Einstein's Genius Club

Home > Other > Einstein's Genius Club > Page 21
Einstein's Genius Club Page 21

by Feldman, Burton, Williams, Katherine


  One scientist can be trumped very quickly by a new advance—consider Schrödinger, who thought his wave equation of 1926 had rid physics of the plague of quantum mechanics, only to find he had been co-opted within a year. Newton was dead two centuries before his theory was supplanted. Some discoveries are tied not to an individual, but to a team, or are a mosaic of findings, supplanted bit by bit. Older scientists begin to harvest the limitations science set on them when they entered the fray, as if a custodianship.

  Every advance costs an earlier achievement's demotion or displacement. Einstein revered Galileo, Newton, Maxwell, Lorentz, and Planck even as his findings dislodged each of them. He turned Newtonian gravitation into a special case of general relativity; used the Maxwellian field concept to supplant Newtonian mechanics; used Maxwell to radically revise older views of space and time, including Maxwell's own; routed the ether principle, which Lorentz clung to; transformed Planck's quantum concept from a “black body” concept into the vast new subject of quantum theory. (The reader can choose other verbs.) If he had succeeded as hoped with unification, the list would be much longer, beginning with a fundamental revision of what electromagnetism and quantum theory mean.

  As the cutting edge advances, those once in the forefront of research are left behind. This can scarcely be lamented, since science would otherwise not keep advancing. Even a Newton or an Einstein will be dislodged. Homer, Bach, Botticelli—never. Science in this sense is one of the strangest human enterprises, imposing a limitation known nowhere else in thought or art.

  None of this was lost on Einstein. His sharp and humorous sense of how he came to be regarded as a “petrified object” was part of his realism about what would happen to his—and everyone else's—place in science. If physics cannot be based on the field concept, he wrote to his old friend Besso in 1954, then “nothing remains of my entire castle in the air, gravitation theory included, [and of] the rest of modern physics.”1 Even if the field theory holds, it will be modified.

  There are countless studies of genius and creativity, but the decline of great scientists is a largely uncharted subject. Some preliminary sifting is needed. If one asks why Einstein ceased being the Einstein who revolutionized physics, a few explanations have become familiar. First and expectedly, his gifts are said to have faded as he grew older. As this happened, the young man's strengths became the older man's handicaps. In the Swiss patent office and in Berlin, he was a loner, unusually stubborn, fiercely independent, self-isolated—all this was an instinctual wisdom about how to protect and fulfill his great gifts. But later, the stubbornness hardened into an obstinate clinging to fixed ideas; the self-isolation ignored new findings that could challenge his preconceptions; he became inflexible as his younger self never was. In this view, too, he was the victim of his own early success. General relativity—that single-handed triumph against all odds and cautious advice—made him overconfident that the same method could handle the new problem. His triumphant experience “seared” him, said Abraham Pais, a colleague of Einstein at Princeton. It kept him persisting, decade after decade, despite setbacks that should have warned him off.

  Yet one may wonder. A quite different picture of the older Einstein also exists. Mathematical ability proverbially weakens early, but the aging Einstein kept his prowess. Peter G. Bergmann, one of his younger mathematical assistants in the 1930s, recalled:

  [What] impressed me—and remember that I was very young and Einstein in his fifties—was his tremendous creativeness… his sheer inventiveness of new approaches, of new mathematical tricks.2

  Mathematics is not, however, the indispensable gift for a theoretical physicist—rather, physical intuition: the inner sense, judgment, hunch, perceptive inspiration, or however one names the inner gyroscopic instinct insisting that Nature supports this idea but not that one—and, of course, turns out to be right. In 1918, when (as noted earlier) Einstein rejected Hermann Weyl's unifying of gravity and electromagnetism as not corresponding to reality, Weyl made a telling remark: “The criticism,” he replied to Einstein, “very much disturbs me, of course, since experience has shown that one can rely on your intuition.”3 Everyone thought the same, and rightly so: Everything Einstein had done since the age of twenty-six demonstrated it. It is why he could often proceed without benefit of laboratory experiments, using only his “thought experiments.”

