Young William James Thinking

Home > Other > Young William James Thinking > Page 41
Young William James Thinking Page 41

by Paul J Croce


  between ac cep tance and strug gle, rest and work, resigned security and con-

  fidence in moral energy clouded access to his theoretical blueprint. In the

  same letter to Bob, William weakly claimed to have “but very few words”

  and forlornly wished, despite all his avid learning, that he “could console

  you with religion or philosophy”; it was indeed one of his few letters that

  year, and he was feeling palpably aware of the limits of theory. The very

  position of feeling down, however, reminded him of his April resolution to

  strug gle against those negative feelings. He declared that “through . . . de-

  privation we learn of resources within us,” but until they are demanded by

  such personal strug gle, “we should else have remained ignorant” of them.

  These other wise hidden energies, as he would later call them, were the con-

  structive benefits of crises, and they gave the “power to resist pain, . . . and

  generally to keep our heads up under circumstances where nothing but

  pure courage will suffice”; so even the failed portions of his experiments

  would support his hypothesis for a will to order. With Minny Temple’s

  death in March still fresh in his mind, he was reminded again that “death

  sits at the heart of each one of us”; especially with his physical and psycho-

  logical prob lems, he even felt that “she takes possession . . . step by step.” At

  these moments, life seemed to be no more than death on the installment

  plan. But rather than dwelling on the real ity of death (both the end- of- life

  kind and his own gradual version), which he could not control, he preferred

  “to think of that alone which seems to belong to us—to our wills—in life,

  namely the keeping up of a true and courageous spirit.” Here is the Stoic

  emphasis on expending concern only for things that we can control. Al-

  though he did not mention Marcus Aurelius by name, he did, as with the

  Roman Stoic, make reference to his “own good will,” which would serve as

  his “inner solitary room” where he could likewise apply a discipline of as-

  sent in the midst of hostile forces. And Marcus may have been the reference

  when he declared, “ ‘A strong man battling with misfortune is a spectacle

  for the Gods’ said an ancient.” Then he added, admitting both the appeal of

  his April resolution and the difficulty of implementing it, “so is a weak man”;

  after all, ac cep tance and strug gle would each have their uses, and so too

  234  Young William James Thinking

  with crises. 68 Ancient wisdom joined with philosophizing and his willful

  resolutions as resources for coping with his crises, even as the crises them-

  selves were resources for cultivating his will.

  During his strug gle to implement his hypothesis for a free and strong

  will, James kept up his steady learning. In addition to his vocational work in

  physiology and psy chol ogy, he maintained his often self- proscribed interest

  in philosophy. That included extensive private reading, and he had already

  joined “a metaphysical club, in Cambridge (consisting of Chauncey Wright,

  C. Pierce [ sic] etc.),” as his brother Henry reported in January 1872, and he

  had likely joined in those meetings since the late 1860s, with individual dis-

  cussions going back even further. These young men pressed big ideas with

  casual familiarity, and for James the settings provided chances to test out his

  ideas of the will and belief. For example, just two years after his April 1870

  resolution, while still searching for vocational direction, James made

  mock- heroic reference to “the great Chauncey Wright,” who often used

  his enthusiasm for scientific empiricism to critique James’s hopes for the

  will. The Metaphysical Club’s “boxing master” made brash claims about

  persuading the ambivalent James to doubt the power of the will to shape

  belief in the face of per sis tent demands for evidence. In response, James

  could enlist tangible experiences according to his program for future sci-

  ence. James jokingly concluded that his older colleague “now lies (as to his

  system of the universe) in my arms as harmless as a babe. ”69 The wrangling

  would continue even after James began teaching in the spring of 1873.

  In the next few months, James continued in spirited critique of Wright’s

  scientific enthusiasm in an unpublished essay he called “Against Nihilism,”

  because he maintained that, with his traditional empiricism, Wright “de-

  nies this to be a Universe, and makes it out a ‘Nulliverse.’ ” When faced with

  the “multitude of repre sen ta tions” around us, Wright denies the idealistic

  view that “the repre sen ta tions come together, and seem to combine and in-

  fluence each other.” James asks, “[I]f each repre sen ta tion is totally in de pen-

  dent,” as his friend suggests, “how does it ever come into collision with any

  other[;] how can it be synthesized with another?” In the essay, James op-

  posed Wright because, although it was difficult to detect the “substantial

  bonds of union, . . . they in some sense unite the heterogeneous into a Uni-

  verse.” Finding support from “Peirce’s criterion, breadth of relation,” James

  anticipates his own later arguments in A Pluralistic Universe (1909), and he

  admits that his emphasis on relation of parts and his commitment to “conti-

  nuity” suggests aspects of the disparaged philosophy of idealism, with its

  Crises and Construction  235

  “duplication of the phenomena,” once as experienced empirically and then

  again as “it is meant.” These relations seem to constitute a “transcending

  [of] actuality” defying empiricism, at least in its traditional form, and they

  suggest a theoretical expression of his speculative hopes for his will, despite

  the very immediate empirical evidence of his trou bles. Wright would say

  simply, “[T]hings only exist once,” in their empirical forms. But James de-

  tects within experience that “in each thing, beside its happening to exist as

  a matter of fact now, there is another kind of being which we may call ideal.”

