Theory and Reality

Home > Other > Theory and Reality > Page 2
Theory and Reality Page 2

by Peter Godfrey-Smith


  To set things up this way is to see science as unlike the kinds of investigation and knowledge that routinely go along with farming, architecture, and other kinds of technology. So a view like this need not claim that people in nonscientific cultures must be ignorant or stupid; the idea is that in order to understand science, we need to distinguish it from other kinds of investigation of the world. And we need to work out how one approach to knowledge developed by a small group of Europeans turned out to have such spectacular consequences for humanity.

  As we move from theory to theory in this book, we will find some people construing science broadly, others narrowly, and others in a way that lies in between. But this does not stop us from outlining, in advance, what kind of understanding we would eventually like to have. However we choose to use the word "science," in the end we should try to develop both

  i. a general understanding of how humans gain knowledge of the world around them and

  z. an understanding of what makes the work descended from the Scientific Revolution different from other kinds of investigation of the world.

  We will move back and forth between these two kinds of questions throughout the book.

  Before leaving this topic, there is one other possibility that should be mentioned. How confident should we be that all the work we call "science," even in the narrower sense described above, has that much in common? One of the hazards of philosophy is the temptation to come up with theories that are too broad and sweeping. "Theories of science" need to be scrutinized with this problem in mind.

  1.3 What Kind of Theory?

  This book is an introduction to the philosophy of science. But most of the book focuses on one set of issues in that field. Within the philosophy of science, we can distinguish between epistemological issues and metaphysical issues (as well as issues that fall into neither category). Epistemology is the side of philosophy that is concerned with questions about knowledge, evidence, and rationality. Metaphysics, a more controversial part of philosophy, deals with general questions about the nature of reality. Philosophy of science overlaps with both of these.

  Most of the issues discussed in this book are, broadly speaking, epistemological issues. For example, we will be concerned with questions about how observational evidence can justify a scientific theory. We will also ask whether we have reason to hope that science can succeed in describing the world "as it really is But we will occasionally encounter metaphysical issues, and issues in the philosophy of language. The discussion will intersect with work in the history of science and other fields as well.

  All of philosophy is plagued with discussion and anxiety about how philosophical work should be done and what a philosophical theory should try to do. So we will have to deal with disagreement about the right form for a philosophical theory of science, and disagreement about which questions philosophers should be asking. One obvious possibility is that we might try for an understanding of scientific thinking. In the twentieth century, many philosophers rejected this idea, insisting that we should seek a logical theory of science. That is, we should try to understand the abstract structure of scientific theories and the relationships between theories and evidence. A third option is that we should try to come up with a methodology, a set of rules or procedures that scientists do or should follow. In more recent years, philosophers influenced by historical work have wanted to give a general theory of scientific change.

  A distinction that is very important here is the distinction between descriptive and normative theories. A descriptive theory is an attempt to describe what actually goes on, or what something is like, without making value judgments. A normative theory does make value judgments; it talks about what should go on, or what things should be like. Some theories about science are supposed to be descriptive only. But most of the views we will look at do have a normative element, either officially or unofficially. When assessing general claims about science, it is a good principle to constantly ask: "Is this claim intended to be descriptive or normative, or both?"

  For some people, the crucial question we need to answer about science is whether or not it is "objective." But this term has become an extremely slippery one, used to mean a number of very different things. Sometimes objectivity is taken to mean the absence of bias; objectivity is impartiality or fairness. But the term "objective" is also often used to express claims about whether the existence of something is independent of our minds. A person might wonder whether there really is an "objective reality," that is to say, a reality that exists regardless of how people conceptualize or describe it. We might ask whether scientific theories can ever describe a reality that exists in this sense. Questions like that go far beyond any issue about the absence of bias and take us into deep philosophical waters.

  Because of these ambiguities, I will often avoid the terms "objective" and "objectivity." But the questions that tend to be asked using those terms will be addressed, using different language, throughout the book. And I will return to "objectivity" in the final chapter.

  Another famous phrase is "scientific method." Perhaps this is what most people have in mind when they imagine giving a general theory of science. The idea of describing a special method that scientists do or should follow is old. In the seventeenth century, Francis Bacon and Rene Descartes, among others, tried to give detailed specifications of how scientists should proceed. Although describing a special scientific method looks like a natural thing to try to do, during the twentieth century many philosophers and others became skeptical about the idea of giving anything like a recipe for science. Science, it was argued, is too creative and unpredictable a process for there to be a recipe that describes it-this is especially true in the case of great scientists like Newton, Darwin, and Einstein. For a long time it was common for science textbooks to have an early section describing "the scientific method;' but recently textbooks seem to have become more cautious about this.