  Did this supreme gift desert him in his later years? The American relativist John Wheeler of Princeton, who knew Einstein well from the 1930s, emphatically thinks not. In 1954, Wheeler hypothesized a “geon”—“a gravitating body made entirely of electromagnetic fields”—and sent his paper to Einstein for comment. Einstein, then seventy-five, thought about it awhile and said he doubted that a geon was stable; it took the much younger Wheeler several years to realize that Einstein was right.4 Einstein's intuition, Wheeler said, was as “amazing” as always.

  But even if all Einstein's powers did flag suddenly and disastrously, this explanation is still too limited. The outcome of any scientific career depends as much on what others accomplish: New discoveries can throw logs across the path, raise perplexities, find powerful new explanations. Einstein hugely admired Lorentz, and Lorentz was hardly bereft of his great powers in 1905, mainly because the young Einstein dismissed the ether to which Lorentz was so committed. Einstein revered Newton even more, but he wrote:

  Newton, forgive me: you found the only way which in your age was just about possible for a man with the highest powers of thought and creativity. The concepts which you created are guiding our thinking in physics even today, although we now know they will have to be replaced by others farther removed from the sphere of immediate experience, if we aim at a profounder understanding of relationships.5

  What Newton did, what Einstein did after him, was possible only because science is a collective and cumulative enterprise.

  The eighteenth-century poet Alexander Pope proclaimed: “God said, Let Newton be! and all was light.” Newton preferred a more sober view. In 1675, he wrote to Hooke:

  You defer too much to my ability in searching into this subject. What Descartes did was a good step. You have added much…. If I have seen further it is by standing on the shoulders of giants.6

  Science, said Robert Oppenheimer, is cumulative in “a quite special sense.” Its findings are defined in terms of the objects and laws and ideas that were the science of its predecessors. What Galileo or Faraday did is, for working physicists, not history to be learned, but tools to be used: the physicist's very language, subject, definitions, rules, instruments, and foundations.

  Einstein used these tools freely in search of his quest for unity. Still, he never believed that Nature can be made to yield her secrets given enough brute force (say, accelerators) and ingenuity. Einstein spoke instead, in a Goethean vein, of the “implacable smile of Nature,” at once benign and mocking towards human efforts to fathom her mysteries. It may be that these efforts will always fall short, since Nature stands beyond. To those with eyes to see, the implacable smile foretells ultimate failure; any lifting of the veil is triumph enough. The smile, however, also bespeaks a benign posture, evidenced in what Einstein said was the ultimate mystery: that the universe is intelligible, and we can partake of that knowledge—and of that nobility. As he once said, “Nature conceals her secret through her essential nobility, not out of cunning.”7

  For Einstein, the defeat that science visits on its practitioners seemed as impersonal as the order of the universe. Most scientists probably agree, in principle. But the daily life of science is simply not geared to Einstein's exalted attitude. Intense competitiveness spurs the scientist to produce that extra surge of energy, labor, and intense concentration needed. It can spill over into unseemly scuffles for fame and prizes. Few work on the rarefied mountain-tops of theory as Einstein did, commanding the grand view—the field is parceled instead into specialties and subspecialties, with teams of researchers instead of the lonely pioneer. By 1929, Dirac had made one extraordinary di
scovery after another; that year, he nonetheless wrote to Niels Bohr that quantum mechanics “will ultimately be replaced by something better, (and this applies to all physical theories).”8

  The pathos of science does not always abide in the future. Often it doesn't wait, but invades the present as pressure, anxiety, doubt, or envy. Rivals may snatch away priority; someone else's research can devastatingly derail years of effort; or the supplanting future can appear in the here and now in the shape of an Einstein or Feynman, discouragingly quick, fertile, original; or invincibly sure-handed like Fermi or Rutherford. When the young Pauli and Heisenberg became Max Born's assistants at Göttingen, the older Born had such a presentiment. He said he couldn't match their genius.

  If science is present-oriented, it also requires sustenance. It is vulnerable to the demands of its benefactors, whether the emergent German state on the cusp of World War I or the triumphant postnuclear United States.

