Young William James Thinking

Home > Other > Young William James Thinking > Page 17
Young William James Thinking Page 17

by Paul J Croce


  goals into practice with careful research on cell physiology and the influ-

  ence of chemicals on living muscles and nerves. 16

  In addition to the work of Bernard and Brown- Séquard, there were still

  more inquiries in the German- speaking countries into the physiology that

  would support medicine. In the 1840s, dissatisfaction with the speculative

  insights of the idealistic, romantic Naturphilosophie school led to the rise of

  systematic, laboratory- based science. These developments extended many

  of the approaches of the Paris clinics. Despite the contrasts between clini-

  cal and laboratory medicine, both shared materialist assumptions and thera-

  peutic hopes. Both methods assumed the uniformity of disease states rather

  than the specificity of disease conditions within individuals or emerging in

  par tic u lar circumstances. The numerical method allowed the assemblage

  of extensive cases to suggest probable causes from the actions of similar

  conditions; clinical observations established correlations between body

  parts and symptoms. Physiology added depth to the same princi ple; using

  microscopic technology, laboratory researchers proposed such correlations

  at the more refined cellular level. Laboratory techniques promised to fulfill

  hopes spurred by clinical medicine that an exclusive focus on the material

  substance of the body would produce healing insights. 17

  German universities provided ample incentives for these inquiries with

  extensive investment in laboratories and high expectations for the worth of

  new knowledge from research. James’s trip in 1867 was at the beginning of

  a great wave of American medical education in Germany: between the late

  1860s and the early twentieth century, thousands of Americans studied

  90  Young William James Thinking

  medically related sciences in German- speaking laboratories; there were so

  many, in fact, that some labs were even conducted in En glish. As doctors in

  training increasingly shifted to laboratory rather than clinical training, the

  advocates of each approach thought of themselves as scientific, even as the

  evolution of cutting- edge medicine in each era was toward the identifica-

  tion of the most scientific, with the microsystem best understood at the time;

  they shared the scientific commitment to bottom-up causation, with the

  clinicians attending to par tic u lar organs, and then the laboratory research-

  ers evaluating cellular functions presented as the cause of medical symp-

  toms. The trend in nineteenth- century scientific medicine, in degrees through

  the clinic- and laboratory- focused periods, was toward analy sis of discrete

  parts rather than the whole person, and toward the concomitant specializa-

  tion into subdisciplines to deal thoroughly with those parts. Both clinic and

  laboratory encouraged the understanding of diseases as uniform entities

  rather than as specific conditions of sick people with individual distinctive-

  ness. These trends in medicine immediately coincided with the direction of

  professionalizing science in general— toward working assumptions for the

  exclusively materialist substance of things, their uniform operation accord-

  ing to universal laws, and their mechanical interaction.

  Despite these strides in scientific pro gress, German physiology by the

  1860s, like French clinical medicine, had few actual therapeutic innovations

  to show for all its scientific insights. The achievements were in analy sis of the

  tissues— leading, in medical terms, to improvements in diagnosis, not thera-

  peutics. The promise that science would provide for improved healing, how-

  ever, was a compelling hope, especially for younger students and prac ti tion ers

  in the field, such as William James. This context put regular medical prac ti-

  tion ers into a paradoxical situation: they looked ahead with great hope for

  improvement, but felt immediate short- term frustration. In the long run,

  their stance would look visionary to supporters of scientific medicine, but in

  the middle of the nineteenth century, they offered only promissory notes.

  James combined that same scientific frustration and faith in the future for

  his own career path when he declared in 1867 that “the time has come for

  Psy chol ogy to begin to be a science.” 18

  James’s Physiological Germany

  James found support for these scientific hopes in Germany, but science was

  not his exclusive focus. He sailed for Eu rope in April 1867 and spent the

  summer in Paris, Bohemia, and Dresden. He read widely outside his work

  Between Scientific and Sectarian Medicine   91

  in medicine and the physiology of mind, and he repeatedly visited water-

  cure baths for his per sis tent back prob lems and depressed mood. Ralph

  Waldo Emerson even wrote a letter of introduction to ease his way into the

  German intellectual world, boasting that this “student of medicine [is a] val-

  ued companion,” traveling “with a view to the further prosecution of his

  studies.” As fall approached, James was eager to take on more serious stud-

  ies, so he was determined “this winter to stick to the study of the ner vous

  system and psy chol ogy.” He was identifying medical fields that would allow

  him to engage in research supporting prac ti tion ers’ needs for new knowl-

  edge enabling improvement of diagnosis and eventually therapy. 19 Medi-

  cine’s promissory notes appealed strongly to the son of Henry James as he

  eagerly anticipated the philanthropic possibilities for science. Despite his

  avocational pursuits and the distractions of poor health, James’s major goal

  during 1867 was to work with leading lights in physiological psy chol ogy by

  attending lectures and joining in laboratory work.