  I said that much twentiethcentury philosophy of science aimed at describing the logical structure of science. What does this mean? The idea is that the philosopher should think of a scientific theory as an abstract structure, something like a set of interrelated sentences. The philosopher aims to give a description of the logical relations between the sentences in the theory and the relations between the theory and observational evidence. Philosophy can also try to describe the logical relations between different scientific theories in related fields.

  Philosophers taking this approach tend to be enthusiastic about the tools of mathematical logic. They prize the rigor of their work. This kind of philosophy has often prompted frustration in people working on the actual history and social structure of science. The crusty old philosophers seemed to be deliberately removing their work from any contact with science as it is actually conducted, perhaps in order to hang onto a set of myths about the perfect rationality of the scientific enterprise, or in order to have nothing interfere with the endless games that can be played with imaginary theories expressed in artificial languages. This kind of logic-based philosophy of science will be discussed in the early chapters of this book. I will argue that the logical investigations were often very interesting, but ultimately my sympathy lies with those who insist that philosophy of science should have more contact with actual scientific work.

  If looking for a recipe is too simplistic, and looking for a logical theory is too abstract, what might we look for instead? Here is an answer that will be gradually developed as the book goes on: we can try to describe the scientific strategy for investigating the world. And we can then hope to describe what sort of connection to the world we are likely to achieve by following that strategy. Initially, this may sound vague or impossible, or both. But by the end of the book I hope to show that it makes good sense.

  Several times now I have mentioned fields that "neighbor" on philosophy of science-history of science, sociology of science, and parts of psychology, for example. What is the relation between philosophical theories of science and ideas in
these neighboring fields? This question was part of the twentiethcentury roller-coaster ride that I referred to earlier. Some people in these neighboring fields thought they had reason to believe that the whole idea of a philosophical theory of science is misguided. They expected that philosophy of science would be replaced by fields like sociology. This replacement never occurred. What did happen was that people in these neighboring fields constantly found themselves doing philosophy themselves, whether they realized it or not. They kept running into questions about truth, about justification, and about the connections between theories and reality. The philosophical problems refused to go away.

  Philosophers themselves differ a great deal about what kind of input from these neighboring fields is relevant to philosophy. This book is written from a viewpoint that holds that philosophy of science benefits from lots of input from other fields. But the argument that philosophy of science needs that kind of input will not be given until chapter io.

  1.4 Three Answers, or Pieces of an Answer

  In this section I will introduce three different answers to our general questions about how science works. In different ways, these three ideas will be recurring themes throughout the book.

  The three ideas can be seen as rivals; they can be seen as alternative starting points, or paths into the problem. But they might instead be considered as pieces of a single, more complicated answer. The problem then becomes how to fit them together.

  The first of the three ideas is empiricism. Empiricism encompasses a diverse family of philosophical views, and debates within the empiricist camp can be intense. But empiricism is often summarized using something like the following slogan:

  Empiricism: The only source of real knowledge about the world is experience.

  Empiricism, in this sense, is a view about where all knowledge comes from, not just scientific knowledge. So how does this help us with the philosophy of science? In general, the empiricist tradition has tended to see the differences between science and everyday thinking as differences of detail and degree. The empiricist tradition has generally, though not always, tended to construe science in a broad way, and it has tended to approach questions in the philosophy of science from the standpoint of a general theory of thought and knowledge. The empiricist tradition in philosophy has also been largely pro-science; science is seen as the best manifestation of our capacity to investigate and know the world.

  So here is a way to use the empiricist principle above to say something about science:

  Empiricism and Science: Scientific thinking and investigation have the same basic pattern as everyday thinking and investigation. In each case, the only source of real knowledge about the world is experience. But science is especially successful because it is organized, systematic, and especially responsive to experience.

  So "the scientific method," insofar as there is such a thing, will be routinely found in everyday contexts as well. There was no fundamentally new approach to investigation discovered during the Scientific Revolution, according to this view. Instead, Europe was freed from darkness and dogmatism by a few brave and brilliant souls who enabled intellectual culture to "come to its senses."

  Some readers are probably thinking that these empiricist principles are empty platitudes. Of course experience is the source of knowledge about the world-what else could be?

  For those who suspect that basic empiricist principles are completely trivial, an interesting place to look is the history of medicine. The history of medicine has many examples of episodes where huge breakthroughs were made by people willing to make very basic empirical tests-in the face of much skepticism, condescension, and opposition from people who "knew better." Empiricist philosophers have long used these anecdotes to fire up their readers. Carl Hempel, one of the most important empiricist philosophers of the twentieth century, liked to use the sad example of Ignaz Semmelweiss (see Hempel 1966). Semmelweiss worked in a hospital in Vienna in the mid-nineteenth century; he was able to show by simple empirical tests that if doctors washed their hands before delivering babies, the risk of infection in the mothers was hugely reduced. For this radical claim he was opposed and eventually driven out of the hospital.