  Finally, the pathos can be shattering. Paul Ehrenfest, Einstein's beloved friend, committed suicide because he felt unable to keep up with the flood of new data and conundrums. His sense of being supplanted knotted unbearably and was—said Einstein—why he killed himself.

  Einstein was also supplanted, but he was not shattered. In his old age, he became the ever more kindly, grandfatherly figure. He never considered his failing quest to be a tragedy. If many of his colleagues did, it was because he rejected quantum mechanics, the most vital new branch of physics. His last thirty years provoked steady and often unbridled opposition from cherished friends. Shortly before he died, Einstein wrote to Niels Bohr about banning nuclear weapons, but he couldn't resist teasing his old friend: “Don't frown like that,” Einstein's letter began, “this is not about quantum mechanics.” Einstein must have known that his personal quest for a unified theory had failed. In the end, belief trumped established science and yet left room for humor.

  David Lindley, in his critical study The End of Physics, suggests that we have reached the end of what can be verified:

  What restrains the theorist from becoming wholly carried away by the attractions of some mathematical theory is the need to make predictions with it and to test them against the hard realities of the real world. But as, during this century, experiments in fundamental physics have become harder to do, more costly, and more consuming of time and manpower, this restraining empirical influence has been weakened.

  Lindley believes that Einstein's general theory of relativity inaugurated a tendency to view “experimental verification [as] something of an afterthought.”9 Even its most fervent proponents acknowledge that superstring, the most encompassing of the string theories, is nearly impossible to test, even indirectly.10 The same was said of early atomic theories; but by the time Russell visited Einstein and his friends in 1943, experiment was catching up to quantum physics. Einstein and Russell would spend the rest of their lives trying to wrest the atom from the industries of war.

  What did the four great men speak of when they met at 112 Mercer Street? We will never know, of course. But speculation as to the topics is quite possible. They probably spoke little of the war: As Russell said, they were all in accord politically. Russell and Einstein disagreed over German war reparations, Einstein unable to forgive his former homeland. The doings of Los Alamos were sufficiently shrouded to have afforded little meat, although Pauli and Einstein were aware of the goings-on. Einstein and Pauli had just collaborated on a paper that touched on unified field theory and, despite their differences over quantum mechanics, found common ground—even suggesting, according to Pauli's biographer Charles Enz, an idea strikingly similar to the strings of string theory.11 Gödel was writing his critique of Russell's mathematical logic for the Living Philosophers volume, but it is unlikely, given Gödel's taciturn nature and Russell's distance from his early work, that much was said of it.

  Russell, however, may have listened attentively and probed deeply. His Human Knowledge was in the planning stages; its subject, the nature of scientific knowledge. In it, Russell would begin modestly and conclude even more modestly. “To discover the minimum principles required to justify scientific inferences is one of the main purposes of this book,” he wrote in the Introduction. Having attempted to do so, he concludes, “[A]ll human knowledge is uncertain, inexact, and partial. To this doctrine we have not found any limitation whatever.”

  BIBLIOGRAPHY

  Achinstein, Peter, and Stephen F. Barker, eds. The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in Philosophy of Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1969.

  Aczel, Amir D. God's Equation: Einstein, Relativity and the Expanding Universe. New York: Four Walls Eight Windows, 1999.

  Aichelburg, Peter C., and Roman U. Sexl, eds. Albert Einstein: His Influence on Physics, Philosophy and Politics. Braunschweig, Wiesbaden: Vieweg, 1979.

  Alonso, Marcelo, and Edward J. Finn. Physics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1970.

  Asimov, Isaac. Understanding Physics. 3 vols. New York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1993.

  Atmanspacher, Harald, and Hans Prinas. “Pauli's Ideas on Mind and Matter in the Context of Contemporary Science.” The Journal of Consciousness Studies. 13, 3, 5–50, 2006.

  Ayer, A. J. Russell and Moore: The Analytical Heritage. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.

  Barnett, Lincoln. The Universe and Dr. Einstein. New York: New American Library, 1952.

  Barrett, William, and Henry D. Aiken, eds. Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, vol. 2, The Rise of the British Tradition and Contemporary Analytic Philosophy. New York: Random House, 1962.

  Bergmann, Peter G. The Riddle of Gravitation. Revised and updated. Mineola, NY: Dover, 1992.

