Young William James Thinking

Home > Other > Young William James Thinking > Page 54
Young William James Thinking Page 54

by Paul J Croce


  48.   MT, 123–24.

  Notes to Pages 221–227  307

  49.   William James to Henry James, Ju nior, Jan[uar]y 19, [18]70, CWJ, 1:140; MT,

  123–24; PRG, 43; and to Alice Howe Gibbens, [October 6, 1876], CWJ, 4:547. Paul

  Croce, “Between Spiritualism and Science,” 212, summarizes vari ous versions of this

  distinction between “fighting faith” and “comforting faith” (TCJ, 2:324) as presented

  by interpreters of James’s religious thought; none of these includes his first commitment

  to this distinction in his 1869 diary.

  50.  Pomfret notes, in TCJ, 1:301–2.

  51.  William to Robertson James, [October 1869]; to Charles Ritter, 1 Decembre

  [18]69 (my translation of the French original); and to Henry Bowditch, Dec[ember] 29,

  [18]69, CWJ, 4:388, 393, 394, 399. In light of his comments relating mental state and

  back pain, Simon, Genuine Real ity, calls “William’s back the barometer of his

  emotional state” (115), which points toward the mingling of body and mind emerging

  in his thought.

  52.   William to Robertson James, Jan[uar]y 2, [18]70, CWJ, 4:400; [Diary 1],

  Jan[uar]y, 1, 1870, [77]; and to Henry James, Ju nior, Jan[uar]y 19, [18]70; May 7, [18]70,

  CWJ, 1:140, 159.

  53.  [Diary 1], Feb[ruar]y 1, 1870, [79–80]. A portion of this entry is also in TCJ, 1:322.

  54.  Unpublished philosophical notes, [May 1873] (notes archived with William

  James to Alice Gibbens, June 7, [18]77, CWJ, 4:570–72); portions of these notes are in

  TCJ, 1:322–23, but without citation, and in Bjork, William James, 103, and the editors

  of the Correspondence refer to them as “fragments” with “reflections on the mystery

  of existence” (CWJ, 4:572); and James to Catherine Havens, Feb[ruar]y 24, [18]69,

  CWJ, 4:369 (my translation of the French original).

  55.  William to Henry James, Jan[uar]y 19, [18]70, CWJ, 1:140; James, [Diary 1],

  May 27, [1868]; and shortly before February 1869, 59, [72–73]; Moreau’s Du Haschisch

  et de l’aliénation mentale, and La Psychologie morbide; Noll, “Jacques Moreau de

  Tours”; Marianne Weber, J. J. Moreau de Tours; Eugene Taylor, William James on

  Exceptional Mental States, 150–53; VRE, 22, 190–91; Taves, “Religious Experience and

  the Divisible Self”; Boring, A History of Experimental Psy chol ogy, 707; and Kelly, The

  Psy chol ogy of the Unconscious.

  56.   [Diary 1], March 9, 1870, [81] (Minny Temple actually died March 8); Henry

  James, Ju nior, to William James, March 29, [1870]; and William to Henry James,

  Ju nior, May 7, [18]70, CWJ, 1:153, 157, 153, 159.

  57.   [Diary 1], March 22, 1870, [82]; Habegger, “New Light”; The Upanishads, 133–34. Robert Richardson, William James, 112–13, 413–14, was the first to evaluate

  the Vedic presence in James’s diary entry; he emphasizes the mystical side of James’s

  insight, without relating it to his struggling impulses for moral effort. And David

  Leary, “New Insights into William James’s Personal Crisis, . . . Part I,” points out that

  James likely read the Vedic words in Arthur Schopenhauer (9, 13), who was another

  resource for his alternative spiritual thinking.

  58.   William James to Thomas Ward, March 14, [18]70; and to Henry James,

  Ju nior, May 7, [18]70, CWJ, 4:404; 1:159, 158. James continued to be outraged with

  Milne- Edwards; [Notebook 26], c. 1870, in the entry “Edwards, H. Milne,” arranged

  not by page but alphabetically by entry title.

  308  Notes to Pages 228–234

  59.   [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [82]; Perry quotes much of this diary entry:

  LWJ, 1:147–48; William to Henry James, Se nior, Oct[ober] 5, [18]68, CWJ, 4:342.

  William James was particularly influenced by Renouvier’s first part (“L’Homme

  et ses fonctions constituants”) of the second essay ( Traité de psychologie ratio-

  nnelle d’après les princi ples du criticisme, tome premier) in Essais de critique

  générale; see especially chap. 13, “La Liberté: État de la question; solution

  provisoire,” 305–31. Also see Devaux, “Variétés: À propos du ‘Renouvierisme’ de

  William James,” 396; J. Alexander Gunn, Modern French Philosophy; Wilbur Long,

  “The Philosophy of Charles Renouvier”; Logue, Charles Renouvier; and Brooks,

  The Eclectic Legacy.