  Idealism itself proposes that each thing “has a meaning, serves a purpose, is

  a cause, or an end, was predestined, has a ‘Nature’ by virtue of which it is as

  it is.” While the idealists have the advantage of emphasizing meaning and

  purpose, the empiricists seem truer to concrete experience. James medi-

  ates these positions by suggesting that the meaning or purpose of a thing is

  “not a- priori and determinant of it,” with conclusions based upon a prior

  plan untouched by experience as with the idealist view. Instead, he sug-

  gests that meaning is “a posteriori to the happening,” justified by appeal to

  experience within the very empirical facts that empiricists such as Wright

  emphasize. Michael Polanyi called this James’s “looser view of teleology”

  with “intelligible directional tendencies . . . operative in the world without

  our having to suppose that they determine all things.” 70

  As with James’s hope for finite absolutes, he was here positing pur-

  posefulness, not based upon prior fixed ideals, but in the making, as im-

  mediately useful as the adaptive trait
s Darwin proposed as the active

  agents of evolutionary change. A purposeful focus resides in subjective

  experience, generally perceived to be decidedly unempirical, by empiri-

  cists such as Wright, and therefore in sharp contrast with objective expe-

  rience. By contrast, James proposed that “a repre sen ta tion” in conscious-

  ness, such as his subjective assertion of will, has a kind of “objective

  being,” alongside empirical facts; or in short, he suggested that “subjectiv-

  ity [has] an objectivity.” These thoughts would prepare him years later for

  integrating subliminal psy chol ogy into his study of religious experience:

  this subconscious realm could be evaluated objectively, while religiously

  it constituted subjective experience. In the early 1870s, while still engaged

  in personal philosophizing, James was hoping to make his will an objec-

  tive factor in his own consciousness. 71 James’s philosophizing was gelling

  into the bases of his mature theories, but at the time it grew from thought

  experiments in his private writing and in discussion for support of his

  own willful action.

  236  Young William James Thinking

  The Metaphysical Club camaraderie contributed to James’s readiness to

  learn through his trou bles, but he realized that his prob lems emerged from

  a convergence of issues, so his improvement might only come from his contin-

  ued experimentation with a clustered combination of factors in health, mood,

  social standing, and philosophy. In May 1872 James visited Newport, where

  he had studied painting a dozen years earlier— and where he had begun his

  long, arduous path to finding his vocation. The old haunts reminded him of

  “the ghost of my dead self with his ignorance and weakness”; only recently,

  Temple’s death had filled him with despair, but he would soon depict such

  dark reminders as parts of painful steps toward growth: vocational and

  personal choices leave behind “murdered . . . sel[ves],” from paths not taken.

  While still sorting out his career decision, memory of one such “dead self”

  left behind in Newport now prompted him to write to his novelist brother

  Henry, “I envy ye the world of art.” Without it, “we sink into a flatter,

  blanker kind of consciousness.” He remembered art’s ability to “startle us

  now and then,” to awaken and enliven with humanity’s “richest potentiali-

  ties”; as with his reflections on the natu ral gracefulness of Greek sculpture,

  he was also feeling the power of art in contrast with the abstractions of

  theory. By October, he was spending still more of his time with the Meta-

  physical Club, but this made him again feel the ill effects of too much

  philosophical reflection: “I have been of late so sickened & skeptical of phil-

  osophical activity as to regret much that I did not stick to painting.” It was

  the concrete observation of physical things as experienced without inter-

  pretation, like willful action or the work of science without the grubbing

  subtleties of philosophical reflection, that attracted him once again to art; so

  he wrote, “simply getting absorbed in the look of nature is after abstract

  study like standing on one’s feet after having been on one’s head.” Although

  he expressed some hope to return to painting sometime— “next summer . . .

