toward

  psy chol ogy, in both its philosophical and physiological aspects. Eliot later sus-

  pected medical prob lems, but he did not offer specifics in diagnosis or timing

  beyond saying that James in his youth suffered some “ill health, or rather

  something which I imagined to be a delicacy of ner vous constitution,” a

  veiled reference to neurasthenia. His teacher also said James possessed a

  “remarkable spirituality.” During his first years of schooling, James did not

  say anything about his own health, but he did continue to study science on

  his own, even as he read widely in other fields as well. While continuing his

  avocational reading, he re entered the Lawrence Scientific School in the fall

  of 1863, now as a student of Jeffries Wyman in the Department of Compara-

  tive Anatomy and Physiology. He revealed support for his new teacher’s

  Darwinian leanings when he admiringly incorporated one of the careful

  anatomist’s experiments into his notebook reflections on the naturalistic

  explanation of “organic phenomena. ”23

  James had already shown interest in physiology when he had been a stu-

  dent of chemistry; noticing this, Eliot gave him a laboratory assignment in

  the fall of 1862 to determine “the effects on the kidneys of eating bread made

  with Liebig- Horsford baking powder, whose chief constituent was acid phos-

  phate.” Since acid phosphate is already pres ent in the human body, the

  physiological response to the consumption of additional acid phosphate in

  the form of the baking powder would have been minimal. With the physio-

  logical presence of the phosphate not yet known, however, this was a reason-

  able if not daring experiment; for the student in lab, however, it was tedious.

  His teacher said James kept an “accurate” rec ord of his findings, but he added

  44  Young William James Thinking

  delicately, the results were “unpromising.” Young James found the whole

  experiment “tiresome,” especially since he was administering the distaste-

  ful bread to himself, and he asked to be given another assignment. Eliot ob-

  served that James’s reaction was part of a trend that would dominate his

  scientific study for almost a de cade: although he would return intermit-

  tently to the laboratory, his first scientific education was “in large propor-

  tion observational.” James keenly wanted to do more lab work, he re-

  spected it deeply as the foundation of scientific comprehension for its

  attention to tangible facts, and he would do extensive and innovative ex-

  perimental work once he started his teaching career, but he did not do

  much experimental work during his original education in science. Within

  the next few years, when he took up reviewing books and other writing, he

  reported that part of his attraction to this work of evaluating the scientific

  experimentation of others was “the simple cleansing of the persona, as it

  were, from the laboratory dirt.” 24 These steps away from the practice of

  science were also steps toward reflections on its methods and toward

  philosophizing.

  Philosophical Reflections within Scientific Study

  In his 1862 notebook, James’s entries on physics trailed off as he filled the

  pages with a range of speculative ideas and personal reflections. Eliot could

  see this trend coming when the young chemistry student grew distracted

  from his “systematic . . . education” in favor of “unsystematic excursions . . .

  [in]to philosophical studies.” For example, he recorded a basic epistemolog-

  ical prob lem about the nature of perception and conception: “Can I without

  consciousness distinguish between two objects—my chair and my wash stand”?

  Here is an early and simple example of a question that would become a

  centerpiece of his psy chol ogy and philosophy, and that he would answer: No,

  the selective attention of consciousness is fundamental to our perception and

  understanding of our world. Without it, the world is a uniform and undistin-

  guished mass of data, but with it, and its selective attention, we make in-

  formed distinctions to or ga nize and deal with the world around us. With his

  notebooks serving as psychological complements to his physics lessons, young

  James was already taking steps away from a spectator view of knowledge and

  toward the “dynamic relationship” of mind and world, which would become

  crucial parts of his mature philosophy.25 Lovering taught him the mechanical

  relation of physical bodies in space, and James questioned the mechanical

  perception of clear and distinct objects in perception.

  First Embrace of Science  45

  As he worked in science, James offered some very basic reflections on

  the relation of the One and the Many: “Realists say, our idea of man has a

  diff[erent] source (reflection) from our idea of men (sense).” This suggests

  his doubts about the merits of separating an abstraction from its concrete

  manifestations in particulars. The pragmatic philosophy of the mature James

  would expand this leaning into a wholesale critique of abstraction: because

  a thing is “known as” its effects, then the only significance of an abstract

  idea is in its relation to concreteness or its “cash value” in experience. He

  took another decisive step toward pragmatism when he first met Charles

  Peirce late in 1861 as a fellow student at the Scientific School, and during

  talks over the next few years, including discussion in their informal Meta-

  physical Club, where they and their colleagues worked their way toward

  pragmatic insights. Even this entry on the abstractions of philosophical re-

  alists likely grew from an exchange with Peirce, who was himself a realist,

  but one who posited that our knowledge of the real truth would not emerge

  from reflection on essences but from experience and inquiry over the long

  run. 26 This orientation toward the future would have a decisive influence

  on James’s prospective emphasis on ideas in the making; meanwhile, he

  continued to learn from sense experiences but began to doubt the increas-

  ingly brash claims of some scientific empiricists.

  James’s interest in large cosmic questions attracted him to the brilliant,

  irascible son of Professor Benjamin Peirce. James was still misspelling his


  name, but already quoting “C. S. Pierce” in his 1862 notebook. Over the next

  few years, as their friendship grew and their discussions deepened, they

  exchanged questions about the role of philosophy and religion in the midst

  of the growing authority of science, which they witnessed in school. James’s

  entry referring to “Pierce” is a strict logical lesson based on the limits of our

  knowledge. In response to “the reductio ad absurdum,” a logical weapon of

  philosophical abstraction that infers the truth of a position from the absurdity

  of its denial, he wrote that it “can never be used in metaphysical discussion

  & rarely in scientific because it assumes that we know the sum of possibili-

  ties.” Both Peirce and James endorsed the elusiveness behind even the most

  proud and confident claims. In addition, unlike the emerging enthusiasts

  for science, they did not hesitate to compare metaphysics with science because

  each contained uncertainty. This quotation, the earliest known evidence of

  James’s intellectual contact with Peirce, significantly points to the probabi-

  listic thinking that James and Peirce would both use to equate the distinct

  fields of science and religion for their common human quests to understand

  46  Young William James Thinking

  the world— and for their mutual limitations. These mainstays of the Meta-

  physical Club would famously search for compromise of science and reli-

  gion, but what is less often understood is their emphasis on the fields’

  shared uncertainties before even the need for compromise. 27

  James continued to assess the plausibility of scientific and religious claims

  in his per sis tent reading of “the ‘Phi los o pher of Königsberg.’ ” His next note-

  book entry is a short philosophical note on the relation of knowledge and

  faith, with a clear summary of Immanuel Kant’s philosophical goals: “Kant

  works critically until he finds it unsatisfactory— and then stops, at morality,

  freedom, God.” And then James claims, “[David] Hume do[es the same],”

  despite the Enlightenment phi los o pher’s bold reputation for antireligious

  sentiments and for disproof of arguments for the existence of the divine

  based on natu ral design. James observes the parallel in Hume for also employ-

  ing philosophical reasoning critically but stopping at a diff er ent endpoint: in

 

‹ Prev