  60.   James to Charles Renouvier, 2 Nov[em]bre, [18]72, CWJ, 4:430 (translated in

  TCJ, I:662); Viney, “William James on Free Will,” 34, 36, 47; James, review of Bain

  and Renouvier, ECR, 325; and “Sentiment of Rationality,” EPH,32–64. Viney,

  “William James on Free Will,” and “The American Reception of Jules Lequyer,”

  shows the influence of Lequyer’s commitment to free will on Renouvier, which

  contributed a dimension more spiritual than in the secular Renouvier to James’s

  understanding; and see Paul Croce, “Mannered Memory,” for review of interpreta-

  tions about Renouvier’s influence and its timing in relation to James’s “crisis,” and

  Logue, Charles Renouvier, 31, for doubts about the extent of Lequyer’s influence on

  Renouvier. Also see Viney, “Jules Lequyer and the Openness of God.”

  61.  As a child, James read Rodolphe Töpffer’s Voyages en Zigzag (1855), a whimsical adventure story, while he was traveling with his family many times across the

  Atlantic; Robert Richardson, William James, notes that he “became everlastingly fond

  of the term” (20); and Jeremy Carrette, in “Growing Up Zig- Zag,” in Halliwell and

  Rasmussen, William James and the Transatlantic Conversation, uses the term as a

  meta phor for both his transatlantic childhood and his attention to philosophical

  relations in his mature theories. The term also applies to James’s youthful path

  through times of strug gle and resignation, and the zigzag imagery also shows his

  halting steps toward integration of dual contrast in realms material and immaterial

  that would set the stage for his mature comprehension of philosophical relations.

  62.   [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [84].

  63.   Ibid., [83].

  64.   Ibid., [83–84]; also LWJ, 1:148; Bain, The Emotions and the Will, 568–70, 500–519; Rylance, Victorian Psy chol ogy, 147–202; O’Donnell, The Origins of Behaviorism, 80–83; Eclipse, 185, 152, 208–09; Menand, The Metaphysical Club, 201–32; and Dixon, “The Psy chol ogy of the Emotions,” 303. Since his own time, James has

  per sis tently been charged with promoting unfounded beliefs; see Dickenson Miller,

  “The Will to Believe and the Duty to Doubt”; and Bertrand Russell, The Duty to

  Doubt.

  65.   [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [84–85].

  66.  [Notebook 1], [1859], 61; [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [83]; and for evaluation of his earlier youthful pledges, see Eclipse, 69–77.

  67.  William to Henry James, Ju nior, May 7, [18]70, CWJ, 1:159; and to Robertson

  James, July 25, [18]70, CWJ, 4:410, 408.

  68.  William to Robertson James, July 25, [18]70, CWJ, 4:409; James, “The

  Energies of Men,” ERM, 130; and Hadot, Inner Citadel, 101.

  Notes to Pages 234–243  309

  69.  Henry James, Ju nior, to Elizabeth Boott, Jan[uary] 24, [1872], Complete Letters of Henry James, 2:431; William James to his family, May 30, [1872], CWJ, 4:422;

  Eclipse, 171–72, 284–85, nn. 61–62; and Edward Madden, Chauncey Wright, 43–50,

  which deals with one side o
f this sparring relationship, in his emphasis on Wright as a

  check on James’s religious impulses. On the discussion group, see Menand, The

  Metaphysical Club; and for earlier evaluations, see Eclipse, part III.

  70.   James, “Against Nihilism” (1873–75), MEN, 150–55; and see his other early

  reflections on the relation of empiricism and idealism in “Miscellanea I: Mostly

  Concerning Empiricism” (1870–73), MEN, 133–39; Polanyi and Prosch, Meaning,

  162–63; see my chapter 3, note 84.

  71.  James, “Against Nihilism” (1873–75), MEN, 154; VRE, 170,190.

  72.   William James to his family, May 30, [1972]; and to Henry James, Ju nior,

  Aug[ust] 24, [18]72; Oct[tober 10, 18]72, CWJ, 4:422; 1:165, 173, 174; and “ Great Men

  and Their Environment,” WB, 171.

  73.  [Diary 1], April 10, [1873], [88–89], also quoted in TCJ, 1:343–44. On “The Rise of Secularism,” see Eclipse, 10–17.