  Berlin, Isaiah. Concepts and Categories: Philosophical Essays. New York: Viking, 1979.

  Bernstein, Jeremy. Albert Einstein and the Frontiers of Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.

  ———, annotator. Hitler's Uranium Club: The Secret Recordings at Farm Hall. New York: Springer-Verlag, 2001.

  Blanshard, Brand. Reason and Analysis. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1964.

  Bodanis, David. E=mc2: A Biography of the World's Most Famous Equation. New York: Berkley, 2000.

  Bondi, Hermann. Relativity and Common Sense: A New Approach to Einstein. Mineola, NY: Dover, 1980.

  Born, Max, and Albert Einstein. The Born-Einstein Letters. Trans. Irene Born. New York: Macmillan, 2005.

  Brian, Denis. Einstein: A Life. New York: John Wiley, 1996.

  ———. The Unexpected Einstein: The Real Man Behind the Icon. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley, 2005.

  Brod, Max. The Redemption of Tycho Brahe. Trans. Felix Warren Cross. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1928.

  Bucky, Peter A. The Private Albert Einstein. Kansas City: Andrews and McMeel, 1992.

  Bunch, Bryan. Mathematical Fallacies and Paradoxes. New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold, 1982.

  Butcher, Sandra Ionno. “The Origins of the Russell-Einstein Manifesto.” Pugwash History Series, no. 1, May 2005.

  Bynum, W. F., E. J. Browne, and Roy Porter, eds. Dictionary of the History of Science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.

  Calaprice, Alice. The Einstein Almanac. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2005.

  Calder, Nigel. Einstein's Universe: A Guide to the Theory of Relativity. New York: Penguin, 1990.

  Card, Charles R. “The Emergence of Archetypes in Present-Day Science and Its Significance for a Contemporary Philosophy of Nature.” Dynamical Psychology, 1996.

  Cassidy, David. Einstein and Our World. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2004.

  ———. Uncertainty: The Life and Science of Werner Heisenberg. New York: W. H. Freeman, 1992.

  Casti, John L., and Werner DePauli. Gödel: A Life of Logic. Cambridge, MA: Perseus, 2000.

  Chandrasekhar, S. Truth and Beauty: Aesthetics and Motivations in Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.

  Chodorow, Joan. “Inner-Directed Movement in Analysis: Early Beginnings.” Inside Pages: The Jung So
ciety of Seattle, Spring 2005.

  Clark, Ronald. Einstein: The Life and Times. New York: Harper & Row, 1984.

  Concise Science Dictionary. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.

  Cook, Alistair. Six Men. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977.

  Crawshay-Williams, Rupert. Russell Remembered. London: Oxford University Press, 1970.

  Crease, Robert P., and Charles C. Mann. The Second Creation: Makers of the Revolution in Twentieth-Century Physics. New York: Macmillan, 1987.

  Davies, Paul. Superforce: The Search for a Grand Unified Theory of Nature. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1984.

  Dawson, John W., Jr., Logical Dilemmas: The Life and Work of Kurt Gödel. Wellesley, MA: A. K. Peters, 1997.

  Dukas, Helen, and Banesh Hoffmann, eds. Albert Einstein: The Human Side. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986.

  Eames, Elizabeth R. Bertrand Russell's Dialogue with His Contemporaries. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1989.

  Edmonds, David, and John Eidinow. Wittgenstein's Poker: The Story of a Ten-Minute Argument Between Two Great Philosophers. New York: HarperCollins, 2001.

  Einstein, Albert. Autobiographical Notes. Trans. and ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1992.

  ———. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Multiple volumes. Ed. John J. Stachel et al. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1987–.

  ———. “Concerning an Heuristic Point of View Toward the Emission and Transformation of Light.” Annalen der Physik. 17, 132, 1905. Translation into English, American Journal of Physics, vol. 33, no. 5, May 1965.

  ———. Dear Professor Einstein: Albert Einstein's Letters to and from Children. Ed. Alice Calaprice. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2002.

  ———. Einstein on Peace. Ed. Otto Nathan and Heinz Norden. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1960.

 

‹ Prev