  James’s hopes were high, but his back and eye prob lems kept him from

  laboratory work, so he feared that “[m]edecine is busted, much to my sor-

  row.” Still, he went to Berlin in September 1867, lived near the university,

  and stayed with his plan to absorb the new scientific knowledge. By this

  time, he felt stronger and more confident after the water cures, and so he

  said, “I have got tolerably well to work, & enjoy my lectures at the university

  intensely.” He systematically began to “attend all the lectures on physiology

  that are given there.” Most notably, that meant immersing himself in the

  work of physiologist Emil du Bois- Reymond; James found him “an irascible

  man of about forty- five [who] gives a very good and clear, yea, brilliant, se-

  ries of five lectures a week.” Caught up in the spirit of his studies, he soon

  declared, “I am going on to study what is already known, and perhaps may

  be able to do some work at it”— that is, his own laboratory investigations. His

  professor was urging a transition in psy chol ogy away from speculation about

  mental states. James had heard and read enough to know that “some mea-

  sure ments have allready [ sic] been made in the region lying between the

  physical changes in the nerves and the appearance of consciousness,” namely

  in the pioneering laboratory work of Johannes Müller, Gustav Fechner, and

  Ernst Weber. Müller developed the theory of specific nerve energies, identif
y-

  ing specific nerve activities with par tic u lar sensory experiences. This was an

  essential precursor to Fechner and Weber’s psychophysics, which offered the

  possibility for quantifying mental life in correspondence to bodily change,

  with the proposition that the intensity of perceived sensations increased

  92  Young William James Thinking

  with physical stimulus, but only logarithmically— that is, by diminishing

  increments. This work both addressed James’s hope to shed light on the

  influence of the physical on the mental and provided his first substantial ex-

  posure to probabilistic thinking, which was embedded in its methods. De-

  spite its materialist implications and applications, psychophysics, especially

  as presented by Fechner, was a mechanical proposition as a step toward un-

  derstanding the “inner psychophysics” of the body’s relation to mind, with

  a hope actually to undercut materialism. 20 These calculations and proposi-

  tions were more widely used, however, to support views about regular pat-

  terns in nature as steps toward establishing the mea sur able research pro-

  grams that made experimental scientific psy chol ogy pos si ble.

  Du Bois- Reymond had studied with Müller, and his own research on

  animal electricity was built on the work of Hermann von Helmholtz, a

  physicist and physiologist at Heidelberg in whose laboratory James hoped

  to work. Du Bois- Reymond used physics models and methods to establish a

  picture of “the interior of the muscle” with “centers of electromotive action.”

  He thought of these hy po thet i cal “electromotive molecules” by analogy

  with the “action of a voltaic pile surrounded by a layer of moist conducting

  substance,” portraying the electrical action in a muscle as a series of evenly

  rowed electrically charged balls. He concluded that “ these experiments jus-

  tify the assumption that in the muscles an electrical arrangement obtains

  similar to that . . . described” in the models used in physics. Using methods

  that also assumed the ability to explain physiology in terms of physics,

  Helmholtz mea sured the speed of a nerve impulse in a frog. He found that

  the impulses operate at the very worldly speed of fifty meters per second,

  even slower than the speed of sound; this tangible mea sure ment dashed the

  long- standing idealistic assumption that nerve impulses were instanta-

  neous or uncountably fast. These insights were triumphs of scientific re-

  search and persuasive arguments for materialist philosophies, which have

  become the basis for modern mainstream textbook models of the mechani-

  cal operation of currents through the axons of the ner vous system at speeds

  much slower than familiar electrical transmissions. 21

  These German scientists were mapping out a scientific basis for psy chol-

  ogy that would wrest understanding of the mind’s operation away from phil-

  osophical assumptions, which had dominated the study of the mind. More

  specifically, du Bois- Reymond and Helmholtz, along with Ernst Brücke and

  Karl Ludwig were all students of Müller in their twenties in the 1840s, and

  they signed a pact written by du Bois- Reymond to insist on materialist ex-

  Between Scientific and Sectarian Medicine   93

  Emil du Bois- Reymond’s Model for Cells Depicting the “ imagined . . . centres of

  electromotive molecules.”

  Du Bois- Reymond, On Animal Electricity, 109–10.