  74.  [Diary 1], April 10, [1873], [90], [88], [83], [84], [85]; William James to Henry James, Ju nior, May 7, [18]70; to Robertson James, July 25, [18]70; to Daniel Coit

  Gilman, May 4, [1878]; and to Charles Eliot Norton, Nov[ember] 14, [1864], CWJ, 1:159,

  4:409, 5:4, 4:94. James’s approach to free will as a position needing faith shows his

  awareness of skeptical and scientific challenges to its plausibility. From Spencer, such

  as in his Princi ples of Psy chol ogy, to Sam Harris, in Free Will, as an example in our time, science- oriented theorists with naturalistic philosophies have maintained that

  apparent free will can be understood in terms of physical factors and explained with

  sufficient natu ral knowledge; James perceived that these scientific ambitions

  themselves rested on faith in pro gress and that natu ral complexities surpass human

  capacities.

  75.  [Notebook 2], 20.

  76.  [Diary 1], April 10, [1873], [87–88], [88–89], [89–90]. Leary, “New Insights into William James’s Personal Crisis, . . . Part I,” calls James’s 1870 “return to Renouvier’s

  texts . . . booster shots” (23), and the same could be said of James’s 1873 verbal

  reinforcements of his hopes for injecting freedom into his convictions.

  77.  [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [88]; “The Dilemma of Determinism” (1884), WB,

  139, 140. On James’s “third path” approach to teleology, see my introduction, note 22;

  chapter 3, note 84; and notes 70–71 in this chapter. On pragmatism as an alternative

  and third way, see Bern stein, The Pragmatic Turn, 106–24, and Beyond Objectivism

  and Relativism, 223; Haack, Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate, 23–25; and Kloppen-

  berg, Uncertain Victory, 3–63. Charles Taylor portrays James in this spirit, as a

  “phi los o pher of the cusp”; see my introduction, note 25.

  78.  [Diary 1], Ap[ri]l 30, [1870], [85]; WB, 18.

  79.   Winslow, On Obscure Diseases, 267, 281, and see my chapter 1, note 37; Huxley,

  “Physical Basis of Life” (1868), and “The Hypothesis That Animals Are Automata”

  (1874), in Methods and Results, 130–65. On du Bois- Reymond, see my chapter 2, notes

  21–23, 30; Eclipse, 10–17; and Bowler, Monkey Trials and Gorilla Sermons, 30–78.

  80.   “Are We Automata?” (1879), EPS, 38–61; ECR, 296; review of Wundt, ECR,

  300; Araujo, Wundt and the Philosophical Foundations of Psy chol ogy, 127, 161; Steffens,

  310  Notes to Pages 243–248

  Autobiography of Lincoln Steffens, 149–50. Also see Ribot, German Psy chol ogy of

  To- day, 188–248; Boring, A History, 316–44, 505–17; Woodward and Ash, The

  Problematic Science, especially 1–14, 167–97; essays in Koch and Leary, A Century of

  Psy chol ogy, especially Sigmund Koch, “Wundt’s Creature,” 8–18, Stephen Toulmin

  and David Leary, “The Culture of Empiricism in Psy chol ogy, and Beyond,” 594–617;

  O’Donnell, The Origins of Behaviorism, especially 29–41; Danziger, Constructing the

  Subject, especially 34–48; Rieber and Robinson, Wilhelm Wundt in History; and Paul

  Croce, “Physiology as the Antechamber to Metaphysics.”

  81.  Jackson, “On the Anatomical and Physiological Localisation of Movements in

  the Brain” (1873), in Selected Writings, 1:49; Laycock, Mind and Brain; Roger Smith,

  Inhibition, 35, 79; Gregory, Scientific Materialism, 102; and Eclipse, 270, 108, 137. Years later, novelist Caleb Carr even gave a cameo appearance to James advocating free will

  in his novel, The Alienist, 56–59, in debate with the main character, Laszlo Kreizler,

  who supports the insanity defense based on cutting- edge scientific skepticism about

  free will because of bodily and social “contexts” shaping personal choices.

  82.  Henry James, Se nior, to Henry James, Ju nior, Mar[ch] 18, 1873, LWJ, 1:170;

  William James, teaching “Psy chol ogy,” Phil[osophy]. 5 (1880–81), reported by student

  George Albert Burdett, “Notes in Philosophy 5,” 122.

  83.   Charles Peirce, “The Fixation of Belief” (1877) and “How to Make Our Ideas

  Clear” (1878), Popu lar Science Monthly, in Writings of Peirce, 3:242–57, 257–76; EPH,

  7–22, 32–64; and William to Henry James, Ju nior, Nov[ember] 24, [18]72, CWJ, 1:177.

  On Peirce’s essays, see Eclipse, 204–22; and the recent collection, Charles Peirce,

  Illustrations of the Logic of Science. On the origins of pragmatism, see Eclipse, 207–15; Thayer, Meaning and Action, 143–45; John Smith, Purpose and Thought, 195–97;

  William James, The Writings of William James, 817; and Gerald Myers, William James,

  89, 270, 294.