  An even simpler example, which I will describe in some detail to provide a change from the usual case of Semmelweiss, has to do with the discovery of the role of drinking water in the transmission of cholera.

  Cholera was a huge problem in cities in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, producing death from terrible diarrhea. Cholera is still a problem whenever there are poor people crowded together without good sanitation, as it is transmitted from the diarrhea through drinking water. In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, there were various theories of how cholera was caused-this was before the discovery of the role of bacteria and other microorganisms in infectious disease. Some thought the disease was caused by foul gases, called miasmas, exuded from the ground and swamps. In London, John Snow hypothesized that cholera was spread by drinking water. He mapped the outbreak of one epidemic in London in 18 54 and found that it seemed to be centered on a particular public water pump in Broad Street. With great difficulty he persuaded the local authorities to remove the pump's handle. The outbreak immediately went away.

  This was a very important event in the history of medicine. It was central to the rise of the modern emphasis on clean drinking water and sanitation, a movement that has had an immense effect on human health and well-being. This is also the kind of case that shows the attractiveness of even very simple empiricist views.

  You might be thinking that we can just end the book here. Empiricism wins; looking to experience is a sure-fire guarantee of getting things right. Those who are tempted to think that no problems remain might consider a cautionary tale that follows up the Snow story. This is the tale of brave Doctor Pettenkofer.

  Some decades after Snow, the theory that diseases like cholera are caused by microorganisms-the "germ theory of disease"-was developed in detail by Robert Koch and Louis Pasteur. Koch isolated the bacteria responsible for cholera quite early on. Pettenkofer, however, was unconvinced. To prove Koch wrong, he drank a glass of water mixed with the alleged cholera germs. Pettenkofer suffered no ill effects, and he wrote to Koch saying he had disproved Koch's theory.

  It is thought that Pettenkofer might have had high stomach acid, which can protect people against cholera infection. Or perhaps the cholera germs had died in that sample. Clearly Pettenkofer was lucky; Koch was right about what causes cholera. But the case reminds us that direct empirical tests are no guarantee of success.

  Some readers, I said, might be thinking that empiricism is true but too obvious to be interesting. Another line of criticism holds that empiricism is false, because it is committed to an absurdly simple picture of thought, belief, and justification. The empiricist slogan I gave earlier suggests that experiences pour into the mind and somehow turn into knowledge. It turns out to be very difficult to refine basic empiricist ideas in a way that makes them more psychologically realistic. Empiricists do not deny that reasoning, including very elaborate reasoning, is needed to make sense of what we observe. Still, they insist that the role of experience is somehow fundamental in understanding how we learn about the world. Many critics of empiricism hold that this is a mistake; they see it as a hangover from a simplistic and outdated picture of how belief and reasoning work. That debate will be a recurring theme in this book.

  I now turn to the second of the three families of views about how science works. This view can be introduced with a quote from Galileo, one of the superheroes of the Scientific Revolution:

  Philosophy is written in this grand book the universe, which stands continually open to our gaze. But the book cannot be understood unless one first learns to comprehend the language and to read the alphabet in which it is composed. It is written in the language of mathematics, and its characters are triangles, circles, and other geometric figures without which it is humanly impossible to understand a single word of it; without
these, one wanders about in a dark labyrinth. (Galileo [16231 1990, 237-38, emphasis added)

  Putting the point in plainer language, here is the second of the three ideas.

  Mathematics and Science: What makes science different from other kinds of investigation, and especially successful, is its attempt to understand the natural world using mathematical tools.

  Is this idea an alternative to the empiricist approach, or something that can be combined with it? Perhaps surprisingly, an emphasis on mathematical methods has often been used to argue against empiricism. Sometimes this has been because people have thought that mathematics shows us that there must be another route to knowledge beside experience; experience is a source of knowledge, but not the only important source. Alternatively, we might claim that empiricism is trivial: of course knowledge is based on experience, but that tells us nothing about what differentiates science from other human thought. What makes science special is its attempt to quantify phenomena and detect mathematical patterns in the flow of events.

  Nonetheless, it is surely sensible to see an emphasis on mathematics as something that can be combined with empiricist ideas. It might seem that Galileo would disagree; Galileo not only exalted mathematics but praised his predecessor Copernicus for making "reason conquer sense [experience]" in his belief that the earth goes around the sun. But this is a false opposition. In suggesting that the earth goes round the sun, Copernicus was not ignoring experience but dealing with apparent conflicts between different aspects of experience, in the light of his background beliefs. And there is no question that Galileo was a very empirically minded person; an emphasis on observations made using the telescope was central to his work, for example. So avoiding the false oppositions, we might argue that mathematics used as a tool within an empiricist outlook is what makes science special.

 

‹ Prev