  James’s physiology teacher in Berlin during winter 1867–68, du Bois- Reymond

  presented the human body in starkly material terms, with these molecules depicted

  in neat rows, on the model of particles in physics. This simplified and frankly

  “ imagined” assumption contrasted with James’s emerging recognition of the robust

  complexity of natu ral facts, the basis of his hope for a “Program of the Future of

  Science” (CWJ, 4:93–94).

  planations. To “this truth” of the materialist outlook, they all “pledged a sol-

  emn oath.” They proposed that “no forces other than the common physical-

  chemical ones are active within the organism.” Their depiction of the future

  coincided with the scientific hopes of mainstream medicine, just as their

  work supplied information and theories to support those hopes. They ded-

  icated themselves to “physical- mathematical methods,” and if explana-

  tions still eluded, they proposed “to assume new forces equal in dignity to

  94  Young William James Thinking

  the chemical- physical forces inherent in matter.” Following the princi ple

  that the elegant simplicity of physics provided the best model, they as-

  sumed that ever more aspects of life, most dramatically human mental life,

  were indeed “reducible to the forces of attraction and repulsion”; James

  would again meet this impulse to “physicalize a whole array of human

  mental powers” in the work of British psychologist Alexander Bain, whose

  work he would study in the Metaphysical Club. James showed his reserva-

  tions about the stark implications of these materialist directions shortly

  after finding an apartment while attending du Bois- Reymond’s lectures: he

  reported that after the lectures, he would return “to this lone room where

  no human com pany but a ghastly lithograph of Johannes Müller and a grin-

  ning skull are to cheer me.” James was showing a backhanded anticipation

  of his “ Will to Believe,” where he defended “precursive faith” in contrast

  with scientific skepticism; in 1867, however, he was encountering a will to

  believe among scientists advocating materialism prior to evidence for medi-

  cal effectiveness because they “tacitly assumed that there may be [such] a

  Philosophy.” In the 1860s, James also directed his critique at Herbert Spen-

  cer, whose steadfast empirical focus in support of materialist assumptions

  he called “pure E[mpiricism],” in reference to his evolutionist philosophy

  exclusively in support of scientific empiricism; his later use of the very same

  phrase, but with “pure experience” then pulled away from its association

  with materialist science, shows his per sis tent eagerness to pres ent his

  own hopes for science without assuming such materialist reduction. 22 Even

  with his critiques and exploratory phrasing, James fully recognized that

  despite their excesses, these grand expectations for science, when applied

  to medicine and psy chol ogy, might produce impor tant new insights.

  Du Bois- Reymond fully applied the terms of his materialist oath to the

  major scientific innovation of the era: Darwinism was the latest develop-

  ment in science to “dispel the illusion[s]” of philosophy and religion. Dar-

  win’s “ultimate triumph” was to pres ent the law of species change through

  natu ral se lection as a “mechanical pro cess.” Du Bois- Reymond’s views of

  Darwinism and medical physiology were an extension of his “physicalist”

  views that coincided with the arguments of Auguste Comte about human

  pro gress toward positivist understanding through science. The German

  physiologist similarly maintained that science was at the root of civilization’s

  improvements in each age: “[P]rogress necessarily depends on consci
ous

  utilization of natu ral forces observed in their orderly workings.” Modern

  civilization has done more than advance from the structures of previous

  Between Scientific and Sectarian Medicine   95

  ages; with science, du Bois- Reymond added forcefully, humanity has “awak-

  ened as it were from a bewildering dream.” He was, however, eager to give

  credit to Chris tian ity in this story. Despite the roadblocks to scientific knowl-

  edge that it and religion in general have imposed on the human mind, he

  insisted, the Christian religion planted the seed for the certainties of scien-

  tific knowledge by “inspiring man with the ardent longing for absolute knowl-

  edge”; he argued with an early version of Robert Merton’s thesis, because of

  its uncompromising spirit of mono the ism, which displaced the “essentially

  tolerant” beliefs of polytheism. But any religious idea was at best a way sta-

  tion toward the pinnacle of “certitude in . . . experimental science. ”23

  Despite his reservations about such enthusiasms for science, James saw

  the practical benefit of adding deeper scientific understanding to his medi-

  cal training. So it is “worth the trou ble,” he noted with patient ac cep tance

  of scientific overconfidence, and he added with determination, “a steady

  boring away is bound to fetch” eventual accomplishment. While he rarely

  showed hesitation about the worth of the scientific material, he found it

  “very discouraging” that his poor health kept him from researching more of

  the alluring work he was reading about. As he well understood, to really

  succeed in scientific research would require expertise in the laboratory, but

  his back and eye prob lems kept him from these firsthand inquiries. “My

  wish was to study physiology practically,” he wrote in September 1867, but

  then added gloomily, “I shall not be able. ”24

  Despite his shaky health, James said, “I find myself getting more inter-

  ested in Physiology,” as he kept learning the field in lectures and books, even

  if not in laboratories. When his symptoms would temporarily improve, he

  “nourish[ed] a hope that I may be able to make its study (and perhaps its

  teaching) my profession.” And back and forth he went, studying hard in his

 

‹ Prev