  84.   Notes for Philosophy 9: Metaphysics (1905–6), ML, 347, 366–67; PRG, 117

  (quoting F. C. S. Schiller); WB, 6; PRG, 258; PU, 145, 20; and PRG, 97.

  85.   James to Thomas Ward, Dec[ember] 30, [18]76; to Alice Gibbens [July 20, 1877]; and to Henry James, Ju nior, May 25, [18]73, CWJ, 4:552, 577–78, and 1:209.

  86.  James to Daniel Coit Gilman, April 23, [1877]; and to Oliver Wendell Holmes,

  Ju nior, May 15, 1868, CWJ, 4:558, 4:302; Cope, “William James’s Correspondence

  with Daniel Coit Gilman”; Johns Hopkins and Lowell Lectures, ML, 3–16, 16–43; and

  Robert Richardson, William James, 141–47, 168–76. Also see O’Donnell, Origins of

  Behaviorism, 91–105; Feinstein, Becoming William James, 316–29; Paul Croce,

  “Physiology as the Antechamber to Metaphysics”; Daniel Wilson, Science, Commu-

  nity, and the Transformation of American Philosophy; and Bordogna, William James at

  the Bound aries.

  87.  William to Henry James, Ju nior, May 25, [18]73; Sept[ember] 2, [18]73;

  Dec[ember] 12, [18]75, CWJ, 1:209, 219, 247.

  88.  William to Alice Gibbens James, May 13, 1888; [October 9, 1876], CWJ, 4:547;

  Simon, Genuine Real ity, 155; and Henry James, Ju nior, to William, May 29, [1878],

  CWJ, 1:303. Perry, TCJ, 1:375, says Thomas Davidson introduced Alice to William in

  1876; and Gunter, in Alice in Jamesland, 45, suggests he may have met her himself; and

  see note 36 in this chapter.

  Notes to Pages 249–253  311

  89.  William James, [Fragments of Early Courses], 1875–85, ML, 125–26; Chapman,

  Memories and Milestones, 26; James to James Leuba, Apr[il] 17, 1904, LWJ, 2:212; and

  to Alice Gibbens James, July 9, 1898, CWJ, 8:390. On James’s later crises, see Myers,

  William James, 51; Seigfried, James’s Radical Reconstruction; Oliver, William James’s

  “Springs of Delight,” 88; Barnard, Explori
ng Unseen Worlds, 18–66; and Paul Croce,

  “Spilt Mysticism.”

  90.   William to Henry James, Ju nior, July 14, [1873]; Nov[ember] 14, [18]75 CWJ,

  1:215, 243.

  91.  William to Henry James, Ju nior, July 5, [1876]; Henry to William James, CWJ,

  1:268, 169; and Henry James, The American, 69–70.

  92.  Eugene Taylor, James on Exceptional Mental States, 15; VRE, 134, 135; and Paul Croce, “Mannered Memory.”

  93.   James, VRE, 135, 134, 135n; Henry James, Se nior, Society the Redeemed Form of Man, 43–54. James was also likely referring to his father in a case culminating in a

  strong “sense of guilt,” which he described with reference to Swedenborg; VRE, 164n.

  For more comparisons of the “crises” of father and son, see Warren, The Elder Henry

  James, 59–86; Young, The Philosophy of Henry James, Se nior, 29–65; Feinstein,

  Becoming William James, 241–45; Henry James, Se nior, Society the Redeemed Form of

  Man, quoted in Henry James, Se nior: A Se lection, 56; Latham, “Henry James Se nior’s

  Mrs. Chichester”; Habegger, The Father, 227–40; King, Iron of Melancholy, 140; Robert

  Richardson, William James, 117–18; Fisher, House of Wits, 81–84, 225, 270–71; and

  Eclipse, 32, 49–53.

  94.  James, VRE, 134; and to Frank Abauzit, June 1, 1904, VRE, 508. James’s letter

  admitting the identity of the French correspondent first appeared in Théodore

  Flournoy’s La Philosophie de William James, 149.

  95.   William to Henry James, Ju nior, Dec[ember] 5, [18]69, CWJ, 1:128; VRE, 163,

  134, 164. The conventional wisdom is that the story is an actual account of James at

  some par tic u lar time between 1869 and 1873: for example, Lewis, The Jameses, 201–2,

  states that “it occurred in fact in” 1870 and in a par tic u lar place, the second- floor

  dressing room of the James house in Cambridge; in correspondence, David Leary has

  suggested that the story is from James’s diary itself, but later torn out, and in fact the

  diary entry for Ap[ri]l 30, [1870] has a torn page where it “ends” (see those last extant

  words referenced in note 65 in this chapter). And in “New Insights into William

  James’s Personal Crisis,” Leary argues for the specificity of the crisis with careful

  evaluation of James’s reading of Arthur Schopenhauer and John Bunyan, which has

 

‹ Prev