  if it is at all pos si ble”—he was already working at another outlet for tangible

  study of nature. And so, he added with more immediacy, “I keep up a small

  daily pegging at my Physiology.” 72

  By the spring of 1873, philosophical reflection and work in physiology

  competed for James’s attention. With his desire for order, he felt a “strong

  moral and intellectual craving . . . for some stable real ity to lean upon,” even

  as he was not persuaded by any of the clashing certainties he witnessed in

  competition around him. He was teaching physiology at Harvard’s Depart-

  ment of Natu ral History, which provided stable employment, but this work

  included scientific messages about physical facts shaping mental choices; he

  Crises and Construction  237

  was continually drawn to philosophy but burned by the instabilities of its

  constant questions. Could his faith in free will offer a substitute, with

  strength enough in the seemingly insubstantial stuff of volition, even when

  the empirical facts of his trou bles gave plenty of reasons to doubt? He wor-

  ried that his reflective inquiries themselves would undercut his goals,

  because “a professed phi los o pher pledges himself publicly never to have

  done with doubt . . . but every day to be ready to criticize afresh and call

  into question the grounds of his faith.” With this posture, he added wist-

  fully, he would have to “renounce the privilege of trusting blindly, which

  every simple man owns as a right”— and which he admired in the graceful

  ancients. His difficulty in sustaining faith—in his case, faith in his own voli-

  tional motivations— was part of a broader context of faith challenged

  throughout the culture by a host of intellectual and scientific forces. He

  knew from his years of trou ble that he could not sustain “such constant

  duty” to engage in skeptical challenges to his faith, so he set his hypothesis

  for free will in contrast with such scrutinizing philosophy: “I fear the con-

  stant sense of instability generated by this [philosophical, skeptical] atti-

  tude would be more than the voluntary faith I can keep going is sufficient to

  neutralize.” 73 Ironically, he experienced his youthful vow for free will not

  as support of the work in philosophy that he would later do but in contrast

  with his wariness about philosophy for its tendency to bring skeptical dis-

  missal of faith, his attempted faith in free will.

  With his first teaching job in the spring of 1873, James felt a vocational

  answer to his dilemma about philosophy and physiology. Choosing the

  concreteness of physiology, with small daily pegging at the natu ral facts of

  scientific inquiry, provided an immediate and welcome order in his per-

  sonal life, because he relished “the concrete facts in which a biologist’s

  responsibilities lie.” Science offered a modern equivalent to the ancients’

  intimate connection to nature, which provided them with orienting direc-

  tion through the modest means of everyday contact with nature; this would

  avoid the “hot imperious tragic way” of thinking that he associated with

  restless modern thinking. But modern science did not adhere to those an-

  cient harmonious assumptions, and it offered its own challenges to his

  hoped- for free will. The strongest supports for the skepticism he dreaded

  were based on scientific arguments for natu ral facts determining choices

  and therefore undercutting freedom. Especially from reading Herbert

  Spencer in the 1860s and then teaching his naturalistic psy chol ogy in the

  1870s, he perceived that these arguments from “Spencerism” against free

  238  Young William James Thinking

  will would challenge, as he had been reporting vehemently, the possibilities

  for “moral freedom,” “passionate initiative,” “creative power,” “pure courage,”

  and the
“power to resist pain [and] evil.” He could not reject the persuasive

  authority of naturalistic science, but he also could not accept its determinis-

  tic implications for a will directed by material forces, which would discour-

  age motivations for taking up willful action. So, while relying on science for

  his stable work, he continued his philosophizing now directed toward the

  methods and implications of his science. After all, those natu ral facts could

  “form a fixed basis from which to aspire as much as he please to the mastery

  of the universal questions.” As he said in 1865, his aspiration was for a

  “ Future Science” that would be less tied to materialistic assumptions,

  which would also mean less fixity of deterministic challenges to free will.74

  Rather than choosing either/or about his attractions to philosophy and

  physiology, James was selecting parts of each, for his theorizing and also

  for his vocational life. He approached philosophy, as he had learned from

  the Stoics, for the directions it could provide, even as those directions re-

  quired a free will that his science undercut; and he went to work in physiol-

  ogy to learn its natu ral facts about the bodily components of thought and

  be hav ior, but he felt no need to adopt its methods and assumptions that he

  found confining.

  In 1873 James was sharpening his diary experiment with a focus on

  physiology and free will. For his continued work, he had another resource,

  based on his personal reflections and his discussions with friends. James’s

  attempts to assert his free will and to take effective action exhibited a tan-

  gible and personal application of his 1862 Peirce- inspired declaration that

  “[n]one succeed in leaving Faith entirely out,” which he turned into an ex-

  periment on the strength of his own faith in free will, with a leap of faith for

  adopting his voluntarist stance.75 This addition of philosophizing to his sci-

  ence would bring improvements that he perceived science to need, in keep-

  ing with the path of constant inquiry that Peirce championed; and applying

  faith to science, with identification of initial premises as belief positions,

  was a bold and even irreverent turn away from the confidence increasingly

  associated with natu ral science. More immediately, this stance would en-

 

‹ Prev